Can Axioms Prove Falsity in Formal Axiomatic Theories?

  • Thread starter roygabv
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Axioms
In summary: This statement is saying that an axiomatic base that is based on false premises cannot prove anything.
  • #1
roygabv
1
0
Hello.

I am working on a paper detailing Godel's Incompleteness Theorm and I came across this statement.

"An axiomatic base where all the axioms are true cannot prove anything to be false."

Is this correct?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
What's an axiomatic base?
 
  • #3
From my interpretation of the sentence, I'd say an "axiomatic base" is the foundation in which a axiom is made up. Basically, an idea founded entirely from axioms cannot prove falsity.

I think the sentence leaves one open to broad interpretations, but I would agree with the statement.
 
  • #4
roygabv said:
"An axiomatic base where all the axioms are true cannot prove anything to be false."
Is this correct?

I'm assuming by axiomatic base they mean those axioms which a system needs and no more :confused:. The irreducibles, I suppose. But, in ANY system, any that I'm aware of any ways, the axioms are taken to be self-evident truths. We speak of axiomatic set-theory, and we hold that its axioms are both self-evidently true and not reducible to any combination of the other axioms. And yet, we prove statements to be either true or false using the rules of logic and these suppositions. Or, I suppose, they are found to be either consistent or inconsistent within our system. But we generally take inconsistency to be falsity, at least within the system. It seems to me that this statement should read "An axiomatic base where the axioms are false cannot prove the truth of a statement." I'm a bit confused, though, and may be entirely wrong. Still...
 
  • #5
You know what? Forget what I said earlier. Following from false pretenses allows one to prove all things, which is really of no use in mathematics. Perhaps better yet, "An axiomatic base where the axioms are false allows for inconsistencies." It still seems to me that rogabv's statement cannot be true.
 
  • #6
It depends on how you set up the axiom system S. Say you start with a set of symbols, then string symbols together to get a set of expressions, then pick out some special expressions to get a set of formulas. Then you pick out some special formulas to get a set of axioms. Then you add rules of inference. A rule of inference (rule, for short) states that some formula (conclusion) can be inferred from a set of formulas (hypotheses). A rule is finite if it has finitely many hypotheses. Then define theorems as follows:
i) The axioms of S are theorems of S;
ii) If all hypotheses of a rule of S are theorems of S, then the rule’s conclusion is a theorem of S.
Then define a proof in S as follows:
If all rules in S are finite, a proof in S is a finite sequence of formulas, each of which is either an axiom or the conclusion of a rule whose hypotheses precede the formula in the proof.
If L is the last formula in proof P, then we say P is a proof of L.
Thus L is a theorem of S iff there is a proof of L in S. (An axiom is a proof of itself.)
You can then add two distinct objects, “T” and “F”, called truth-values. These objects just have to be distinct, but we can let them mean "truth" and "falsehood". T and F are assigned to formulas. Say we've designed our inference rules so that if T is assigned to all hypotheses of rule, then T is also assigned to the conclusion of the rule. Assign T to all axioms. Then T is assigned to all theorems of S. Recall that L is a theorem of S iff there is a proof of L in S. So no proof of L in S results in F being assigned to L. IOW, we can't prove any formula is false. Well, I skipped over a lot of things, but I think that works.
 
  • #7
honestrosewater said:
If L is the last formula in proof P, then we say P is a proof of L.
Thus L is a theorem of S iff there is a proof of L in S. (An axiom is a proof of itself.)
You can then add two distinct objects, “T” and “F”, called truth-values. These objects just have to be distinct, but we can let them mean "truth" and "falsehood". T and F are assigned to formulas. Say we've designed our inference rules so that if T is assigned to all hypotheses of rule, then T is also assigned to the conclusion of the rule. Assign T to all axioms. Then T is assigned to all theorems of S. Recall that L is a theorem of S iff there is a proof of L in S. So no proof of L in S results in F being assigned to L. IOW, we can't prove any formula is false.
I think I follow what you are trying to state here. But, more to the point, it seems to me that no value of F would ever be assigned to an L. By your definition, L would be arrived at, in a purely mechanistic fashion, from axioms assigned T, by accepted inference rules. L would only be arrived at in the case that L is T. It is not that we may say the assertion L is F. We may not make the assertion L at all, unless of course L is T. Only L which are T may be stated, no others would occur, not in this fashion. I agree with your point here, at least in reference to roygabv's assertion.
honestrosewater said:
It depends on how you set up the axiom system S. Say you start with a set of symbols, then string symbols together to get a set of expressions, then pick out some special expressions to get a set of formulas. Then you pick out some special formulas to get a set of axioms. Then you add rules of inference. A rule of inference (rule, for short) states that some formula (conclusion) can be inferred from a set of formulas (hypotheses). A rule is finite if it has finitely many hypotheses. Then define theorems as follows:
i) The axioms of S are theorems of S;
ii) If all hypotheses of a rule of S are theorems of S, then the rule’s conclusion is a theorem of S.
It is here that I disagree. That a theorem may follow from another theorem by a rule, I take as a true statement. That an axiom may follow from an application of a rule on a set of expressions or formulas, I do not. As a rule, an axiom is an irreducible, an underivable assertion. Though you may not call a primitive expression an axiom, it is still nonetheless. Your axioms then, as defined in your statement, would really more aptly be called theorems, as they follow from the application of some set of procedures on these primitives. If, by chance, you are referring to metastatements, as preceding statements, then I think we must treat the metacase as a different case. If I missed your point, or misinterpreted you in any way, let me know.
:smile:
 
  • #8
inquire4more said:
I think I follow what you are trying to state here. But, more to the point, it seems to me that no value of F would ever be assigned to an L. By your definition, L would be arrived at, in a purely mechanistic fashion, from axioms assigned T, by accepted inference rules. L would only be arrived at in the case that L is T. It is not that we may say the assertion L is F. We may not make the assertion L at all, unless of course L is T. Only L which are T may be stated, no others would occur, not in this fashion. I agree with your point here, at least in reference to roygabv's assertion.
Right, because S has been set up precisely so that we can't prove any formula unless it's true- it has been set up to be sound (and complete BTW). There certainly are false formulas; The negation of each theorem in S, by the axioms and rules of S, are false- we just can't derive them in S. With different axioms or rules, we could derive false formulas, as you noted about inconsistent axiom systems.
It is here that I disagree. That a theorem may follow from another theorem by a rule, I take as a true statement.
Good because you couldn't disagree with that- it's how theorems were defined. :-p
That an axiom may follow from an application of a rule on a set of expressions or formulas, I do not.
We have to build up a language before we can even state an axiom. That's what the symbols, expressions, and formulas are for- they tell us how the language works and allow us to actually say things in the language. We may create a rule- not an inference rule though, those are different- that decides which formulas are axioms, or we can just state each of them (if there are finitely many, of course). What I outlined above is the usual way of building axiom systems. Well, it's the syntactic side of axiom systems, dealing with the formal aspects, symbols, and such; There's also a semantic side, dealing with concepts, meaning and such, but I'll get to that.
As a rule, an axiom is an irreducible, an underivable assertion.
From your experience, axioms may be what you say. But as defined in this system, axioms are formulas. They really have to be- you can't state them otherwise. And axioms don't have to be irreducible. Here are a few examples of axiom schemas of axiom systems for propositional logic- don't worry if you don't understand them- a B alone is a formula, as are ~B and (B -> C), so these are certainly reducible:
A1) (B -> (C -> B))
A2) ((B -> (C -> D)) -> ((B -> C) -> (B -> D)))
A3) (((~C) -> (~B)) -> (((~C) -> B) -> C))
__
B1) B v B -> B
B2) B -> B v C
B3) B v C -> C v B
B4) (C -> D) -> (B v C -> B v D)
__
C1) B -> (B & B)
C2) B & C -> B
C3) (B -> C) -> (~(C & D) -> ~(D & B))
__
D1) [(((B -> C) -> (~D -> ~E)) -> D) -> F] -> [(F -> B) -> (E -> B)]
-taken from Mendelson's "Intro to Mathematical Logic", 4th. Notice they also use different symbols; That's part of the language. :)
On the semantic, conceptual side of axiom systems, you may want your axioms to be as simple as possible, but it isn't necessary. Simpler axioms may make the rest of your work easier. You may also want other people to understand what you're talking about without having to explain a lot or for people to accept that your axioms are true "outside" of the system. But none of these are necessary. You only need to consider your choice of axioms if you want your axiom system to behave in a certain way, and even then, you may have several axiom sets that do the job equally well, as is the case above.
Though you may not call a primitive expression an axiom, it is still nonetheless. Your axioms then, as defined in your statement, would really more aptly be called theorems,
Ah, but axioms are theorems- though a special kind of theorem, granted. ;)
as they follow from the application of some set of procedures on these primitives. If, by chance, you are referring to metastatements, as preceding statements, then I think we must treat the metacase as a different case. If I missed your point, or misinterpreted you in any way, let me know.
:smile:
You would be right if they were metastatements, but they aren't. We wouldn't have to build the language then; We could just start talking about axioms right away. :smile:
Oh, BTW, you actually use some of the properties of expressions and formulas to prove things about not in the axiom system. For instance, you may use the length of a formula (the number of symbols in it) to prove something about the system. So you don't just use them at the beginning and forget them.
 
Last edited:
  • #9
inquire4more said:
Following from false pretenses
Premises?

.
 
  • #10
honestrosewater said:
You would be right if they were metastatements, but they aren't. We wouldn't have to build the language then; We could just start talking about axioms right away.
Oh, BTW, you actually use some of the properties of expressions and formulas to prove things about not in the axiom system. For instance, you may use the length of a formula (the number of symbols in it) to prove something about the system. So you don't just use them at the beginning and forget them.
I've been busy the last two days but I've had a minute or two to look at your statement. First, your axiom systems seem to me to be roughly, or perhaps exactly, equivalent. I understand your point here. Still, I need to see the actual method of their construction before I decide for myself whether or not axioms may follow, as well as precede, and I do not count equivalent statements, or restatements, as developments of separate axioms. Can you point me to where I might find these constructions? And you're saying these constructions are done in the system, without use of some meta-system?
 
  • #11
inquire4more said:
I've been busy the last two days but I've had a minute or two to look at your statement. First, your axiom systems seem to me to be roughly, or perhaps exactly, equivalent.
I take it you mean the specific axiom sets I listed. This is bordering on my comfort zone; I'll try to be careful, but take this with a grain of salt. The axiom sets are similar in that they are all axiom sets of a formal axiomatic theory for the propositional calculus. (You may already know there are different axiomatizations for set theory, but they are all still recognized as axiomatizations for set theory. Same general idea.)
Some things those axiomatizations for propositional calculus have in common: a finite set of connective symbols, a countably infinite set of propositional symbols, an effective procedure for determining formulas, a finite set of axiom schemas, and a finite set of inference rules (all sets are non-empty). It's the specific symbols, axioms, etc. in which they may differ.
I'm not sure how equivalency would apply to axiom sets, sorry. The first axiom set I listed is part of a sound, complete axiomatic theory for propositional calculus. I presume the others are also.
I understand your point here. Still, I need to see the actual method of their construction before I decide for myself whether or not axioms may follow, as well as precede, and I do not count equivalent statements, or restatements, as developments of separate axioms. Can you point me to where I might find these constructions?
Sure. The examples I gave were from Mendelson's "Introduction to Mathematical Logic", 4th ed. You can find this info in just about any other mathematical logic book or site; Two books I like are Shoenfield's "Mathematical Logic" and Machover's "Set theory, logic and their limitations" (though IIRC Shoenfield skips this for propositional logic and goes straight into first-order logic).
By all means, try those if that's what you want, but you don't really need them. I've pretty much told you how the axioms are constructed, beginning with sets of symbols. If you want more details, I can handle that. If you want to know how an author goes about choosing axioms or how propositional logic developed historically, those books aren't the place to look. Try this article. If you're really interested, you could check out Boole's "Laws of Thought".
And you're saying these constructions are done in the system, without use of some meta-system?
(As you'll see if you read those books, especially Machover) The line is clearly drawn between the metalanguage (English, for me) and what's called the object language. Of course, the metalanguage is used to describe the object language, and the symbols we use in the metalanguage only denote the actual symbols of the object language- which may not even have a written form. But, yes, the object language is completely separate from the metalanguage, and the object language is built from scratch.
 

FAQ: Can Axioms Prove Falsity in Formal Axiomatic Theories?

What is an axiom?

An axiom is a statement or proposition that is assumed to be true without needing to be proven. It serves as a starting point for logical reasoning and building mathematical or scientific theories.

How do axioms relate to the concept of proof?

Axioms cannot be proven because they are accepted as true without needing evidence or justification. However, they are used as the basis for proving other statements or theorems. If an axiom is proven to be false, it can no longer be used as a starting point for logical reasoning.

Why can't axioms prove falsity?

Axioms are by definition assumed to be true, and therefore cannot be used to prove something false. In order for a statement to be proven false, it must be shown to be logically inconsistent or contradictory, which cannot be done with an axiom.

Can axioms ever be changed or modified?

Yes, axioms can be revised or replaced, but this is a rare occurrence and only happens when there is a need to redefine the foundation of a theory or system. This is typically done when a contradiction or inconsistency is found within the existing axioms.

How are axioms developed and chosen?

Axioms are typically developed through observation, experimentation, and logical reasoning. They are chosen based on their simplicity, consistency, and ability to support a broad range of theories and systems. Axioms should also be intuitive and widely accepted by the scientific community.

Similar threads

Back
Top