This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics (Week 249)

In summary, John Baez's "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics" column discussed the Erlangen program, which was a plan created by Felix Klein to reduce different forms of geometry to group theory. Klein's lecture outlining this program was originally not given as his inaugural speech at Erlangen, but it is now available online thanks to a recent HTML version by Johan Ernst Mebius. Klein's lecture has also been translated into English by M. W. Haskell and can be found on the University of California, Riverside website. The Erlangen program can be understood in the modern language of groupoids, which are a way to think about symmetries. Klein's program relates to the traditional approach of using a group acting transitively on a
  • #1
John Baez
Also available as http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/week249.html

April 8, 2007
This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics (Week 249)
John BaezAs you may recall, I'm telling a long story about symmetry, geometry,
and algebra. Some of this tale is new work done by James Dolan, Todd
Trimble and myself. But a lot of it is old work by famous people which
deserves a modern explanation.

A great example is Felix Klein's "Erlangen program" - a plan for
reducing many sorts of geometry to group theory. Many people tip
their hat to the Erlanger program, but few seem to deeply understand
it, and even fewer seem to have read what Klein actually wrote about it!

The problem goes back a long ways. In 1871, while at Goettingen,
Klein worked on non-Euclidean geometry, and showed that hyperbolic
geometry was consistent if and only if Euclidean geometry was.
In the process, he must have thought hard about the role of symmetry
groups in geometry. When he was appointed professor at Erlangen
in 1872, he wrote a lecture outlining his "Erlanger Programm" for
reducing geometry to group theory.

But, he didn't actually give this lecture as his inaugural speech!
He spoke about something else.

So, nobody ever heard him announce the Erlangen program. And, until
recently, the lecture he wrote was a bit hard to find. Luckily, now
you can get it online:

1) Felix Klein, Vergleichende Betrachtungen ueber neuere geometrische
Forsuchungen, Verlag von Andreas Deichert, Erlangen, 1872. Also
available at the University of Michigan Historical Mathematics Collection,
http://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/text-idx?c=umhistmath;idno=ABN7632

Even better, Johan Ernst Mebius has recently prepared an HTML version,
with links to the above version:

2) Johan Ernst Mebius, Felix Klein's Erlanger Programm,
http://www.xs4all.nl/~jemebius/ErlangerProgramm.htm

But what if you have the misfortune of only reading English, not
German? Until now the only translation was quite hard to obtain:

3) Felix Klein, A comparative review of recent researches in geometry,
trans. M. W. Haskell, Bull. New York Math. Soc. 2, (1892-1893), 215-249.

In case you're wondering, the "New York Mathematical Society" no longer
exists! It was founded in 1888, but in 1894 it went national and became
the American Mathematical Society.

Luckily, Chris Hillman got ahold of this old journal and scanned it in!
So now, you can read Klein's paper in English here:

4) The Erlangen program, http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/erlangen/

English-speakers can read more about the Erlangen program here:

5) Felix Klein, Elementary Mathematics from an Advanced Standpoint:
Geometry, part 3: Systematic discussion of geometry and its foundations,
Dover, New York, 1939.

Luckily Dover keeps its books in print!

For more on the Erlangen program, try these:

6) Garrett Birkhoff and M. K. Bennett, Felix Klein and his
"Erlanger Programm", in History and Philosophy of Modern Mathematics,
eds. W. Aspray and P. Kitcher, Minnesota Stud. Philos. Sci. XI,
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1988, pp. 145-176.

7) Hans A. Kastrup, The contributions of Emmy Noether, Felix Klein and
Sophus Lie to the modern concept of symmetries in physical systems,
in Symmetries in Physics (1600-1980), ed. M. G. Doncel, World Scientific,
Singapore, 1987, pp. 113-163.

8) I. M. Yaglom, Felix Klein and Sophus Lie: Evolution of the
Idea of Symmetry in the Nineteenth Century, trans. S. Sossinsky,
Birkhauser, Boston, 1988.

For more about Klein, try "week213" and this little biography:

9) MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, Felix Klein,
http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Klein.html

But what does the Erlangen program actually amount to, in the language
of modern mathematics? This will take a while to explain, so the best
thing is to dive right in.

Last week in the Tale of Groupoidification I tried to explain two slogans:

GROUPOIDS ARE LIKE 'SETS WITH SYMMETRIES'

SPANS OF GROUPOIDS ARE LIKE 'INVARIANT WITNESSED RELATIONS'

They're a bit vague; they're mainly designed to give you enough intuition
to follow the next phase of the Tale, which is all about how:

GROUPOIDS GIVE VECTOR SPACES

SPANS OF GROUPOIDS GIVE LINEAR OPERATORS

But before the next phase, I need to say a bit about how groupoids
and spans of groupoids fit into Klein's Erlangen program.

Groupoids are a modern way to think about symmetries. A more
traditional approach would use a group acting as symmetries of
some set. And the most traditional approach of all, going back to
Galois and Klein, uses a group acting *transitively* on a set.

So, let me explain the traditional approach, and then relate it
to the modern one.

I hope you know what it means for a group G to "act" on a set X.
It means that for any element x of X and any guy g in G, we get a
new element gx in X. We demand that

1x = x

and

g(hx) = (gh)x.

More precisely, this is a "left action" of G on X, since we write
the group elements to the left of x. We can also define right actions,
and someday we may need those too.

We say an action of a group G on a set X is "transitive" if given
any two elements of X, there's some guy in G mapping the first
element to the second. In this case, we have an isomorphism of sets

X = G/H

for some subgroup H of G.

For example, suppose we're studying a kind of geometry where the symmetry
group is G. Then X could be the set of figures of some sort: points, or
lines, or something fancier. If G acts transitively on X, then all
figures of this sort "look alike": you can get from anyone to any other
using a symmetry. This is often the case in geometry... but not always.

Suppose G acts transitively on X. Pick any figure x of type X and let
H be its "stabilizer": the subgroup consisting of all guys in G that map
x to itself. Then we get a one-to-one and onto map

f: X -> G/H

sending each figure gx in X to the equivalence class [g] in G/H.

If you haven't seen this fact before, you should definitely prove it -
it's one of the big ways people use symmetry!

Here's one kind of thing people do with this fact. The 3d rotation
group G = SO(3) acts on the sphere X = S^2, and the stabilizer of
the north pole is the 2d rotation group H = SO(2), so the sphere is
isomorphic to G/H = SO(3)/SO(2). The same sort of result holds in any
dimension, and we can use it to derive facts about spheres from facts
about rotation groups, and vice versa.

A grander use of this fact is to set up a correspondence between
sets on which G acts transitively and subgroups of G. This is
one of the principles lurking behind Galois theory.

Galois applied this principle to number theory - see "week201" for
details. But, it really has nothing particular to do with number theory!
In his Erlangen program, Klein applied it to geometry.

Klein's goal was to systematize a bunch of different kinds of non-Euclidean
geometry. Each kind of geometry he was interested in had a different
group of symmetries. For example:

n-dimensional spherical geometry has the rotation group SO(n+1) as
symmetries. (Or, if you want to include reflections, the bigger
group O(n+1).)

n-dimensional Euclidean geometry has the Euclidean group ISO(n) as
symmetries. (This group is built from rotations in SO(n) together
with translations in R^n.)

n-dimensional hyperbolic geometry has the group SO(n,1) as symmetries.
(This group also shows up in special relativity under the name of
the "Lorentz group": it acts on the "mass hyperboloid", and that's how
hyperbolic geometry shows up in special relativity.)

n-dimensional projective geometry has the group SL(n+1) as symmetries.
(This group consists of nxn matrices with determinant 1. Scalar multiples
of the identity act trivially on projective space, so you can mod out by
those and use the "projective special linear group" PSL(n+1).)

The details here don't matter much yet; the point is that there are lots
of interesting kinds of geometry, with interesting symmetry groups!

Klein realized that in any kind of geometry like this, a "figure"
corresponds to a subgroup of G: namely the stabilizer group H of
this figure. Here a "figure" could be a point, a line, a plane,
or something much fancier. Regardless of the details, the set
of all figures of the same type is G/H, and G acts transitively
on this set.

The really cool part is that we can use Klein's idea to *define* a
geometry for any group G. To do this, we just say that *every* subgroup
H of G stabilizes some figure. So, we work out all the subgroups of G.
Then, we work out all the incidence relations - relations like "a point
lies on a line". To do this, we take two sets of figures, say

X = G/H

and

Y = G/K

and find all the invariant relations between them: that is, subsets of
X x Y preserved all the symmetries. I'll say more about how to do this
next time - we can use something called "double cosets". In nice cases,
like when G is a simple Lie group and H and K are so-called "parabolic"
subgroups, these let us express all the invariant relations in terms of
finitely many "atomic" ones! So, we can really carry out Klein's program
of thoroughly understanding geometry starting from groups - at least in
nice cases.

In short, group actions - especially transitive ones - are a traditional
and very powerful way of using symmetry to tackle lots of problems.

So, to bridge the gap between the traditional and the new, I should
explain how group actions give groupoids. I'll show you that:

A GROUPOID EQUIPPED WITH CERTAIN EXTRA STUFF IS
THE SAME AS A GROUP ACTION

It's not very hard to get a groupoid from a group action. Say we have
a group G acting on a set X. Then the objects of our groupoid are
just elements of X, and a morphism

g: x -> y

is just a group element g with

gx = y.

Composing morphisms works the obvious way - it's basically just
multiplication in the group G.

Some people call this groupoid an "action groupoid". I often call
it the "weak quotient" X//G, since it's like the ordinary quotient
X/G, but instead of declaring that x and y are *equal* when we have
a group element g sending x to y, we instead declare they're
*isomorphic* via a specified isomorphism g: x -> y.

But for now, let's call X//G the "action groupoid".

So, group actions give action groupoids. But, these groupoids come
with extra stuff!

First of all, the action groupoid X//G always comes equipped with a
functor

X//G
|
|p
|
v
G

sending any object of X//G to the one object of G, and any morphism
g: x -> y to the corresponding element of G. Remember, a group is
a groupoid with one object: this is the 21st century!

Second of all, this functor p is always "faithful": given two morphisms
from x to y, if p maps them to the same morphism, then they were equal.

And that's all! Any groupoid with a faithful functor to G is
equivalent to the action groupoid X//G for some action of G on some
set X. This takes a bit of proving... let's not do it now.

So: in my slogan

A GROUPOID EQUIPPED WITH CERTAIN EXTRA STUFF IS
THE SAME AS A GROUP ACTION

the "certain extra stuff" was precisely a faithful functor to G.

What if we have a *transitive* group action? Then something nice
happens.

First of all, saying that G acts transitively on X is the same as
saying there's a morphism between any two objects of X//G. In
other words, all objects of X//G are isomorphic. Or in other words,
there's just one isomorphism class of objects.

Just as a groupoid with one object is a group, a groupoid with one
*isomorphism class* of objects is *equivalent* to a group. Here
I'm using the usual notion of "equivalence" of categories, as
explained back in "week76".

So, G acts transitively on X on precisely when X//G is equivalent
to a group!

And what group? Well, what could it possibly be? It's just the
stabilizer of some element of X! So, in the case of a transitive
group action, our functor

X//G
|
|p
|
v
G

is secretly equivalent to the inclusion

H
|
|i
|
v
G

of the stabilizer group of this element.

So, we see how Klein's old idea of geometrical "figures" as subgroups of G
is being generalized. We can start with any groupoid Y of "figures" and
"symmetries between figures", and play with that. It becomes an action
groupoid if we equip it with a faithful functor to some group G:

Y
|
|
|
v
G

Then the action is transitive if all the objects of Y are isomorphic.
In that case, our functor is equivalent to an inclusion

H
|
|
|
v
G

and we're back down to Klein's approach to geometry. But, it's actually
good to generalize what Klein did, and think about arbitrary "groupoids
over G" - that is, groupoids equipped with functors to G.

So, when we blend our ideas on spans of groupoids with Klein's ideas,
we'll want to use spans of groupoids "over G" - that is, commutative
diamonds of groupoids and functors, like this:

S
/ \
/ \
/ \
/ \
v v
X Y
\ /
\ /
\ /
\ /
v v
G

There's much more to say about this, but not today!

I'll say one last thing before quitting. It's a bit more technical,
but I feel an urge to see it in print.

People often talk about "the" stabilizer group of a transitive action
of some group G on some set X. This is a bit dangerous, since every
element of X has its own stabilizer, and they're not necessarily all equal!

However, they're all *conjugate*: if the stabilizer of x is H,
then the stabilizer of gx is gHg^{-1}.

So, when I say above that

X//G
|
|p
|
v
G

is equivalent to

H
|
|i
|
v
G

I could equally well have said it's equivalent to

H
|
|i'
|
v
G

where the inclusion i' is the inclusion i conjugated by g. If you
know some category theory, you'll see that i and i' are naturally
isomorphic: a natural isomorphism between functors between groups
is just a "conjugation". Picking the specific inclusion i requires
picking a specific element x of X.

Of course, I'll try to write later issues in a way that doesn't force
you to have understood all these nuances!

-----------------------------------------------------------------------
Previous issues of "This Week's Finds" and other expository articles on
mathematics and physics, as well as some of my research papers, can be
obtained at

http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/

For a table of contents of all the issues of This Week's Finds, try

http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/twfcontents.html

A simple jumping-off point to the old issues is available at

http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/twfshort.html

If you just want the latest issue, go to

http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/this.week.html
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Hi John,

Long time no see or hear. I thought I'd add a few comments on the
Erlanger program
which are certain to be ill-informed.

One way I look at the question is this: take a category C and an
object X in it.
Consider natural ways to attach to X a subcategory G(X) of C. One can
ask
when it's possible to recover X from G(X). In Klein's situation, at
least as far as
my ignorant understanding goes, one takes G(X) to be the category
with
one object and automorphism group Aut(X). In this form, the
reconstruction
of X is impossible in most situations. For example, if C consists of
metrized
compact two-manifolds, most of them have trivial automorphism group.
So Klein was thinking of a quite `homogeneous' setting in his notion
of geometry. I guess one can make this rather precise
in the study of homogeneous spaces or hyperbolic manifolds.

But one other interesting case looks at a different
category associated to X, namely Cov(X), the category of covering
spaces. Here, if C is the category of the spectrum of algebraic number
fields, for example,
and Cov(X) is interpreted as etale coverings in the sense of algebraic
geometry,
then it is a theorem of Neukirch and Uchida that you can indeed
recover X
from Cov(X). The same works when you let the X run over the category
of
hyperbolic algebraic curves over number fields. This was part of the
`anabelian program' discussed by Grothendieck in the 80's.
>From this point of view, the anabelian program has quite a bit of

the Erlanger program in it. I should admit, however, that the main
experts in anabelian geometry feel quite luke-warm about this
way of looking at things.

In any case, the X -> G(X) -> X problem could be a not-entirely-
uninteresting question in many other situations.

BTW, I believe (but I' m not sure) the recovery of X from Cov(X) works
also
in the category of hyperbolic manifolds (in the usual sense, no
arithmetic here) of dimension at least three.

One other theorem I know about that doesn't require arithmetic
geometry
to discuss is when C is the category of compact smooth manifolds.
Here let G(X) be the the group of diffeomorhisms of X. Then one can
recover
X from G(X).

I had thought that the `Yoneda Lemma' could be thought of as a trivial
instance
of such recovery in a very general setting, but then realized while
writing this post is that it's not
so simple to formulate it in that way.

I hope things are well.

Minhyong
 

FAQ: This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics (Week 249)

What is "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics (Week 249)"?

"This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics" is a weekly blog series written by mathematician and physicist John Baez. It covers a wide range of topics related to mathematical physics, including current research, interesting problems, and connections between different areas of mathematics and physics.

Who is John Baez?

John Baez is a mathematician and physicist who is a professor at the University of California, Riverside. He is known for his work in category theory, quantum gravity, and mathematical physics. He is also a prolific writer and blogger, and his blog "Azimuth" includes his popular series "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics".

How often is "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics" updated?

The blog series is updated weekly, with a new post published every Friday. Each post covers a specific week, and the numbering system (e.g. "Week 249") corresponds to the number of weeks since the series began in 1993.

Can anyone understand "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics" or is it only for experts?

While some of the topics covered in the blog series may be more advanced and technical, John Baez strives to make the content accessible to a wide audience. Many posts include visual aids and explanations to help readers understand the concepts, and Baez often provides links to further resources for those who want to delve deeper into a particular topic.

How can I stay updated on "This Week's Finds in Mathematical Physics"?

The best way to stay updated on the blog series is to subscribe to the Azimuth blog, where the posts are published. You can also follow John Baez on social media platforms such as Twitter, where he often shares links to his latest posts. Additionally, you can browse the archive of past posts on the Azimuth blog to catch up on any you may have missed.

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
3K
Replies
1
Views
3K
Replies
1
Views
3K
Replies
1
Views
3K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
4
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
994
Replies
1
Views
3K
Back
Top