qm_interpretations

The Fundamental Difference in Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Estimated Read Time: 5 minute(s)
Common Topics: state, quantum, mechanics, interpretations, make

A topic that continually comes up in discussions of quantum mechanics is the existence of many different interpretations. Not only are there different interpretations, but people often get quite emphatic about the one they favor so that discussions of quantum mechanics can easily turn into long arguments. Sometimes this even reaches the point where proponents of a particular interpretation claim that anyone who doesn’t believe it is “idiotic”, or some other extreme term. This seems a bit odd given that all of the interpretations use the same theoretical machinery of quantum mechanics to make predictions, and therefore whatever differences there are between them are not experimentally testable.

In this article, I want to present what I see as a fundamental difference in interpretation that I think is at the heart of many of these disagreements and arguments.

I take no position on whether either of the interpretations I will describe is “right” or “wrong”; my purpose here is not to argue for either one but to try to explain the fundamental beliefs underlying each one to people who hold the other. If people are going to disagree about interpretations of quantum mechanics, which is likely to continue until someone figures out a way of extending quantum mechanics so that the differences in interpretations become experimentally testable, it would be nice if they could at least understand what they are disagreeing about instead of calling each other idiots. This article is an attempt to make some small contribution towards that goal.

The fundamental difference that I see is how to interpret the mathematical object that describes a quantum system. This object has various names: quantum state, state vector, wave function, etc. I will call it the “state” both for brevity and to avoid adopting any specific mathematical framework since they’re all equivalent anyway. The question is, what does the state represent? The two fundamentally different interpretations give two very different answers to this question:

  • (1) The state is only a tool that we use to predict the probabilities of different results for measurements we might choose to make of the system. Changes in the state represent changes in the predicted probabilities; for example, when we make a measurement and obtain a particular result, we update the state to reflect that observed result, so that our predictions of probabilities of future measurements change.
  • (2) The state describes the physically real state of the individual quantum system; the state allows us to predict the probabilities of different results for measurements because it describes something physically real, and measurements do physically real things to it. Changes in the state represent physically real changes in the system; for example, when we make a measurement, the state of the measured system becomes entangled with the state of the measuring device, which is a physically real change in both of them.

(Some people might want to add a third answer: the state describes an ensemble of a large number of similar systems, rather than a single system. For purposes of this discussion, I am considering this to be equivalent to answer #1, because the state does not describe the physically real state of a single system, and the role of the ensemble is simply to enable a frequentist interpretation of the predicted probabilities.)

(Note: Originally, answer #1 above talked about the state as describing our knowledge of the system. However, the word “knowledge” is itself open to various interpretations, and I did not intend to limit answer #1 to just “knowledge interpretations” of quantum mechanics; I intended it to cover all interpretations that do not view the state as directly describing the physically real state of the system.)

The reason there is a fundamental problem with the interpretation of quantum mechanics is that each of the above answers, while it contains parts that seem true, leads us, if we take it to its logical conclusion, to a place that doesn’t make sense. No choice gives us just a set of comfortable, reasonable statements that we can easily accept as true. Picking an interpretation requires you to decide which of the true things seems more compelling which ones you are willing to give up, and/or which of the places that don’t make sense is less unpalatable to you.

  • For #1, the true part is that we can never directly observe the state, and we can never make deterministic predictions about the results of quantum experiments. That makes it seem obvious that the state can’t be the physically real state of the system; if it were, we ought to be able to pin it down and not have to settle for merely probabilistic descriptions. But if we take that idea to its logical conclusion, it implies that quantum mechanics must be an incomplete theory; there ought to be some more complete description of the system that fills in the gaps and allows us to do better than merely probabilistic predictions. And yet nobody has ever found such a more complete description, and all indications from experiments (at least so far) are that no such description exists; the probabilistic predictions that quantum mechanics gives us are the best we can do.
  • For #2, the true part is that interpreting the state as physically real makes quantum mechanics work just like all the other physical theories we’ve discovered, instead of being a unique special case. The theoretical model assigns the system a state that reflects, as best we can in the model, the real physical state of the real system. But if we take this to its logical conclusion, it implies that the real world is nothing like the world that we perceive. We perceive a single classical world, but the state that QM assigns is a quantum superposition of many worlds. We perceive a single definite result for measurements, but the state that QM assigns is a quantum superposition of all possible results, entangled with all possible states of the measuring device, and of our brains, perceiving all the different possible results.

Again, my purpose here is not to pick either one of these and try to argue for it. It is simply to observe that, as I said above, no matter which one you pick, #1 or #2, there are obvious drawbacks to the choice, which might reasonably lead other people to pick the other one instead. Neither choice is “right” or “wrong”; both are just best guesses, based on, as I said above, which particular tradeoff one chooses to make between the true parts and the unpalatable parts. We have no way of resolving any of this by experiment, so we simply have to accept that both viewpoints can reasonably coexist at the present state of our knowledge.

I realize that pointing all this out is not going to stop all arguments about interpretations of quantum mechanics. I would simply suggest that, if you find yourself in such an argument, you take a moment to step back and reflect on the above and realize that the argument has no “right” or “wrong” outcome and that the best we can do at this point is to accept that reasonable people can disagree on quantum mechanics interpretations and leave it at that.

194 replies
Newer Comments »
  1. PeterDonis says:
    ohwilleke

    Suppose that we have a top quark and an ultra sensitive gravitational force sensor.We don't have a good theory of quantum gravity, so this is not a good example to use, since we have no actual theoretical model on which to base predictions.

    Also, if you find yourself thinking that case 1 and case 2 make different predictions, you are doing something wrong. The whole point of different interpretations of QM is that they all use the same underlying mathematical model to make predictions, so they all make the same predictions. If you have something that makes different predictions, it's not an interpretation of QM, it's a different theory.

  2. ohwilleke says:
    PeterDonis

    I thought cases 1 and 2 in the article already described that, but I'll give it another shot.

    Case 1 says the state is not real; it's just a description of our knowledge of the system, in the same sense that, for example, saying that a coin has a 50-50 chance of coming up heads or tails describes our knowledge of the system–the coin itself isn't a 50-50 mixture of anything, nor is what happens when we flip it, it's just that we don't know–we can't predict–how it is going to land, we can only describe probabilities.

    Case 2 says the state is real, in the same sense that, for example, a 3-vector describing the position of an object in Newtonian physics is real: it describes the actual position of the actual object.So, to give a concrete example. Suppose that we have a top quark and an ultra sensitive gravitational force sensor.

    In Case 1, the gravitational force sensor is always going to report a gravitational force consistent with a point particle at all times.

    In Case 2, the gravitational force sensor is going to report a gravitational force consistent with having the mass-energy of the top quark smeared predominantly within a volume of space that is not point-like, because the top quark is literally present at all of the places it could be when measured to a greater or lesser degree, simultaneously.

    Or, I have a misunderstood something?

  3. ohwilleke says:
    stevendaryl

    When you're talking about huge numbers, there is the possibility of what I would call a "soft contradiction", which is something that maybe false but you're not likely to ever face the consequences of its falseness. An example from classical thermodynamics might be "Entropy always increases". You're never going to see a macroscopic violation of that claim, but our understanding of statistical mechanics tells us that it can't be literally true; there is a nonzero probability of a macroscopic system making a transition to a lower-entropy state.I like that terminology. I'll have to file it away for future use.

  4. ohwilleke says:
    PeterDonis

    I didn't want to overcomplicate the article, but this is a fair point: there should really be an additional qualifier that the dynamics of QM, the rules for how the quantum state changes with time, are linear, so there is no chaos–i.e., there is no sensitive dependence on initial conditions. You need nonlinear dynamics for that. So whatever is keeping us from making deterministic predictions about the results of quantum experiments, it isn't chaos due to nonlinear dynamics of the quantum state.That is really helpful. I've never heard anyone say that quite that clearly before.

    It's basically the same, at least to the extent that the term "reality" has a reasonably well-defined meaning at all in those discussions. The discussions about entanglement that you refer to are more relevant to my case #2: they are discussions of problems you get into if you try to interpret the quantum state in the model as modeling the physically real state of a quantum system. For case #1, entanglement and all of the phenomena connected to it are not an issue, because you don't have to believe that anything "real" happens to the system when your knowledge about it changes.Thanks again. That makes sense.

  5. PeterDonis says:
    ohwilleke

    I'm not quite clear on why it is that if "we can never make deterministic predictions about the results of quantum experiments" that this implies non-reality, as opposed, for example, to a system that is chaotic (in the sense of having dynamics that are highly sensitive to slight changes in initial conditions)I didn't want to overcomplicate the article, but this is a fair point: there should really be an additional qualifier that the dynamics of QM, the rules for how the quantum state changes with time, are linear, so there is no chaos–i.e., there is no sensitive dependence on initial conditions. You need nonlinear dynamics for that. So whatever is keeping us from making deterministic predictions about the results of quantum experiments, it isn't chaos due to nonlinear dynamics of the quantum state.

    ohwilleke

    I am also unclear with regard to whether the "reality" that you are discussing is the same as the "reality" people are talking about in QM when they state that given quantum entanglement, you can have locality, reality, or causality, but you can't simultaneously have all three, or whether you are talking about something different.It's basically the same, at least to the extent that the term "reality" has a reasonably well-defined meaning at all in those discussions. The discussions about entanglement that you refer to are more relevant to my case #2: they are discussions of problems you get into if you try to interpret the quantum state in the model as modeling the physically real state of a quantum system. For case #1, entanglement and all of the phenomena connected to it are not an issue, because you don't have to believe that anything "real" happens to the system when your knowledge about it changes.

  6. ohwilleke says:

    For #1, the obviously true part is that we can never directly observe the state, and we can never make deterministic predictions about the results of quantum experiments. That makes it seem obvious that the state can’t be the physically real state of the system; if it were, we ought to be able to pin it down and not have to settle for merely probabilistic descriptions. But if we take that idea to its logical conclusion, it implies that QM must be an incomplete theory; there ought to be some more complete description of the system that fills in the gaps and allows us to do better than merely probabilistic predictions. And yet nobody has ever found such a more complete description, and all indications from experiments (at least so far) are that no such description exists; the probabilistic predictions that QM gives us really are the best we can do.I'm not quite clear on why it is that if "we can never make deterministic predictions about the results of quantum experiments" that this implies non-reality, as opposed, for example, to a system that is chaotic (in the sense of having dynamics that are highly sensitive to slight changes in initial conditions) with sensitivity to differences in initial conditions that aren't merely hard to measure, but are inherently and theoretically impossible to measure because measurement is theoretically incapable of measuring both location and momentum at the scale relevant to the future dynamics of a particle.

    Now, I'm not saying that there aren't other aspects of QM that make a chaotic system with real particles interpretation problematic – I'm thinking of experiments that appear to localize different properties of the same particle in different physical locations, or little tricks like off-shell virtual particles and quantum tunneling. But, chaotic but deterministic systems can look so much like truly random systems phenomenologically for lots of purposes (which is why people invented tools like dice, lottery ball spinners, slot machines, card decks, and roulette wheels), so you can have a deterministic and stochastic conceptions of QM that are indistinguishable experimentally, at least for many purposes, but which have profoundly different theoretical implications. But, then again, maybe I'm wrong and there are easy ways to distinguish between the two scenarios.

    Also, I do hear you when you say that the question is whether the "state" is real, and not just whether particles are real, and the "state" is a much more empheral, ghost-like thing than a particle.

    I am also unclear with regard to whether the "reality" that you are discussing is the same as the "reality" people are talking about in QM when they state that given quantum entanglement, you can have locality, reality, or causality, but you can't simultaneously have all three, or whether you are talking about something different. To be clear, I'm not asking the more ambitious question of what "reality" means, only the less ambitious question of whether one kind of reality that is hard to define non-mathematically is the same as another kind of reality that is also hard to define non-mathematically. It could be that "reality" is instead two different concept that happens to share the same name and both of which are hard to define non-mathematically, in which case the term is a "false friend" as they say in foreign language classes.

  7. Fra says:

    I find the different perspectives interacting here truly entertaining.

    vanhees71

    This is all solid scientific work and not wild "philosophical" speculation.We can probably agree that physics is not logic, nor mathematics, nor is it philosophy. But all ingredients are needed, this is why i think physics is so much more fun than pure math.

    I think Neumaier said this already elsewhere but there is also a difference in progressing science or creating new sensible hypothesis, and applying mature science to technology. Its not a coincidence that the founders of quantum theory seemed to be very philosophical, and the people that some years later formalized and cleaned up the new ideas was less so. I think it is deeply unfair to somehow suggest that the founders like Bohr or Heisenberg was someone inferior physicists than those that worked out the mathematical formalism better in an almost axiomatic manner. This is not so at all! I think all the ingredients are important. (Even if noone said the word inferior, its easy to get almost that impression, that the hard core guys to math, and the others do philosophy)

    On the other hand, RARE are those people that can span the whole range! It takes quite some "dynamic" mindset, to not only understand complex mathematics, but also the importance or sound reasoning and how to create feedback between abstraction and fuzzy reality. If you narrow in too much anywhere along this scale you are unavoidable going to miss the big picture.

    As for "wild", I think for some pure theorists and philosophers even a soldering iron my be truly wild stuff! Who knows what can go wrong? You burn tables books and fingers. Leave it to experts ;-)

    /Fredrik

  8. bhobba says:
    AlexCaledin

    Feynman would say measurement is done when "nature knows" the outcome – is this a wild speculation?The quote you gave does not support what you said Feynman says. He was saying regardless of if you look or not if nature decides its up then its up.

    Thsnks
    Bill

  9. AlexCaledin says:

    – I mean just what an ordinary student must think reading Feynman's Lectures :

    You do add the amplitudes for the different indistinguishable alternatives inside the experiment, before the complete process is finished. At the end of the process you may say that you “don’t want to look at the photon.” That’s your business, but you still do not add the amplitudes. Nature does not know what you are looking at, and she behaves the way she is going to behave whether you bother to take down the data or not.
    . . .
    …You may argue, “I don’t care which atom is up.” Perhaps you don’t, but nature knows…"

    http://www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu/III_03.html

  10. vanhees71 says:
    A. Neumaier

    I only asserted that the bridge between theoretical physics (mathematically defined) and experimental physics (operationally defined) is philosophy, and hence open to interpretation. Only what is theoretically precise can be subject to precise arguments.Well, you can call that philosophy, but it's constraint by the necessity for empirical testability, i.e., you have an idea of how to theoretically describe an experiment, including the preparation of the observed system and the measurement of the quantities of interest and then see whether the experiment agrees or disagrees with that prediction. Of course, it's not easy to analyze the errors in both experiment and theory etc. etc. E.g., the claim one might have discovered faster-than-light neutrinos at CERN could not immediately lead to giving up relativity but one had to exclude all sources of errors in the experimental setup first, and indeed after an independent control measurement in accordance with the theory and a long search one found two defects in the time-of-flight-measurement setup which finally explained the wrong findings etc. etc. This is all solid scientific work and not wild "philosophical" speculation.

  11. A. Neumaier says:
    bhobba

    Yes – but its usually pretty obvious philosophy. If you get too deep about it you are led into very murky waters and really don't get anywhere.It is pretty obvious in classical mechanics but not in quantum mechanics. This is why the quantum measurement problem constitutes very murky waters, and nobody really gets anywhere, before it is made pretty obvious.

  12. bhobba says:
    A. Neumaier

    I only asserted that the bridge between theoretical physics (mathematically defined) and experimental physics (operationally defined) is philosophy, and hence open to interpretation. Only what is theoretically precise can be subject to precise arguments.Yes – but its usually pretty obvious philosophy. If you get too deep about it you are led into very murky waters and really don't get anywhere.

    With regard to Ballentine he does indeed analyse such things and uses the Ensemble interpretation. I wont argue if it's the right one, but its pretty simple and does provide a minimalist sort of link between the formalism and application.

    It's like when you first learn the Kolmogorov axioms how to apply it ie what is meant by events etc is picked up with a bit of experience. They gave it meaning with a not too rigorous reference to the strong law of large numbers – which of course cant be fully detailed at the beginner level. Its fixed up later but the alternate Bayesian view isn't usually presented until Bayesian statistics. I don't think I ever formally studied the Cox axioms – l learnt about it years later in my own reading.

    Difficult interpretive issues are mostly deferred. Strangely though around here with beginners it seems to dominate. Interesting isnt it.

    Thanks
    Bill

  13. A. Neumaier says:
    vanhees71

    the deformed view about physics that everything should be mathematically defined, but physics is no mathematics.I only asserted that the bridge between theoretical physics (mathematically defined) and experimental physics (operationally defined) is philosophy, and hence open to interpretation. Only what is theoretically precise can be subject to precise arguments.

  14. vanhees71 says:

    Again, a theory book or scientific paper has not the purpose to tell how something is measured. That's done in experimental-physics textbooks and scientific papers! Of course, if you only read theoretical-physics and math literature you can come to the deformed view about physics that everything should be mathematically defined, but physics is no mathematics. It just uses matheamtics as a language to express its findings using real-world devices (including our senses to the most complicated inventions of engineering like the detectors at the LHC).

  15. A. Neumaier says:
    bhobba

    Ballentine has two axioms

    1. Outcomes of observations are the eigenvalues of some operator.
    2. The Born Rule.But he doesn't say what it means that one subsystem (an observer) of the physical system called the Earth has measured a property of another subsystem (a particle, say). This is the gap that makes all the interpretations vague when it comes to analyzing the measurement process as a physical process rather than as a metaphysical appearance of outcomes of observations from nowhere. It is filled by vague words about a collapse happening (when and where), worlds splitting (why and how?), etc..

  16. vanhees71 says:
    Ian J Miller

    In my opinion, part of the reason there is such scope for interpretations is that nobody actually KNOWS what Ψ means. Either there is an actual wave of there is not, and here we have the first room for debate. If there is, how come nobody can find it, and if there is not, how come a stream of particles reproduce a diffraction pattern in the two slit experiment? No matter which option you try, somewhere there is a dead rat to swallow. As it happens, I have my own interpretation which differs from others in two ways after you assume there is an actual wave. The first, the phase exp(2πiS/h) becomes real when S = h (or h/2) – from Euler. This is why electrons pair in an energy well, despite repelling each other. Since it becomes real at the antinode, I add the premise that the expectation values of variables can be obtained there. The second is that if there is a wave, the wave front has to arrive at the two slits about the same time as the particle. If so, the wave must transmit energy (which waves generally do, but the dead rat here is where is this extra energy? However, it is better than Bohm's quantum potential because it has a specific value.) The Uncertainty Principle and Exclusion Principle follow readily, as does why the electron does not radiate its way to the nucleus. The value in this, from my point of view, is it makes the calculation of things like the chemical bond so much easier – the hydrogen molecule becomes almost mental arithmetic, although things get more complicated as the number of electrons increase. Nevertheless, the equations for Sb2 gave an energy within about 2 kJ/mol, which is not bad.In real-world physics there's not much scope for interpretations. QT is just used as what it is, namely a mathematical description of what's observed in nature, and it is very well known what ##psi## (or more generally quantum states) mean: It gives probabilities for the outcome of measurements on a system which is prepared in the corresponding state. The diffraction pattern is quite easily predicted by solving the Schrödinger equation. There's no "dead rat to swallow". I don't comment on your enigmatic claims on the phase etc.

  17. bhobba says:
    Auto-Didact

    What is mathematically inconsistent about QM is that half the formalism (measurement process) has completely different mathematical properties than the other half (Schrodinger equation). Its even worse than that since the measurement process has not even actually been fully formalized. There is no other physical theory which suffers from these problems.I have a couple of minutes spare before going to the dentist so can answer some of the other issues raised.

    Remember what I said before: 'Imagine you have a coin that has a predictable mechanism inside it so its bias deterministically varies in time. You can write a deterministic equation giving the probabilities of getting heads or tales if flipped.'

    That leads to exactly the same situation as QM – a deterministic equation describing a probabilistic quantity. Is that inconsistent too? Of course not. Inconsistency – definition: If there are inconsistencies in two statements, one cannot be true if the other is true. Obviously it can be true that observations are probabilistic and the equation describing those probabilities deterministic. There is no inconsistency at all,

    And the measurement process has been fully formalized – its just after decoherence has occurred. The issue is not everyone agrees for reasons I have mentioned before. I will not argue they are wrong and I am correct – but saying that it has not been resolved is misrepresenting the situation. It just has not been resolved to everyone's satisfaction eg some want a 'formalization' where interference terms just don't decay to a very small value – but are actually zero. Most would say for all practical purposes (FAPP) it has been resolved – in fact probably many who think issues of defining remain will likely agree it has been resolved FAPP – they just want more than FAPP. I am not going to argue if they are right or wrong – I think everyone knows my opinion – but opinions are like bums – everyone has one – it does not make it correct. But this is in large part a philosophical morass – is FAPP good enough? It's part of what I mean if you push it too hard you are lead into a morass of issues.

    And, as posted previously – its the same with many areas of applied math – push it too hard and you are lead down a path like Wittgenstein was led down. He was an excellent applied mathematician studying aeronautical science. He went to do his PhD but came under the influence of Bertrand Russell and wanted to know 'why' about issues with even basic arithmetic. He then became a philosopher. His view was very strange from a scientific viewpoint – he thought it all just convention. Was he correct – blowed if I know – all I can say to me its a very strange view.

    Thanks
    Bill

  18. bhobba says:
    Stephen Tashi

    Why is the concept of the collapse of a wave function any more (or any less) of a problem in logical consistency than other applications of probability theory where there are probabilities of various outcomes followed by only one of the outcomes happening?Of course it isn't – leaving aside that collapse isn't really part of QM – only some interpretations. In fact QM is simply a generalization of ordinary probability theory:
    https://arxiv.org/abs/1402.6562

    Stephen Tashi

    Mathematical probability theory (based on measure theory) says nothing about events actually happening and has no axiom stating that it is possible to take take random samples. Taking random samples (i.e. "realizing" the outcome of a random variable) is a topic for applications of probability theory, so it involves an interpretation of probability theory not explicitly given in the mathematical axioms.Exactly – and that's where the morass I previously spoke about comes into it. If you push it too deeply you run unto unresolved philosophical issues of a formidable nature – even in ordinary probability theory when you apply it they rear their ugly head. But its usually bypassed by simple reasonableness criteria such as for all practical purposes. An example is the issue I mentioned, since QM is a theory about observations that appear here in an assumed macro world (we will exclude strange interpretations like consciousness creates the external world and causes collapse and stick with what most consider reasonable and not 'mystical') how can it explain that world? We have made a lot of progress in that but if you really push it, it still has issues eg decoherence models show that interference terms very quickly decay to zero – but usually never quite reach it – but are so small to be irrelevant. Some do not accept that (ie it must be zero to truly explain it) – which is OK – but then you are stuck, as I put it in a very deep morass of complex issues. Physics has long made reasonableness assumptions – if you don't do that then you are unlikely to get anywhere – although occasionally you can find something very deep and powerful such as in figuring out what that damnable Dirac Delta Function really is you create distribution theory that has wide applicability. But often you get nowhere.

    Stephen Tashi

    Is that a good analogy, from your point of view?Of course.

    Thanks
    Bill

  19. bhobba says:
    Auto-Didact

    One of the goals and duties of mathematical and theoretical physicists is to be able to demonstrate mathematical consistency of a physical theory by being to able to derive a theory entirely from first principles; QM is just another physical theory and thus not an exception to this. As the theory stands today, since its conception, this full derivation is not yet possible; no other accepted physical theory suffers from this. (NB: QFT has foundational issues as well, but that's another discussion).Ballentine has two axioms

    1. Outcomes of observations are the eigenvalues of some operator.
    2. The Born Rule.

    Everything is derived from that except some things that in physics is usually accepted eg you can find the derivative of a wave-function and the POR.

    So I have zero idea where you are getting this from – its certainly not from textbooks that carefully examine QM. Textbooks at the beginner/intermediate level sometimes have issues – but they are fixed in the better, but unfortunately, more advanced texts.

    There are other misconceptions – but that's the one that stood out to me.

    Thanks
    Bill

  20. Fra says:
    AlexCaledin

    But how it can be coherent? What happens in every local measurement is choice between variants of the whole universe, while QM is telling about a limited experimental system.Posting past midnight isnt a good thing but here is a simplified view of what i think of as an "inference interpretation", which is a highly twisted version of Peter Donis (1) version of the interpretation.

    Coherence requires unifying unitary evolution with information updates, in the sense that in the unitary description by O3 of [O1 observing O2] must have a hamiltonian describing the internation interactions of the O1-O2 system that as per the inside view, is information updates. The problem is that if O1 is not a classical observer, the current theory does not apply. This is conceptually incoherent.

    1) "Observer equivalence"
    A coherent theory of physical inference must somehow apply to any observers inference on its environment. Not only to classical observers, because the difference is simply a matter of complexity scale(mass?). Current experimental evidence provides NO insight into the inferences of non-classical observers(*)

    2) "Inferrability"
    An inference itself contains premises and some rule of the inference. This rule can be a deductive rule such as hamiltonian evolution, or it can be a random walk. The other premises are typicaly initial conditions or priorly prepared states. Now from the point of view of requiring that only inferrable arguments enter the inference, we end up with the conclusion that we must treat information about initial conditions, no different than information about the rules. Ie. a coherent theory should unify state and law.

    => The inference systems itself, is inferred, and thus evolves. We natuarally reach a paradigm of evolution of physical law.

    (*) This ultimately relates to unifying the interactions. To unify forces, and to understand how the hamiltonian or lagrangian of the unified interactions look like, is the same problem as to understand how all physical interactions in the standard model can be understood as the small non-classical observers making inferences and measurements on each other.

    Once this is "clear", the task is to "reinvent" the mathematical models we need:
    My mathematical grip on this, is that i have started a reconstruction of an algorithmic style of inference, implemented as random processes guided by evolving constraints. Physical interactions will be modelled a bit like "interacting computers", where the computer hardware are associated with the structure of matter. Even the computers evolve, and if this is consistent, one should get predictions from stable coexisting structures, that match the standard model. All in a conceptually coherent way.

    Conventional models based on continuum mathematics should also correspond to steady states. In particular certain deductive logical system are understood as emergent "stable rules" in an a priori crazy game. In this sense we will see ALL interactions as emergent.

    The big problem here is that the complexity here is so large, that no computer simulation can simulated the real thing, because the computational time actually relates to time evolution and tehre is simply no way to "speed up time". But theere is on exploit that has given me hope, and that is to look at the simplest possible observers, it would be probably doable to simulate parts of the first fractions of the big bang for one reason – the rules from the INSIDE are expected to be almost trivially simple at unification scale. They just LOOK complicated from the low energy perspective. But the task is huge indeed. But its not just a philosophical mess at all! Its rather a huge task of trying to reconstruct from this picture all spacetime and matter properties.

    /Fredrik

  21. David Halliday says:

    I understand that you were primarily contrasting two (2) interpretations (alluding to something like a third, or so), but there are a whole lot more than just a few interpretations that can be "cubbyholed" into the dichotomy you presented. (Basically, there are additional choices and other "dimensions" that can differ as well.)

    However, your conclusion that "the best we can do at this point is to accept that reasonable people can disagree on QM interpretations and leave it at that" still holds firm!

  22. Auto-Didact says:
    bhobba

    No – its perfectly consistent.
    … But be my quest – post the exact inconsistency. Schrodinger's equation is a deterministic equation about something (the wavefunction) that determines probabilities – there is no inconsistency in that.There is nothing mathematically inconsistent about the Schrodinger equation itself. What is mathematically inconsistent about QM is that half the formalism (measurement process) has completely different mathematical properties than the other half (Schrodinger equation). Its even worse than that since the measurement process has not even actually been fully formalized. There is no other physical theory which suffers from these problems.

    stevendaryl

    I think an actual inconsistency is impossible to prove because one half of the quantum formalism is informal: The notion of what it means to measure a quantity.Exactly my point.

    A. Neumaier

    This is only a definition of what an observable is, not a definition of what it means to have measured something. (The link addresses only the classical situation, where this actually can be modeled, in principle.)Arnold, as usual, hits the nail on the head.

    bhobba

    Meaning – of course that's something different that the math bypasses. Of course – it's what an observable is – not the MEANING of to measure/observe. That however is a minefield if you want to pin it down exactly – but almost trivial in use.Application is of course trivial, but that is misunderstanding the problem at hand here. One of the goals and duties of mathematical and theoretical physicists is to be able to demonstrate mathematical consistency of a physical theory by being to able to derive a theory entirely from first principles; QM is just another physical theory and thus not an exception to this. As the theory stands today, since its conception, this full derivation is not yet possible; no other accepted physical theory suffers from this. (NB: QFT has foundational issues as well, but that's another discussion).

    bhobba

    The same in QM – if you look at it very deeply its a morass (just one obvious thing – since observations occur here in the macro world how does a theory that assumes such in the first place explain it – a lot of progress has been made – I think the answers we now know are just fine – others disagree) – if not its rather obvious. Its a matter of taste if you think such questions are worthwhile. I happen to think going too deep into it isn't that worthwhile – but not everyone agrees.With all due respect, but your personal opinion or the opinion of large groups of physicists on what is or isn't worthwhile figuring out with respect to theories lacking proper foundations yet being able to generate predictions, should not be given too much weight. Actually putting too much weight on the experts opinion is doing a disservice to science, because doing this leads to the creation of a perpetuation of dogma among the young practitioners who often lack the experience or courage to properly analyse the expert's points. The incessant upholding of expert opinion and promulgating of obscurantist dogma is equivalent to relaxing or removing the capability of a science to spontaneously self-correct.

    This is no new phenomenon here either, the other sciences are absolutely rife with this problem, precisely because almost all their theories have not ever reached the stage of being sufficiently formalized such that it can be fully derived from first principles, in stark contrast with theories in physics. In the history of physics however, it is precisely such fundamental inconsistencies in theories as we see here in QM which have ended up unraveling centuries long accepted theories and research programmes, e.g. Aristotelian mechanics, Ptolemaic epicycle theory and Newtonian gravity. In each of the above cases, the experts and practitioners also tended to agree that the theories worked marvelously and relooking at the foundations of their theory wasn't a worthwhile endeavor, sometimes even dogmatically insisting on not doing so and so delaying scientific progress for centuries. These invaluable insights into science as a human process, which itself can be studied in a scientific manner, are important lessons easily gained purely by taking the history and philosophy of science, and in particular that of physics, to heart.

  23. PeterDonis says:
    Stephen Tashi

    It's controversial whether probabilities (in physics) represent a state of knowledge or whether they are objective.Yes, agreed; but as you note, for purposes of this discussion I am using the term in the former sense.

    Stephen Tashi

    In your view, the angle theta is a "physically real" aspect of the coin and the probability of the coin landing heads is not.Yes.

  24. Stephen Tashi says:

    Why is the concept of the collapse of a wave function any more (or any less) of a problem in logical consistency than other applications of probability theory where there are probabilities of various outcomes followed by only one of the outcomes happening?

    Mathematical probability theory (based on measure theory) says nothing about events actually happening and has no axiom stating that it is possible to take take random samples. Taking random samples (i.e. "realizing" the outcome of a random variable) is a topic for applications of probability theory, so it involves an interpretation of probability theory not explicitly given in the mathematical axioms.

    PeterDonis

    Sure, that's why I said we're dealing with vague ordinary language. I'm not trying to put a specific definition on the word "real". I'm just trying to say that, as far as I can tell, people who espouse Case 1 interpretations consider the quantum state to be like probabilities, and in common ordinary language usage probabilities do not describe the physically real state of anything; they just describe our knowledge (or the limitations thereof). If it helps, substitute "case 1 says the quantum state is like probabilities" for "case 1 says the quantum state is not real".It's controversial whether probabilities (in physics) represent a state of knowledge or whether they are objective. However, your make it clear that your definition of "physically real" excludes a quantity that represents a probability.

    Case 2 interpretations of QM do not say a physically real state produces a deterministic outcome (that would contradict stan; they just say the quantum state is physically real. So I don't see how this helps to clarify anything relevant to this discussion.To make a classical analogy, suppose we take a coin with uniform mass density and bend it in the middle at angle theta. When used in a coin toss experiment, the angle theta may affect the probability that the coin lands heads. In your view, the angle theta is a "physically real" aspect of the coin and the probability of the coin landing heads is not.

    Is that a good analogy, from your point of view?

  25. bhobba says:
    Fra

    I think of the mathematical theory of QM as incoherent from the point of a general inference perspective. Sometimes i think of this as inconsistent reasoning. But this reasoning is not deductive in nature its more abductive but even such may have consistency requirements.Gee – I wonder why it has never been falsified.

    The mathematics is not incoherent – what is incoherent is thinking the obvious mapping you use to apply is somehow at fault – it isn't. Its like saying the obvious mapping you use in applying Euclidean Geometry to points and lines is incoherent. Its a very difficult philosophical question when looked at deeply enough – but even 10 year olds have no trouble doing it. The same in QM – if you look at it very deeply its a morass (just one obvious thing – since observations occur here in the macro world how does a theory that assumes such in the first place explain it – a lot of progress has been made – I think the answers we now know are just fine – others disagree) – if not its rather obvious. Its a matter of taste if you think such questions are worthwhile. I happen to think going too deep into it isn't that worthwhile – but not everyone agrees.

    Thanks
    Bill

  26. AlexCaledin says:
    Fra

    … mathematical theory of QM as incoherent …But how it can be coherent? What happens in every local measurement is choice between variants of the whole universe, while QM is telling about a limited experimental system.

  27. Fra says:
    stevendaryl

    So the inconsistency that I worry about is not in the mathematical formalism, but in applying the mathematical formalism to a real measurement.Indeed. And this is exactly where the physics part lies.

    A mathematician can easily enter the mine field as he can walk without feet.

    I think of the mathematical theory of QM as incoherent from the point of a general inference perspective. Sometimes i think of this as inconsistent reasoning. But this reasoning is not deductive in nature its more abductive but even such may have consistency requirements.

    /Fredrik

  28. A. Neumaier says:
    Fra

    whether it is rational to enter the minefield in order to progress fundamental physicsThis is not primarily a matter of ratio but of personal preferences and risk profiles.

    I find it worth my time to ponder about the measurement problem at its root.

  29. A. Neumaier says:
    bhobba

    Yes :smile::smile::smile::smile::smile::smile::smile::smile:.

    But then again it likely applies to a number of areas in applied math if you think about it hard enough eg normal probability theory – John Baez certainly thinks so:
    http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/bayes.htmlYes, see https://www.physicsforums.com/posts/5918976/ for a reference that discusses this in some depth.
    But in classical mechanics this is no fundamental issue since probability enters only through the approximation process.

  30. Fra says:
    A. Neumaier

    This is the root of the problem in clarifying the precise meaning of quantum mechanics, and hence the source of the many interpretations.Another distinguishing factor that reflects the selection principle for our interpretations is wether it is rational to enter the minefield in order to progress fundamental physics or not?

    This is another factor that divides us.

    /Fredrik

  31. bhobba says:
    stevendaryl

    I don't think that decoherence changes anything in principle. In practice, decoherence makes it impossible to see macroscopic superpositions. So we're free to assume that once decoherence has occurred, that the miracle of collapse has already happened. We're free to assume that in the practical sense that observations are not likely to prove us wrong.Correct – other assumptions are required without detailing them eg you assume an observation has occurred once decoherence happens.

    Thanks
    Bill

  32. bhobba says:
    A. Neumaier

    This is the root of the problem in clarifying the precise meaning of quantum mechanics, and hence the source of the many interpretations.Yes :smile::smile::smile::smile::smile::smile::smile::smile:.

    But then again it likely applies to a number of areas in applied math if you think about it hard enough eg normal probability theory.

    Thanks
    Bill

  33. A. Neumaier says:
    bhobba

    the MEANING of to measure/observe. That however is a minefield if you want to pin it down exactly – but almost trivial in use.This is the root of the problem in clarifying the precise meaning of quantum mechanics, and hence the source of the many interpretations.

  34. stevendaryl says:
    bhobba

    Now in applying it you have to map the formalism to things you want to apply the theory to. In principle you should be able to do it, but using the methods in that book I haven't seen it, but using normal methods at least a partial solution is known in decoherence models.I don't think that decoherence changes anything in principle. In practice, decoherence makes it impossible to see macroscopic superpositions. So we're free to assume that once decoherence has occurred, that the miracle of collapse has already happened. We're free to assume that in the practical sense that observations are not likely to prove us wrong.

  35. bhobba says:
    stevendaryl

    So the inconsistency that I worry about is not in the mathematical formalism, but in applying the mathematical formalism to a real measurement. Is the description of the measurement process as a complex quantum interaction among a macroscopic number of particles consistent with the abstraction described in that paper?Its a textbook by mathematicians for mathematicians.

    Now in applying it you have to map the formalism to things you want to apply the theory to. In principle you should be able to do it, but using the methods in that book I haven't seen it, but using normal methods at least a partial solution is known in decoherence models. Its like Hilbert's Euclidean Geometry axioms and Euclid's. Everybody in practice uses Euclid – but in principle you could use Hilbert's.

    Thanks
    Bill

  36. stevendaryl says:
    bhobba

    Mathematical consistency is what I am talking about. Everything is defined rigorously in mathematical language in the reference I gave – includung to measure ie
    page 12 'Suppose L is an abstract Boolean σ-algebra. We shall define a Y-valued observable associated with L to be any σ-homomorphism B(Y) into L. If Y is the real line we call these observables real valued and refer to them simply as observables.' Here B(Y) is the all the Borel subsets of Y into L.Without getting into the mathematical details of how that works, I certainly believe that a formalization of measurement along mathematical lines such as those can be made consistent. My worries about inconsistency are not found there. What the authors are describing is an abstraction of the measurement process. However, an actual measurement in the real world is an interaction involving a macroscopic number of particles, each of which is presumably described by quantum mechanics. So the inconsistency that I worry about is not in the mathematical formalism, but in applying the mathematical formalism to a real measurement. Is the description of the measurement process as a complex quantum interaction among a macroscopic number of particles consistent with the abstraction described in that paper?

  37. bhobba says:
    A. Neumaier

    This is only a definition of what an observable is, not a definition of what it means to have measured something. (The link addresses only the classical situation, where this actually can be modeled, in principle.)Meaning – of course that's something different that the math bypasses. Of course – it's what an observable is – not the MEANING of to measure/observe. That however is a minefield if you want to pin it down exactly – but almost trivial in use.

    Thanks
    Bill

  38. A. Neumaier says:
    bhobba

    Mathematical consistency is what I am talking about. Everything is defined rigorously in mathematical language in the reference I gave – includung to measure ie
    page 12 'Suppose L is an abstract Boolean σ-algebra. We shall define a Y-valued observable associated with L to be any σ-homomorphism B(Y) into L. If Y is the real line we call these observables real valued and refer to them simply as observables.' Here B(Y) is the all the Borel subsets of Y into L.This is only a definition of what an observable is, not a definition of what it means to have measured something. (The link addresses only the classical situation, where this actually can be modeled, in principle.)

  39. bhobba says:
    stevendaryl

    I think an actual inconsistency is impossible to prove because one half of the quantum formalism is informal: The notion of what it means to measure a quantity.Mathematical consistency is what I am talking about. Everything is defined rigorously in mathematical language in the reference I gave – includung to measure ie
    page 12 'Suppose L is an abstract Boolean σ-algebra. We shall define a Y-valued observable associated with L to be any σ-homomorphism B(Y) into L. If Y is the real line we call these observables real valued and refer to them simply as observables.' Here B(Y) is the all the Borel subsets of Y into L.

    Just another example of how a theory becomes unrecognizable once mathematicians get a hold of it.

    What mathematical consistency independent physical consistency in a physics theory means I am not sure of.

    Thanks
    Bill

  40. stevendaryl says:
    bhobba

    No – its perfectly consistent.I think an actual inconsistency is impossible to prove because one half of the quantum formalism is informal: The notion of what it means to measure a quantity. Since measurement necessarily involves macroscopic systems with astronomical numbers of degrees of freedom, there is no feasible way to do an exact analysis of the measurement process. When you're talking about huge numbers, there is the possibility of what I would call a "soft contradiction", which is something that maybe false but you're not likely to ever face the consequences of its falseness. An example from classical thermodynamics might be "Entropy always increases". You're never going to see a macroscopic violation of that claim, but our understanding of statistical mechanics tells us that it can't be literally true; there is a nonzero probability of a macroscopic system making a transition to a lower-entropy state.

  41. bhobba says:
    Auto-Didact

    This stochastic selection of the state from the ensemble which occurs during a measurement is precisely what makes QM a mathematically inconsistent theory consisting of deterministic unitary evolution and a stochastic non-unitary reduction. The former is the orthodox viewpoint of QM theoreticians.No – its perfectly consistent.

    If you don't think so you need to see a rigorous presentation and the exact axioms its based on:
    https://www.amazon.com/Geometry-Quantum-Theory-V-S-Varadarajan/dp/0387493859

    If you can find an inconsistency be my quest. Many very great mathematicians have studied it and found none. Of course I too have read it – it has none I can find. But be my quest – post the exact inconsistency. Schrodinger's equation is a deterministic equation about something (the wavefunction) that determines probabilities – there is no inconsistency in that. Imagine you have a coin that has a predictable mechanism inside it so its bias deterministically varies in time. You can write a deterministic equation giving the probabilities of getting heads or tales if flipped.

    Thanks
    Bill

  42. stevendaryl says:

    Very nice, and concise, summary of the key aspects of the disagreement over interpretations of QM, @PeterDonis.

    The PBR theorem, which for a long time left me cold, because it didn't seem to prove anything new, seems to be a strong argument against the claim that [itex]psi[/itex] is epistemological.

    Here's my nonmathematical of what I think their argument amounts to: If [itex]psi[/itex] is just epistemological, then there would be a possibility of two situations that differ only in our knowledge. For a classical example, with coin flips, we can have two situations:

    1. I flip a coin and look at it and see that it's "heads". We describe this by "P(H) = 1, P(T) = 0". It has zero probability of being tails.
    2. I flip a coin and don't look at it. We describe this by "P(H) = 1/2, P(T) = 1/2". It has equal probability of being tails.

    If I prepare two coins, one via procedure 1, and one via procedure 2, there may be no difference in the coins in the two cases: It's possible that they're both "heads". So obviously, there is no empirical test that is guaranteed to distinguish, once and for all, which of those cases we're in.

    In contrast, consider two spin-1/2 particles, one of which is prepared to have spin-up in the z-direction [itex]|psi_1rangle = |Urangle[/itex], and the other of which is in the superposition state:[itex]|psi_2rangle = frac{1}{sqrt{2}} (|Urangle + beta |Drangle)[/itex]. PBR argues that if the quantum state is epistemological, just reflecting our knowledge, then there should be no way to empirically distinguish these two in a single test. If they can be distinguished in a single test, then that shows that there is something "real" about the difference. The PBR theorem shows that if two systems do not have identical wave functions, then it is possible (in principle) to distinguish them in a single experiment.

    Okay, they don't actually show that. What they show is that if you have two different wave functions, you can use them to construct two different composite (entangled) states of two identical systems such that a single experiment suffices to distinguish the two states.

  43. lightarrow says:
    PeterDonis

    Please read what I said in the article: I said that viewpoint #2 says that the quantum state is "physically real". In other words, the wave function/state vector/whatever you want to call it, a particular well-defined thing in the math, represents something "physically real". The quantum state is not position, momentum, spin components, etc. It's the particular well-defined thing in the math.Thanks.


    lightarrow

  44. Auto-Didact says:
    bhobba

    Here he pinpoints what he thinks is the central issue – its how an improper mixed state becomes a proper one. It, at a more technical level is just a variation on how is the result selected from the ensemble.Exactly. This stochastic selection of the state from the ensemble which occurs during a measurement is precisely what makes QM a mathematically inconsistent theory consisting of deterministic unitary evolution and a stochastic non-unitary reduction. The former is the orthodox viewpoint of QM theoreticians.
    The latter is not used to mathematically derive the theory as the former is, but is instead empirically seen and thus tacked on next to the mathematical derivation as phenomenology.

    bhobba

    To understand it you have to go back to the actual axioms of QM as found in a good source like Ballentine – there you will see nothing at all about collapse – its simply part of some interpretations. That's the real value of this interpretation stuff IMHO.I agree with all of this except specifically that collapse is de facto not actually an interpretation of QM because orthodox QM has no collapse, orthodox QM being purely the Schrodinger equation and its mathematical properties. As I said above however QM as a whole is a mathematically inconsistent conjoining of the Schrodinger equation and the stochastic selection of the state from the ensemble which occurs empirically.

    Collapse is therefore a prediction of a phenomenologic theory which directly competes with QM, but which has yet to be mathematically formulated. This theory should then contain QM as some particular low order limit, analogous to how Newtonian mechanics is a low order limit of SR.

    The reason this theory has continued to defy mathematical formulation is because the two aspects of QM, i.e. unitary evolution and stochastic reduction, aren't easily mathematically unified due to all kinds of incompatible views and differing attitudes between their respective underlying mathematical bases. I believe higher category theory might be necessary to resolve this issue.

  45. bhobba says:
    meopemuk

    I think, following Einstein and Bohr, we can make this dilemma even simpler. The question is: "Does God really play dice?"I know where you are coming from – but I would express it slightly differently – but that difference IMHO is crucial.

    That god played dice with the universe didn't really worry him – despite the famous quote. After all, as I mentioned previously he made foundational contributions to statistical mechanins. Einstein thought there was a reason why God payed dice – like there is in statistical mechanics. In his view this was evidence it was incomplete – which is what he thought to his dying day. And indeed it is incomplete eg we don't have a theory of Quantum Gravity below the Plank Scale. Einstein wanted to know what God thought when he made the world – he simply thought it went beyond just probabilities. It's just a conviction he had about the world. He may even be correct – who knows what we may uncover when a complete theory of Quantum Gravity is finally arrived at.

    Thanks
    Bill

  46. bhobba says:
    microsansfil

    To buid a rational and complet interpretation, it seems to me that we need to dissect how we construct our knowledge from the effects we capture up to ours objectifications and taking in acount all the humain process from ours first-person experience. Moreover It could be relevant to be aware of our blind spot when we made ours objectivations/reifications.I think we have many rational and compete interpretations – that's the issue. Which do you pick?

    My view is it doesn't really matter – I have picked one – but really who cares. As a practical matter it's wise to know at least a couple – they all shed light on the formalism. For example, naively, and you will find it even in some textbooks, you may think QM has collapse – it doesn't – as many worlds proves. To understand it you have to go back to the actual axioms of QM as found in a good source like Ballentine – there you will see nothing at all about collapse – its simply part of some interpretations. That's the real value of this interpretation stuff IMHO.

    Thanks
    Bill

  47. bhobba says:

    Nice article Peter.

    Ok – what to I think about interpretations?

    Well first I think everyone should know a couple – they all shed light of the formalism.

    But what do we have then – what exactly is the central mystery of QM. I don't its that it is probabilistic – Einstein for example despite his famous quote – didn't really have a problem with that – he just thought it evidence it was incomplete like statistical mechanics is incomplete without knowing its underlying basis – classical mechanics. He even came up with his own interpretation – the Ensemble – to make that idea clearer.The real issue boils down IMHO to two things

    1. Simply a carry over of the arguments some have about the meaning of probability:
    http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/bayes.html

    Einstein hated subjectivity coming into physics and rebelled against Copenhagen because it took a more subjective view – that's another reason he came up came up with his Ensemble Interpretation:
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ensemble_interpretation

    Here his issue with QM is clearly laid out – how is the observation selected from the ensemble – he deliberately chose that name because its widely used in statistical mechanics and wanted to pinpoint clearly the issue – we know why in statistical mechanics – we need to also know why in QM.

    2. The issue is gone into quite deeply by Schlosshauer:
    https://www.amazon.com/Decoherence-Classical-Transition-Frontiers-Collection/dp/3540357734

    Here he pinpoints what he thinks is the central issue – its how an improper mixed state becomes a proper one. It, at a more technical level is just a variation on how is the result is selected from the ensemble.

    There are all sorts of answers depending on the interpretation:

    1. Many Worlds. Nothing is selected – they all happen – but in separate worlds.
    2. Who cares – science always assumes things – this is just another assumption – you don't like that particular assumption ie it somehow becomes a proper mixed state then its simply your issue – nature is as nature is.
    3. Bohmian Mechanics. The result exists before observation because everything is objectively real.
    4, Decoherent Histories. Reformulate the problem in a different way as the stochastic theory of histories (a history is simply a sequence of projection operators) – its like Many Worlds without the Many Worlds.
    5. Nelsons Stochastic's – at a level we cant experimentally reach yet – or maybe never will be able to – there are stochastic processes similar to statistical mechanics.

    Tons of others.

    I hold to 2 – but some are not satisfied with that. That's the key issue IMHO.

    Thanks
    Bill

  48. DennisN says:

    Nice article, Peter Donis!

    I've recently developed a new interpretation, MII, the Many Interpretations Interpretation.
    It's incredibly simple, only two postulates, and it is guaranteed to satisfy every physicist;

    1. The system exists in a superposition of interpretations.
    2. When the system is observed, it collapses into the interpretation most favored by the experimenter.

    An added benefit is that this interpretation explains why there are so many different interpretations (due to different people), but it fails to explain why we get a particular interpretation for a particular person.
    :smile:

  49. bhobba says:
    Ian J Miller

    In my opinion, part of the reason there is such scope for interpretations is that nobody actually KNOWS what Ψ means.That's not quite true.

    I would become acquainted with Gleasons Theorem:
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gleason's_theorem

    At a rigorous mathematical level:
    file:///D:/Users/Owner/Downloads/Gleasonexplained.pdf

    Or the version I came up with (its the same as in the above but I worked hard to spell each step out – see post 137):
    https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/the-born-rule-in-many-worlds.763139/page-7

    I will post my view on the reason for different interpretations in a minute. Of course it in no way changes the excellent article Peter wrote – just a different view.

    Thanks
    Bill

  50. meopemuk says:

    Peter,

    thank you for condensing this debate to two simple alternatives. I think, following Einstein and Bohr, we can make this dilemma even simpler. The question is: "Does God really play dice?"

    If your answer is "no", then you have to complain

    PeterDonis

    … it implies that QM must be an incomplete theory; there ought to be some more complete description of the system that fills in the gaps and allows us to do better than merely probabilistic predictions.But if you are OK with God playing dice, then there is nothing wrong with the probabilistic behavior of Nature. All these quantum events are simply unpredictable. So, existing quantum mechanics does a good job at describing this unpredictability. If somebody asks you why the electron hit this particular place on the screen, you can simply reply: "I don't know and don't care. It was just random."

    I think, with this thought all of us should rejoice: we finally came to a satisfying end of the scientific quest (at least in this particular direction). We don't have to keep unraveling the never-ending chain of cause-and-effect relationships. Because we came to the class of quantum events, which don't have causes, since they are truly random. Congratulations everyone!

    Eugene.

  51. Auto-Didact says:

    I am somewhat surprised this thread is allowed at all, since interpretations of QM is purely a philosophy of science/physics topic. This side discussion about the imprecision of language is a red herring, since there are already certain words in philosophy which have specified meanings to make clear distinctions, for example, physical is such a word. As was said before in post 5, the main distinction between interpretations of QM is precisely whether or not the state is itself ontic or epistemic; everything else (e.g. whether or not it is determistic or stochastic) is independent with regard to the ontic/epistemic distinction.

    Moreover, some 'interpretations' of QM, in particular the collapse ones, are clearly not interpretations but incomplete extensions to or revisions of QM, i.e. alternative theories awaiting mathematical completion. It is here most clearly that philosophers of physics, i.e. physicists and other scientists focusing on these philosophical themes of their discipline by extending theories and placing extensions and alternative hypotheses in proper context, have contributed more to this aspect of physics than regular physicists have done so far.

    This is an essential aspect of science which does not nearly get enough attention, mostly because in the practice of physics we don’t often explicitly run into such difficulties (implicitly is a whole different story) and therefore don't see the need for philosophical expertise. When we do however run into these difficulties, this kind of philosophical reevaluation of some theory is the correct method to take that actually can point the way forward. It is somewhat a matter of luck that in the early 20th, both Einstein and the founders of QM acknowledged this and so could end up discarding and reformulating core traditional principles of physics and so end up creating the correct mathematical formulations thereof, which we today refer to as relativity and QM.

    Today we are somewhat priviliged that the philosophers of physics have already simplified and classified the different interpretations and also given instructions on how to proceed. It is tragic that not many physicists have been willing to listen. In any case, the only way physicists can do more in advancing our understanding of QM deeper than what the philosophers of physics have done so far, is by actually creating new mathematical theories based on or incorporating those ideas from first principle, with hopefully one of the resulting mathematical theories being self-consistent and simultaneously not being trivially equivalent to QM itself.

    The collapse theories tend to be of this variety, but their dynamical formulations to this day remain mathematically incomplete. Somewhat unfortunate is that the domain of physics concerned with critical phenomenon, of which the mathematical theory is very much a theory of principle, has become somewhat directly associated with condensed matter physics, which is itself a collection of constructive theories. This is unfortunate because the mathematical methods required by the theoreticians to derive these theories from first principles are precisely the mathematical methods taught to condensed matter physicists except in a very different context and with a completely different purpose.

  52. PeterDonis says:
    Stephen Tashi

    Parsing that definition seems to hinge on whether probabilities are "real".Sure, that's why I said we're dealing with vague ordinary language. I'm not trying to put a specific definition on the word "real". I'm just trying to say that, as far as I can tell, people who espouse Case 1 interpretations consider the quantum state to be like probabilities, and in common ordinary language usage probabilities do not describe the physically real state of anything; they just describe our knowledge (or the limitations thereof). If it helps, substitute "case 1 says the quantum state is like probabilities" for "case 1 says the quantum state is not real".

    Stephen Tashi

    In your definition, must a physically real state be sufficient to produce a deterministic outcome ?Case 2 interpretations of QM do not say a physically real state produces a deterministic outcome (that would contradict stan; they just say the quantum state is physically real. So I don't see how this helps to clarify anything relevant to this discussion.

    Stephen Tashi

    What aspect of that example is significant?Just what I said: case 2 interpretations treat the quantum state vector similarly to the way Newtonian physics treats the position 3-vector of a particle: it describes the physically real state of something.

    I think you're making this more difficult that it needs to be. I'm not trying to be abstruse.

  53. PeterDonis says:
    Stephen Tashi

    What I'm suggesting is that your give examples of the thesis of your article – that the two cases naturally divide the various interpretations- e.g. perhaps Case 2 leads to the Many Worlds or the Bohmian interpretation etc.Ah, ok. If you want a quick categorization of some common interpretations, here it is:

    Case 1: Copenhagen, ensemble

    Case 2: Many worlds, Bohmian*

    * – the Bohmian interpretation is kind of a special case, because it contains nonlocal hidden variables: the actual particle positions. The standard Bohmian interpretation considers these to be in principle unobservable, but it also considers the wave function–the "quantum potential"–to be real, which is why I put it in case 2.

    But one could easily envision an extended Bohmian interpretation in which they were observable. This would amount to a new theory extending QM and making testable predictions that could distinguish it from standard QM, which would take it out of the topic area discussed in the article. Similar remarks apply to things like the GRW model, which adds an additional "objective collapse" process that makes different testable predictions from standard QM.

  54. PeterDonis says:
    Fra

    I often feel that the descriptor "real", would be better replaced in these discussions with "objective", or observer invariant.Perhaps, but that would fail to acknowledge the fundamental difference in interpretations which was the main topic of the article. :wink: I think all interpretations agree that the quantum state/wave function is observer invariant; that's not where the difference lies.

  55. Stephen Tashi says:
    PeterDonis

    I thought cases 1 and 2 in the article already described that, but I'll give it another shot.What I'm suggesting is that your give examples of the thesis of your article – that the two cases naturally divide the various interpretations- e.g. perhaps Case 2 leads to the Many Worlds or the Bohmian interpretation etc.

    Case 1 says the state is not real; it's just a description of our knowledge of the system, in the same sense that, for example, saying that a coin has a 50-50 chance of coming up heads or tails describes our knowledge of the system–the coin itself isn't a 50-50 mixture of anything, nor is what happens when we flip it, it's just that we don't know–we can't predict–how it is going to land, we can only describe probabilities.Parsing that definition seems to hinge on whether probabilities are "real". In your definition, must a physically real state be sufficient to produce a deterministic outcome ?

    Case 2 says the state is real, in the same sense that, for example, a 3-vector describing the position of an object in Newtonian physics is real: it describes the actual position of the actual object.What aspect of that example is significant?

    One feature of that example is that if point particle_1 has the same 3-vector as point particle_2 then particle_1 and particle_2 are the same particle. By contrast, if we are only given that particle_1 and particle_2 are both in a laboratory in Texas then, from that description, the names might refer to different particles.

    Another aspect of that example is that we can measure the 3-vector associated with a particle. However, we could also determine whether a particle is in a laboratory in Texas, so the ability to measure the 3-vector seems not to be the outstanding feature of the example.

  56. Fra says:
    PeterDonis

    There is no precise definition of the term "physically real". That's part of what makes discussions of QM interpretations difficult: one is trying to go beyond the basic model of QM, which is expressed in math and has precise definitions, to interpretations that use ordinary language, where words do not have precise definitions.I often feel that the descriptor "real", would be better replaced in these discussions with "objective", or observer invariant.

    Thus real would mean, that different observers should arrive at a consistent descriptions of the same system. And then it begs the question of explaining how does one make this "consistency check"? This is a bit like trying to compare angles of vectors living at different tangent planes or so. You need some kind fo "parallell transport".

    As I see it, the consistency check is that the two systems making the inferences must physically interact/communicate. If they can do this without distorting the opinion of the other party, then they are consistent, and they have reached a consensus. And in many cases where there is an "apparent" disagreement, this is often identifed as an interaction term or force between the observers! And accounting for this, one can add some new interactions and recover a new elevated level of objectivity. This is also typically the situation that works fine in classical mechanics. And while we have observers also in classical mechanics, the fact that they typically easily reach a consensus of observations, is why the observations rarely are emphasised as of fundamental importance.

    So unless we can define the interaction that constitutes the consistency check, the notion of "real" is not only slightly ambigous, it seems too undefined to be recommended.

    /Fredrik

  57. Fra says:
    Dr. Courtney

    The only interesting cases are where differing interpretations make different testable predictions.This is also my position, and in particular to understand how the choice of interpretation"implies" a certain research direction in the open questions, or even WHICH the open question are, such as unification of interactions. Then if a certain interpretations shows to provide a more fruitful "angle" to making progress, then that would be my "preferred" interpretation.

    Lets note that this is a DIFFERENT selection strategy than those that think we need no modification to current theories, and that the preferred interpretation thus is some kind of "minimalist one". I fully agree that the minimalist selection principle makes sense if the interpretation served only the purposes of decreasing angst over understanding or not understanding the foundations..

    /Fredrik

  58. Dr. Courtney says:

    I focus more on predictions than "interpretations."

    One could have differing interpretations of Lagrangian, Hamiltonian, and Newtonian Mechanics (and I've met physicists who do argue one is right and the other two are "wrong"). However, all the predictions are the same.

    The only interesting cases are where differing interpretations make different testable predictions. This is real science. Then we can perform an experiment to distinguish between them.

  59. PeterDonis says:
    Stephen Tashi

    it would be helpful to have examples of how , in your opinion, different concepts of the reality of the wave function lead to well-known interpretations of QM.I thought cases 1 and 2 in the article already described that, but I'll give it another shot.

    Case 1 says the state is not real; it's just a description of our knowledge of the system, in the same sense that, for example, saying that a coin has a 50-50 chance of coming up heads or tails describes our knowledge of the system–the coin itself isn't a 50-50 mixture of anything, nor is what happens when we flip it, it's just that we don't know–we can't predict–how it is going to land, we can only describe probabilities.

    Case 2 says the state is real, in the same sense that, for example, a 3-vector describing the position of an object in Newtonian physics is real: it describes the actual position of the actual object.

  60. Stephen Tashi says:
    PeterDonis

    There is no precise definition of the term "physically real".True, but your article inherits an imprecise meaning directly from imprecision of "physically real". It would be unreasonable to expect any commentary on interpretations of QM to be free of all ambiguity, but in order to get the "general drift" of what you are saying it would be helpful to have examples of how , in your opinion, different concepts of the reality of the wave function lead to well-known interpretations of QM.

    Even if we cannot precisely define "physically real" to the extent of proposing a physical test for it or a mathematical definition, it may be possible to agree on certain properties of "physically real" things. For example, thinking in terms of mathematics, if I grant that X and Y are physically real aspects of something then should I also say that any function f(X,Y) is also physically real? One would suspect the answer is "No". A tricky mathematician would have us consider the constant function f(X,Y) = 13. So perhaps the mathematical property of a physically real f(X,Y) should be that we can reconstruct the values of X and Y given the value of f(X,Y) or , more generally that we can reconstruct the values of X and Y from a given value f(X,Y) and values of some other functions of X and Y.

    (Some people might want to add a third answer: the state describes an ensemble of a large number of similar systems, rather than a single system. For purposes of this discussion, I am considering this to be equivalent to answer #1, because the state does not describe the physically real state of a single system.)I don't understand that passage. For example, is the fact that a person is a resident of the state of Texas a physically real property of that person? Isn't belonging to the ensemble of Texans a real property of that single person? Would we define a physically real property of a person to be sufficient information to distinguish a unique person?

  61. Ian J Miller says:

    In my opinion, part of the reason there is such scope for interpretations is that nobody actually KNOWS what Ψ means. Either there is an actual wave of there is not, and here we have the first room for debate. If there is, how come nobody can find it, and if there is not, how come a stream of particles reproduce a diffraction pattern in the two slit experiment? No matter which option you try, somewhere there is a dead rat to swallow. As it happens, I have my own interpretation which differs from others in two ways after you assume there is an actual wave. The first, the phase exp(2πiS/h) becomes real when S = h (or h/2) – from Euler. This is why electrons pair in an energy well, despite repelling each other. Since it becomes real at the antinode, I add the premise that the expectation values of variables can be obtained there. The second is that if there is a wave, the wave front has to arrive at the two slits about the same time as the particle. If so, the wave must transmit energy (which waves generally do, but the dead rat here is where is this extra energy? However, it is better than Bohm's quantum potential because it has a specific value.) The Uncertainty Principle and Exclusion Principle follow readily, as does why the electron does not radiate its way to the nucleus. The value in this, from my point of view, is it makes the calculation of things like the chemical bond so much easier – the hydrogen molecule becomes almost mental arithmetic, although things get more complicated as the number of electrons increase. Nevertheless, the equations for Sb2 gave an energy within about 2 kJ/mol, which is not bad.

  62. PeterDonis says:
    lightarrow

    do you think that term, "physically real" refers only to physical quantities as position, momentum, spin components, etc, or even to something else?Please read what I said in the article: I said that viewpoint #2 says that the quantum state is "physically real". In other words, the wave function/state vector/whatever you want to call it, a particular well-defined thing in the math, represents something "physically real". The quantum state is not position, momentum, spin components, etc. It's the particular well-defined thing in the math.

  63. A. Neumaier says:
    eltodesukane

    What are the Interpretations of Classical Mechanics ?The book by Laurence Sklar, Physics and Chance, discusses the philosophy of classical mechanics. But the subject have fallen out of fashion since it is known that classical mechanics fails completely in the subatomic domain.

  64. lightarrow says:
    PeterDonis

    There is no precise definition of the term "physically real". That's part of what makes discussions of QM interpretations difficult: one is trying to go beyond the basic model of QM, which is expressed in math and has precise definitions, to interpretations that use ordinary language, where words do not have precise definitions.Ok, and do you think that term, "physically real" refers only to physical quantities as position, momentum, spin components, etc, or even to something else? For example could I pretend that "physically real" is the "setting of the experiment" if it's prepared in a specific and reproducible way?
    To which of the 2 "paradigms" you describes belongs this vision?
    Thanks.


    lightarrow

  65. microsansfil says:

    Hi,

    Nice article that shows a facet of epistemic (#1)/ontological (#2) duality. My understanding (and thus my point of view) is that the observer (humain being, measurements apparatus) interact with something that resist to us ("real in itself"), but can only capture the interaction effects and not the causes.

    To buid a rational and complet interpretation, it seems to me that we need to dissect how we construct our knowledge from the effects we capture and then we have to take in acount all the humain process from ours first-person experience up to ours objectifications. Moreover It could be relevant to be aware of our blind spot when we made ours objectivations/reifications.

    Best regards,
    Patrick

  66. PeterDonis says:
    lightarrow

    when you write "physically real", do you refer to which definition of it?There is no precise definition of the term "physically real". That's part of what makes discussions of QM interpretations difficult: one is trying to go beyond the basic model of QM, which is expressed in math and has precise definitions, to interpretations that use ordinary language, where words do not have precise definitions.

  67. Buzz Bloom says:

    Hi Peter:

    I very much like the clarity of the dichotomy you present.

    Sometimes I find myself comfortably accepting either of the two points of view at different times. The particular choice I make depends on my recognizing that the context makes one choice more convenient than the other. When I think about my practice of doing this, I interpret this as actually accepting both points of view at the same time, and when I do that I just ignore the apparent contradictions. I summarize this practice with the maxim:

    Reality is fundamentally paradoxical.​

    Regards,
    Buzz

Newer Comments »

Leave a Reply

Want to join the discussion?
Feel free to contribute!

Leave a Reply