classroom

Explore Some Sins in Physics Didactics

Estimated Read Time: 12 minute(s)
Common Topics: quantum, theory, wave, electromagnetic, energy

Introduction

There are many sins in physics didactics. Usually, they occur, because teachers, professors, textbook or popular-science-book writers, etc. try to simplify things more than possible without introducing errors in reasoning, or they copy old-fashioned methods of explaining an issue, leading to the necessity to “erase” from the students’ heads what was hammered in in a careless way before. Some examples are the introduction of a velocity-dependent mass in special relativity, which is a relic from the very early years after Einstein’s ground-breaking paper of 1905, or the use of Bohr’s atomic model as an introduction to quantum theory, which provides not only quantitatively but even qualitatively wrong pictures about how an atom is understood nowadays in terms of “modern quantum theory”. In this blog, I like to address some of the questionable cases of physics didactics. Of course, this is a quite subjective list of “sins”.

For each case, I’ll first give a rather non-technical review, which should be understandable by a high-school student. Then I’ll give a more technical description of the point of view of contemporary (theoretical) physics.

The photoelectric effect and the abuse of the notion of photons

Particularly seductive is quantum theory to the well-intentional teacher. This has several reasons. First of all, it deals with phenomena at atomic or even subatomic scales that are not within our daily experience, and this realm of the natural world can be described only on quite abstract levels of mathematical sophistication. So it is difficult to teach quantum theory in the correct way, particularly on an introductory level, let alone on a level understandable to laypeople.

In this article, I address readers who are already familiar with modern nonrelativistic quantum theory in terms of the Dirac notation.

Historical development

Often introductory texts on quantum theory start with a heuristic description of the photoelectric effect, inspired by Einstein’s famous paper on the subject (1905). There he describes the interaction of light with the electrons in a metallic plate as the scattering of “light particles”, which have an energy of ##E=\hbar \omega## and momentum##\vec{p}=\hbar \vec{k}##, where ##\hbar## is the modified Planck constant, ##\omega## the frequency of monochromatic light, and ##\vec{k}## the wave number.

To kick an electron out of the metal one needs to overcome its binding energy ##W##, and the conservation of energy thus implies that the kicked-out electrons have maximal energy of \begin{equation} \label{1} E=\hbar \omega-W, \end{equation} and this formula is often demonstrated by letting the photo-electrons run against an electric field, which just stops them, and measuring the corresponding stopping voltage as a function of the light’s frequency ##\omega## nicely confirms Einstein’s Law.

After Planck’s discovery and statistical explanation of the black-body-radiation law in 1900, this work of Einstein’s started the true quantum revolution. Planck’s derivation was already mind-puzzling enough because he realized that he had to assume that electromagnetic radiation of frequency ##\omega## can only be absorbed in energy portions of the size ##\hbar \omega##. In addition, he had to apply a pretty strange method to count the number of microstates for the given macroscopic situation of radiation at a fixed temperature in a cavity in order to use Boltzmann’s famous relation between the entropy and this number of microstates, which in fact was written down first by Planck himself in explicit terms: ##S=k_{\text{B}} \ln \Omega##, where ##\Omega## is the number of microstates.

Although already this was breaking with the classical picture, and Planck tried to “repair” this radical consequences of his own discovery till the very end of his long life, Einstein’s paper was much clearer about how deep this departure from the principles of classical physics indeed was. First of all Einstein (re)introduced the idea of a particle nature of light, which was abandoned pretty much earlier due to the findings of wavelike phenomena like interference effects as in Young’s famous double-slit experiment, demonstrating the refraction of light. Finally, Maxwell’s theory about electromagnetism revealed that light might be nothing else than waves of the electromagnetic field, and H. Hertz’s experimental demonstration of electromagnetic waves with the predicted properties, lead to the conviction that light indeed is an electromagnetic wave (in a certain range of wavelengths, the human eye is sensitive to).

Second, Einstein’s model (which he carefully dubbed a “heuristic point of view” in the title of the paper) introduced wave properties into the particle picture. Einstein was well aware that this “wave-particle duality” is not a very consistent description of what’s going on on the microscopic level of matter and its interaction with the electromagnetic field.

Nevertheless, the wave-particle duality of electromagnetic radiation was an important step towards the modern quantum theory. In his doctoral dissertation, L. de Broglie introduced the idea that wave-particle duality may be more general and may also apply to “particles” like the electron. For a while, it was not clear what the stuff in vacuum tubes might be, particles or some new kind of wave field, until in 1897 J. J. Thomson could measure that the corresponding entity indeed behaves like a gas of charged particles with a fixed charge-mass ratio by studying how it was moving in electro- and magnetostatic fields.

All these early attempts to find a consistent theory of the microcosm of atoms and their constituents were very important steps towards the modern quantum theory. Following the historical path, summarized above, the breakthrough came in 1926 with Schrödinger’s series of papers about “wave mechanics”. Particularly he wrote down a field-equation of motion for (nonrelativistic) electrons, and in one of his papers, he could solve it, using the famous textbook by Courant and Hilbert, for the stationary states (energy eigenstates) of an electron moving in the Coulomb field of the much heavier proton, leading to an eigenvalue problem for the energy levels of the hydrogen atom, which were pretty accurate, i.e., only lacking the fine structure, which then was thought to be a purely relativistic effect according to Sommerfeld’s generalization of Bohr’s quantum theory of the hydrogen atom.

Now the natural question was, what the physical meaning of Schrödinger’s wave function might be. Schrödinger himself had the idea that particles have in fact a wavy field-like nature and might be “smeared out” over finite regions of space rather than behaving like point-like bullets. On the other hand, this smearing was never observed. Free single electrons, hitting a photo plate, never gave a smeared-out pattern but always a point-like spot (within the resolution of the photo-plate, given by the size of the grains of silver salt, e.g., silver nitrate). This brought Born, applying Schrödinger’s wave equation to describe the scattering of particles in potential, to the conclusion that the square of the wave function’s modulus, ##|\psi(\vec{x})|^2##, gives the probability density to find an electron around the position ##\vec{x}##.

A bit earlier, Heisenberg, Born, and Jordan had found another “new quantum theory”, the “matrix mechanics”, where the matrices described transition probabilities for a particle changing from one state of definite energy to another. Heisenberg had found this scheme during a more or less involuntary holiday on the Island of Helgoland, where he moved from Göttingen to escape his hay-fever attacks, by analyzing the most simple case of the harmonic oscillator with the goal to use only observable quantities and not theoretical constructs like “trajectories” of electrons within an atom or within his harmonic-oscillator potential. Back home in Göttingen, Born quickly found out that Heisenberg had reinvented matrix algebra, and pretty rapidly he, Jordan, and Heisenberg wrote a systematic account of their new theory. Quickly Pauli could solve the hydrogen problem (also even before Schrödinger with his wave mechanics!) within the matrix mechanics.

After a quarter of a century of the struggle of the best theoretical physicists of their time to find a consistent model for the quantum behavior of microscopic particles, all of a sudden one had not only one but even two of such models. Schrödinger himself could show that both schemes were mathematically equivalent, and this was the more clear, because around the same time another young genius, Dirac, found another even more abstract mathematical scheme, the so-called “transformation theory”, by introducing non-commuting “quantum numbers” in addition to the usual complex “classical numbers”, which commute when multiplied. The final step for the complete mathematical resolution of this fascinating theory came with a work by von Neumann, who showed that states and observables can be described as vectors in an abstract infinite-dimensional vector space with a scalar product, a so-called Hilbert space (named after the famous mathematician) and so-called self-adjoint operators acting on these state vectors.

In the next section, we shall use this modern theory to show, what’s wrong with Einstein’s original picture and why it is a didactical sin to claim the photoelectric effect proves the quantization of the electromagnetic field and the existence of “light particles”, now dubbed photons.

Modern understanding of the photoelectric effect

Let us discuss the photoelectric effect in the most simple approximation, but in terms of modern quantum theory. From this modern point of view, the photoelectric effect is the induced transition of an electron from a bound state in the metal (or any other bound system, e.g., a single atom or molecule) to a scattering state in the continuous part of the energy spectrum. To describe induced transitions, in this case, the absorption of a photon by an atom, molecule, or solid, we do not need to quantize the electromagnetic field at all but a classical electromagnetic wave will do, which we shall prove now in some detail.

The bound electron has of course to be quantized, and we use the abstract Dirac formalism to describe it. We shall work in the interaction picture of time evolution throughout, with the full bound-state Hamiltonian, \begin{equation} \label{2} \hat{H}_0=\frac{\hat{\vec{p}}^2}{2 \mu}+V(\hat{\vec{x}}), \end{equation} which we have written in terms of an effective single-particle potential, leading to bound states ##|E_n,t \rangle##, where ##n## runs over a finite or countable infinite number (including possible degeneracies of the energy spectrum, which don’t play much of a role in our treatment) and a continuous part ##|E ,t\rangle## with ##E \geq 0##. It is important to note that in the interaction picture the eigenvectors of operators that represent observables are time dependent, evolving with the unperturbed Hamiltonian, which is time-independent in our case, according to \begin{equation} \label{2b} |o,t \rangle=\exp \left [\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} (t-t_0) \hat{H}_0 \right ] |o,t_0 \rangle. \end{equation} For the eigenvectors of the unperturbed Hamiltonian this implies \begin{equation} \label{2c} |E,t \rangle=\exp \left [\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} (t-t_0) E \right ]|E,t_0 \rangle. \end{equation} The operators which represent observables themselves move accordingly as \begin{equation} \label{2d} \hat{O}(t)=\exp \left [\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} (t-t_0) \hat{H}_0 \right ] \hat{O}(t_0) \exp \left [-\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} (t-t_0) \hat{H}_0 \right ]. \end{equation} The classical radiation field is for our purposes best described by an electromagnetic four-vector potential in the non-covariant radiation gauge, i.e., with \begin{equation} \label{3} A^0=0, \quad \vec{\nabla} \cdot \vec{A}=0. \end{equation} Then the electromagnetic field is given by \begin{equation} \label{4} \vec{E}=-\frac{1}{c} \partial_t \vec{A}, \quad \vec{B}=\vec{\nabla} \times \vec{A}. \end{equation} This field is coupled to the particle in the minimal way, i.e., by substitution of \begin{equation} \label{5} \hat{\vec{p}} \rightarrow \hat{\vec{p}}+\frac{e}{mc} \hat{\vec{A}} \quad \text{with} \quad \hat{\vec{A}}=\vec{A}(t,\hat{\vec{x}}) \end{equation} in (\ref{2}). For a usual light wave we can assume that the corresponding field is very small compared to the typical field the electron “feels” from the binding potential. Thus we can restrict ourselves to the leading linear order in the perturbation ##\vec{A}##. We can also assume that a typical electromagnetic wave has much larger wavelengths than the dimensions of the typical average volume the electron is bound to within the atom, i.e., we can take \begin{equation} \label{6} \hat{\vec{A}} \simeq \vec{A}(t)=\vec{A}_0 \cos(\omega t)=\frac{\vec{A}_0}{2} [\exp(\mathrm{i} \omega t)+\exp(-\mathrm{i} \omega t)]. \end{equation} Then ##\vec{A}## is a pure external c-number field and commutes with ##\hat{\vec{p}}##. To linear order the perturbation (“interaction”) Hamiltonian thus reads \begin{equation} \label{7} \hat{H}_{\text{I}}=\frac{e}{mc} \vec{A} \cdot \hat{\vec{p}}. \end{equation} Now in the interaction picture the equation of motion for the state vector of the electron reads \begin{equation} \label{8} \mathrm{i} \hbar \partial_t |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{H}_{\mathrm{I}} |\psi(t) \rangle. \end{equation} The formal solution is the time-ordered exponential [see any good textbook on quantum theory, e.g., J. J. Sakurai, Modern Quantum Mechanics, 2nd Edition, Addison Wesley (1994)], \begin{equation} \label{9} |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{C}(t,t_0) |\psi(t_0) \rangle, \quad \hat{C}(t,t_0) = \mathcal{T} \exp \left [-\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} \int_{t_0}^{t} \mathrm{d} t’ \hat{H}_{\text{I}}(t’) \right ]. \end{equation} In leading order the exponential reads \begin{equation} \label{10} \hat{C}(t,t_0) = 1-\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} \int_{t_0}^{t} \mathrm{d} t’ \hat{H}_{\text{I}}(t’). \end{equation} Now we want to evaluate the transition probability that the electron which is assumed to have been at time ##t_0## in a bound state ##|\psi(t_0) \rangle=|E_n \rangle## to be found in a scattering state ##|E \rangle##. The corresponding transition-probability amplitude is given by \begin{equation} \label{11} a_{fi}=\langle E,t_0|\hat{C}(t,t_0)|E_n \rangle = -\frac{\mathrm{i}}{\hbar} \int_{t_0}^t \mathrm{d} t’ \langle E|\hat{V}_{\mathrm{I}}(t’)|E_n,t_0 \rangle. \end{equation} For the matrix element, because of (\ref{7}), we only need \begin{equation} \label{12} \langle E,t_0|\hat{\vec{p}}(t’)|E_n,t_0 \rangle = \exp \left (\mathrm{i} \omega_{fi} t’ \right) \langle E,t_0|\hat{\vec{p}}(t_0)|E_n,t_0 \rangle, \end{equation} where we have used the time evolution (\ref{2d}) for the momentum operator and the abbreviation ##\omega_{fi}=[E-E_n]/\hbar##.

Plugging this into (\ref{11}) we find \begin{equation} \begin{split} \label{13} a_{fi} &=-\frac{\alpha}{2 \hbar} \left [\frac{\exp[\mathrm{i} (\omega_{fi}-\omega) (t-t_0)]-1}{\omega_{fi}-\omega}+ \frac{\exp[\mathrm{i} (\omega_{fi}+\omega) (t-t_0)]-1}{\omega_{fi}+\omega} \right] \\ &= -\frac{\mathrm{i} \alpha}{\hbar} \left [\exp[\mathrm{i} (\omega_{fi}-\omega)(t-t_0)/2] \frac{\sin[ (\omega_{fi}+\omega)(t-t_0)/2]}{\omega_{fi}-\omega} +(\omega \rightarrow -\omega) \right], \end{split} \end{equation} where \begin{equation} \label{13b} \alpha=\vec{A}_0 \cdot \langle E,t_0|\hat{\vec{p}}(t_0)|E,t_0 \rangle \end{equation}

Now we are interested in the probability that the electron is excited from a bound state with energy ##E_i##,
\begin{equation}
\label{14}
\begin{split} P_{fi} = |a_{fi}|^2 =& \frac{\alpha^2}{\hbar^2}\frac{\sin^2[(\omega_{fi}-\omega)(t-t_0)]}{(\omega_{fi}-\omega)^2} \\ & + \frac{\alpha^2}{\hbar^2} \frac{\sin^2[(\omega_{fi}+\omega)(t-t_0)]}{(\omega_{fi}+\omega)^2} \\ &+ \frac{2 \alpha^2}{\hbar^2} \cos(\omega t) \frac{\sin[(\omega_{fi}-\omega)(t-t_0)]}{\omega_{fi}- \omega}\frac{\sin[(\omega_{fi}+\omega)(t-t_0)]}{\omega_{fi}+ \omega}. \end{split} \end{equation} For ##t-t_0 \rightarrow \infty## we can use \begin{equation} \label{15} \frac{\sin[(t-t_0) x)}{x} \simeq \pi \delta(x), \quad \frac{\sin^2[(t-t_0) x]}{x^2} \simeq \pi (t-t_0)\delta(x). \end{equation} Thus, after a sufficiently long time the transition rate, becomes \begin{equation} \label{16} w_{fi} = \dot{P}_{fi} \simeq \frac{\alpha^2}{\hbar^2} \delta(\omega_{fi}-\omega). \end{equation} This shows that the transition is only possible, if \begin{equation} \label{17} \omega_{fi} = \omega \; \Rightarrow \; E=E_i+\hbar \omega. \end{equation} Now ##E_i=-W<0## is the binding energy of the electron in the initial state, i.e., before the light has been switched on. This explains, from a modern point of view, Einstein’s result (\ref{1}) of 1905, however without invoking any assumption about “light particles” or photons.

We note that the same arguments, starting from Eq. (18), hold for ##\omega_{fi}<0## and ##\omega=-\omega_{fi}##. Then one has \begin{equation} \label{18} E_f=E_i-\hbar \omega, \end{equation} which describes the transfer of an energy ##\hbar \omega## from the electron to the radiation field due to the presence of this radiation field. This is called stimulated emission. Again, we do not need to invoke any assumption about a particle nature of light.

Where this feature truly comes into the argument can be inferred from a later work by Einstein (1917): One can derive Planck’s black-body-radiation formula (1900) only under the assumption that despite the absorption and stimulated emission of energy quanta ##\hbar \omega## of the electromagnetic field, there is also a spontaneous emission, and from a modern point of view, this can indeed only be explained from the quantization of the electromagnetic field (in addition to the quantization of the electron). Then indeed, for the free quantized electromagnetic field, there is a particle-like interpretation, leading to a consistent picture of the electromagnetic field, interacting with charged particles, Quantum Electrodynamics.

Interesting reading:
http://arxiv.org/abs/1309.7070
http://arxiv.org/abs/1203.1139

 

Read my next article: https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/relativistic-treatment-of-the-dc-conducting-straight-wire/

203 replies
« Older Comments
  1. Feeble Wonk says:

    “For the QM bit – Ballentine – Quantum Mechanics – A Modern Development.

    For Classical Mechanics – Landau – Mechanics.

    Be amazed at the rock bottom of what a lot of physics is about – symmetry.

    Thanks
    Bill”

    Leon Lederman’s book “Symmetry and the Beautiful Universe” makes your point (symmetry being at the foundation of most physical concepts) very well. It’s far less mathematically demanding than the other sources you’ve offered… which, of course, is why I was better able to understand what he was saying. It also gave me a much greater appreciation for the work of Emmy Noether.

  2. bhobba says:

    “Nice post together with the comprehensive mathematical treatment. Although I am a physics graduate I am having hard time grasping the mathematical part since my quantum mechanics and classical mechanics are a bit rusty. What should I particularly revise to get this?”

    For the QM bit – Ballentine – Quantum Mechanics – A Modern Development.

    For Classical Mechanics – Landau – Mechanics.

    Be amazed at the rock bottom of what a lot of physics is about – symmetry.

    Thanks
    Bill

  3. atyy says:

    “Also, we are not creating robots – hands and feet are irrelevant for an automatic mathematician.”

    But doesn’t it need to hoard chalk to be a real mathematician? :biggrin:

    [URL]http://gizmodo.com/why-mathematicians-are-hoarding-this-special-type-of-ja-1711008881?utm_source=digg&utm_medium=email[/URL]

  4. A. Neumaier says:

    “We should see what A. Neumaier is using in his robots :biggrin:”
    Neither paradox nor magic; everything is nicely decidable or remains undecided. Just a large and detailed semantic memory together with algorithms to automatically expand it with new, useful content, with heuristics to decide what falls under this category – to avoid learning didactical sins, and with heuristics to clean up older information – to unlearn what turned out to be a didactical sin. The heuristics are derived from heuristics of the sort professional mathematicians use. The implementation is at the very beginning – it is a lot of work already to impart to a computer program the implicit knowledge needed to read a single math textbook sentence. Also, we are not creating robots – hands and feet are irrelevant for an automatic mathematician.

  5. Ken G says:

    “I think the lines and points are not real, only the correspondence between reality and syntax.[/quote]I agree, indeed I feel what you mean by “reality” here is what I mean by “meaning” or “semantics” when applied to the syntax of objective perceptions. So I would say what meaning we can give to what is real is whatever correspondence we can find between semantics (by which I mean the syntax of a metalanguage we create to talk about reality), and the syntax of objective perceptions. Then we also have the syntax of our physics theory, which can serve as a kind of simplified replacement for the syntax of the objective perceptions. Testing the connections between those three syntaxes is what we call science. Since the testing process itself requires another model to say when a test has been passed, we need another model of the scientific process itself, and when we want to know what that means, we need another model, so we find that it is models all the way up. Each model has a metalanguage syntax that supplies meaning to the model below it, but requires its own model to supply meaning to it. Usually we imagine the models are going downward, from rocks to atoms to quantum fields, etc., but it seems to me the models go up also, because a syntactic manipulation of a model that gives us a sense of meaning, which we then call an interpretation, is like an “upward” model rather than a downward one– when we interpret quantum mechanics we “lift” the formal QM syntax up into a more everyday language, one capable of attributing meaning, but that lifting is not unique. Each such lifting can then spawn its own downward set of models, so the interpretation process can be used to find new paths to new theories. All we mean by “reality” is the meaning we attribute to our models, i.e., the “upward” modeling process, but what is meant by SUACAM is always looking downward, considering only the syntax of the theory and the syntax of the objective perceptions, never the metalanguage syntax that provides semantic meaning to either. The sense of understanding we get is from that upward modeling process, so from the interpretations we find– not from simply finding a successful simplification from the syntax of obective perceptions to the syntax of some theory. That’s my issue with SUAMAC, and is the reason I claim no physicists (or physics thinkers like yourself) actually do that.
    [quote] Also, does “Skolem’s paradox” have any relevance here? [URL=’https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Skolem%27s_paradox’]https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Skolem’s_paradox[/URL][/quote]As I understand that paradox, it says that we can use a symantic system to prove the existence of things that our model of the semantic system cannot give any meaning to. So it is in some sense the opposite of the Goedel proof, as Goedel showed that truth-by-meaning can extend beyond truth-by-proving, but here we have that truth-by-proving can extend beyond truth-by-meaning. I guess the bottom line is that what we regard as true, and what we can prove are true, are just not the same things in many important situations.
    [quote]
    Or can we escape it by using second-order logic? [URL]http://lesswrong.com/lw/g7n/secondorder_logic_the_controversy/[/URL][/quote]That’s a remarkable blog entry, hard to follow but it seems to make the case that first-order logic, first-order set theory, and second-order logic, form a sequence of increasing proving power but also increasing uneasiness around their soundness. It seems mathematicians are free to choose their own personal comfort level in how far down that rabbit hole they wish to go!
    “We should see what A. Neumaier is using in his robots :biggrin:”Indeed!

  6. julcab12 says:

    “A simple introduction is perhaps [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/%7Eneum/ms/optslides.pdf’]Optical models for quantum mechanics[/URL].
    .”

    Just a question that has been bugging me for a while. Under pg 19. 3. “Traditional quantum mechanics does not answer this. But it provides formulas for the computation of the mean position hqi and the mean momentum hpi of each quantum object which can be prepared as an individual . . . . . . provided that one assigns a state to each individual object. Those strictly adhering to a statistical interpretation may find this a forbidden use. But how else shall we encode into quantum mechanics the knowledge that, at a particular time, a particular object is at a particular place in the experimental setup?”

    Would it be possible to have like a quadruple, any lensing type effect on microscale or a field that has that effect?. [ATTACH=full]84814[/ATTACH]

    The black circle is a particle and x is the true position of a particle(assuming) and four x’s are the location of the projection or critical points. Sorry for the crappy illustration.

  7. A. Neumaier says:

    Saying much more here on the thermal interpretation would go too far from the topic here – ”didactic sins”. Could you perhaps open a new thread, and cut down your answer her to a link to there? Then I’ll answer in the new thread.

  8. Jimster41 says:

    “Almost every nonlinear deterministic system is chaotic, in a precise mathematical sense of ”almost” and ”chaotic”. It ultimately comes from the fact that already for the simplest differential equation ##dot x = ax## with ##a>0##, the result at time ##tgg 0## depends very sensitively on the initial value at time zero, together with the fact that nonlinearities scramble up things. Look up the [URL=’https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Baker%27s_map’]baker’s map[/URL] if this is new to you.”

    P32 of your lecture.
    “Thus the QED photon is a global state of the whole space, a time-dependent solution of the Maxwell equation. It acts as a carrier of photon particles, which are extended but localized lumps of energy moving with the speed of light along the beam defined by a QED photon state. It is interesting to note that Colosi & Rovelli 2006 arrived at a similar conclusion from a completely different perspective. They argue from quantum general relativity, starting with the Unruh effect.”

    So the global state of the whole (H space of states) spans what space-times? I am trying to connect this notion to the AdS/CFT correspondence, where entanglement seems important. Your perspective is that “entanglement” is captured by this “global” field state. Does that global EM field state “do” anything to relate space-like separated space-times, or is it totally irrelevant? I am reading you as saying, “yes, of course it does”. But I’m not exactly sure what you are saying it does. What does it mean for a global EM field state to connect space-like points?

    I am totally intrigued by the connection you are pointing to with the Unruh Effect. This makes me think there is some synergy or reconciliation between your theory and those theories of quantum GR.

    I hear “determinism” wrong often because of the way deterministic chaotic dynamics are and are not the same as “randomness” and “unpredictability”. I totally buy the local deterministic dynamics leading to chaotic unpredictable outcomes (baker’s map). It’s confusing to me at the level of detail, why nature should be model-able in this simultaneously recursive and diffusive way. And I’m confused as to whether or not the idea of non-locality is involved. Trying to understand your take on that. Also, the chaotic dynamics as related to periodic structure, or “self-similarity” in chaotic systems seems relevant to this problem. Nature is clearly not just a stirring process, but rather a strange mixture of stirring and self-organization, right?

    Note this conversation does seem to connect to Prof N’s Insights article on Causal Peturbation theroy and discussion of the same, so I hope I don’t get in trouble for careless thread logistics.

  9. harrylin says:

    “All hidden variable theory arguments I have seen – without exception – assume a particle picture; they become vacuous for fields. Indeed, already the simplest deterministic fields – plane waves – behave precisely the nonlocal way that is responsible for Bell’s theorem. This is the reason I don’t discuss the latter in my book. [/quote]
    It would be nice (understatement of the year perhaps) if one could demonstrate by means of a simulation, even with a “toy model”, that a field model can produce the results that with particle models look like “spooky action at a distance”.

    For example, just now I found a paper of a few years ago by Matzkin, [URL]http://arxiv.org/abs/0808.2420v2[/URL]. At first sight the there presented model looks like a hidden variables model (but using field theory), and it looks simple enough to be tested with numerical simulations. Regretfully it appears that that paper has not been reviewed.
    [quote] [..]But I had written a paper on Bell inequalities [URL=’http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0303047′]quant-ph/0303047 [/URL]= Int. J. Mod. Phys. B 17 (2003), 2937-2980, which is in fact the (at that time still embryonic) origin of my thermal interpretation. I also discuss this stuff in my lecture on [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/ms/lightslides.pdf’]Classical and quantum field aspects of light[/URL] and in my paper [URL=’http://arxiv.org/abs/0706.0155′]A simple hidden variable experiment[/URL], though without direct reference to my thermal interpretation.[..][/quote]
    Thanks :smile:

  10. A. Neumaier says:

    “One stumbling block is that Arnold’s book does not discuss Bell’s theorem nor its cousins, so all the standard objections about hidden variables flood into my mind when I hear an interpretation that sounds deterministic.”

    All arguments I have seen against hidden variable theories – without exception – assume a particle picture; they become vacuous for fields.

    Indeed, already the simplest deterministic fields – plane waves – behave precisely the nonlocal way that is responsible for Bell’s theorem. This is the reason I don’t discuss the latter in my book. For my book is supposed to be free of all weird quantum stuff (that is weird only because of an inappropriate interpretation of the phenomena) – without didactical sins in the sense of the present thread.

    But I had written a paper on Bell inequalities [URL=’http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0303047′]quant-ph/0303047 [/URL]= Int. J. Mod. Phys. B 17 (2003), 2937-2980, which is in fact the (at that time still embryonic) origin of my thermal interpretation. I also discuss this stuff in my lecture on [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/ms/lightslides.pdf’]Classical and quantum field aspects of light[/URL] and in my paper [URL=’http://arxiv.org/abs/0706.0155′]A simple hidden variable experiment[/URL], though without direct reference to my thermal interpretation.

    It follows that quantum field theory is not affected by the extended literature on hidden variables.
    (Further discussion of this please in [URL=’https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/clarifying-the-meaning-of-random-in-quantum-physics.819719/#post-5145374′]this thread on randomness[/URL].)

    The problems of few particle detection arise because their traditional treatment idealizes the detector (a complex quantum field system) to a simple classical object with a discrete random response to very low intensity field input. It is like measuring the volume of a hydrodynamic system (a little pond) in terms of the number of buckets you need to empty the pond – it will invariably result in integral results unless you model the measuring device (the bucket) in sufficient detail to get a continuously defined response.

    Maybe this will act as a dam against the metaphysical flood.

  11. A. Neumaier says:

    “Where does the “inherent chaoticity of the kinetic, hydrodynamic, and elasticity equations for macroscopic matter” come from?” Almost every nonlinear deterministic system is chaotic, in a precise mathematical sense of ”almost” and ”chaotic”. It ultimately comes from the fact that already for the simplest differential equation ##dot x = ax## with ##a>0##, the result at time ##tgg 0## depends very sensitively on the initial value at time zero, together with the fact that nonlinearities scramble up things. Look up the [URL=’https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Baker%27s_map’]baker’s map[/URL] if this is new to you.

  12. strangerep says:

    “[…] Maybe Mr. Neumaier has something that is already written up that outlines his research, on the level of Scientific American?” The book is more detailed than anything else I’ve seen.

    BTW, I think you mean “O. Univ-Prof. Dr. Neumaier”, not “Mr. ….” :-)

  13. Jimster41 says:

    “One can repeat the experiment many times only for microscopic systems, since the assumptions underlying the statistical interpretation is that one can prepare a system independently and identically many times. It is impossible to do this for a macroscopic system, let alone for a quantum field that extends from the earth to the sun.

    Yes, in QFT everything is deterministic; God doesn’t play dice since he world was created according to a QFT. The randomness is in the inability to reproduce identical quantum conditions for a macroscopic system, together with the inherent chaoticity of the kinetic, hydrodynamic and elasticity equations for macroscopic matter.

    For the system under discussion in the main part of this thread, it is the randomness in the photodetector that is responsible for the indeterminism.”

    Really enjoying this thread.

    Where does the “inherent chaoticity of the kinetic, hydrodynamic, and elasticity equations for macroscopic matter” come from? If they macroscopic objects are composed of quanta which behave according to determinism even if their behavior is unpredictable there must be some cause?

  14. atyy says:

    “If you hold that to be true, then it is natural to be a SUACAM type. I would say there is an important difference, which is those who wish to have a deep understanding of physics, versus those content to simply use the benefits of physics– like someone who wants to understand electrodynamics, versus someone who just wants to use an i-phone. Note the distinction I draw there is not between practicing physicists and armchair physicists, it is between those who gain some degree of understanding from the theories, and those who are content that algorithms exist to predict outcomes. SUACAM should be happy with algorithms, but physicists generally are not– even those who claim to be SUACAM types!”

    Let’s say we do Euclidean geometry. Then (under some circumstances) lines and points are dual. Then there are also real lines and real points. Since lines and points are dual, the real line can modelled as a mathematical point. So what is real? I think the lines and points are not real, only the correspondence between reality and syntax.

    Also, does “Skolem’s paradox” have any relevance here? [URL]https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Skolem%27s_paradox[/URL]

    Or can we escape it by using second-order logic? [URL]http://lesswrong.com/lw/g7n/secondorder_logic_the_controversy/[/URL]

    We should see what A. Neumaier is using in his robots :biggrin:

  15. atyy says:

    “If you hold that to be true, then it is natural to be a SUACAM type. I would say there is an important difference, which is those who wish to have a deep understanding of physics, versus those content to simply use the benefits of physics– like someone who wants to understand electrodynamics, versus someone who just wants to use an i-phone. Note the distinction I draw there is not between practicing physicists and armchair physicists, it is between those who gain some degree of understanding from the theories, and those who are content that algorithms exist to predict outcomes. SUACAM should be happy with algorithms, but physicists generally are not– even those who claim to be SUACAM types!”

    Well, but if this non-physicist believes that electric fields and spacetime etc really exist in reality (not as a mathematical model), then he will be indistinguishable from the physicist who has reality, mathematical model and syntax.

  16. Ken G says:

    “There is no difference between a physicist and a non-physicist. [/quote]If you hold that to be true, then it is natural to be a SUACAM type. I would say there is an important difference, which is those who wish to have a deep understanding of physics, versus those content to simply use the benefits of physics– like someone who wants to understand electrodynamics, versus someone who just wants to use an i-phone. Note the distinction I draw there is not between practicing physicists and armchair physicists, it is between those who gain some degree of understanding from the theories, and those who are content that algorithms exist to predict outcomes. SUACAM should be happy with algorithms, but physicists generally are not– even those who claim to be SUACAM types!
    [quote]There are only differences between platonist and non-platonists. For example, take the tribe or whatever that counts 1,2,3, infinity. Are we any different? Has any computer counted to infinity, or is all of science consistent with manipulation of finite strings? Only people like Goedel who believe in the natural numbers are different.[/quote]I agree that SUACAM types would be less likely to be platonists, but even non-platonic physicists generally seek a level of understanding of what they are doing, and are not content with purely syntactic algorithms for predicting outcomes. There are no “didactic sins” at all if our only goal is syntactic success, indeed we have no need to explain anything other than what equation to use and how to solve it. It’s certainly true that physics starts with this, we have to teach people what equations to use when, how to solve them, and how to set up the experiments that test them. But it rarely ends there– physics pedagogy almost always goes beyond the rules of what equations to use and how to solve them, and experimental acumen almost always goes beyond how to set up the experiment. Physics pedagogy attempts to inspire a deeper understanding, which will guide thinking toward the next theory by looking at essentially the philosophy of the current set of equations, and experimental acumen attempts to inspire what new experiments to try and what would be the most insightful way to get nature to reveal some new secret. These elements underpin SUACAM, they make it work better and produce a more satisfying result, though they come at the cost of producing some variance of opinion (as any forum can attest!). Vive la difference, it promotes varied pathways of exploration.
    [quote]
    Bohmian mechanics has a cut, and Copenhagen has a cut. It just depends on how accurate one thinks that map is. [/quote]Yet to even assert this is to go beyond SUACAM, because in SUACAM, there are no cuts, there is only the syntax of the testable predictions, and that syntax is the same in Bohm, Bohr, or Everett. Maybe that won’t always be true, as our technology allows us access to new tests, but when that’s no longer true, then those will be separate theories rather than separate interpretations of the same theory. Hence what I am saying boils down to the reasons that we have interpretations of our theories in the first place– it’s not that we need to marry one interpretation or another, it’s that we like to have them at all. But SUACAM never includes them, as they violate the “SU” part.

    Let me pose that differently. Imagine you had access to an i-phone app that would allow you to input any experimental apparatus, and the app would output the result of the experiment. Would you then consider yourself empowered to be the greatest physicist ever, based on the complete mastery of the SUACAM approach you now have? We could call it the “nature app”. But in a sense physics begins with the nature app, it doesn’t end there, because nature will already provide us with the syntactic output of any experiment we can set up. What we want from physics is more than that– we also want a semantic content, a kind of lesson extracted from a theory that can provide an insightful shortcut to the output of the “nature app.” Without that, we don’t really have anything we can call physics, we just have a more convenient means for asking nature questions.

    [quote] A really accurate map should contain a tiny version of itself in the map which contains a tiny version of the map in itself etc. Bohmian mechanics is the belief that our map should at least contain a tiny version of ourselves.”That sounds both profound and impossible at the same time!

  17. A. Neumaier says:

    “Maybe Mr. Neumaier has something that is already written up that outlines his research, on the level of Scientific American?” A simple introduction is perhaps [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/%7Eneum/ms/optslides.pdf’]Optical models for quantum mechanics[/URL].

    Starting from the discovery that everything known today about a single qubit was already known to Stokes in 1852 in completely deterministic terms, long before the advent of quantum mechanics, I go on to discussing elements of my thermal interpretation.

  18. A. Neumaier says:

    “Good for you, if you can SEE mathematics or SEE the mathematical representation of the electron.” I am a mathematician. As one can easily infer (”see”) by looking at typical mathematics textbooks and articles, mathematicians SEE everything they understand! And (except for strict Bourbakists) it is all about forming the right mental pictures. No constructions but Anschauung.

  19. A. Neumaier says:

    “They would have been good lectures I’m sure. Have you given any talks that were recorded on this material, maybe time for one?” This term I am giving a course on quantum mechanics for mathematicians, but again not recorded; sorry.

  20. atyy says:

    “That part is true of non-scientists– they “have” those things too. I’m saying that if all these things are to us is a syntactic algorithm for predicting experimental outcomes, then we have no closer connection to the physics than a non-physicist does. Where in SUACAM does it matter if it is our minds that are involved in that process, or someone else’s?”

    There is no difference between a physicist and a non-physicist. There are only differences between platonist and non-platonists. For example, take the tribe or whatever that counts 1,2,3, infinity. Are we any different? Has any computer counted to infinity, or is all of science consistent with manipulation of finite strings? Only people like Goedel who believe in the natural numbers are different.

    Bohmian mechanics has a cut, and Copenhagen has a cut. It just depends on how accurate one thinks that map is. A really accurate map should contain a tiny version of itself in the map which contains a tiny version of the map in itself etc. Bohmian mechanics is the belief that our map should at least contain a tiny version of ourselves.

  21. Ken G says:

    “I don’t understand, what you mean. It’s the very foundation of the scientific method to have a model (or even a theory) of (or a certain part of) nature, leading to quantitative predictions for the outcome of experiments. [/quote]That part is true of non-scientists– they “have” those things too. I’m saying that if all these things are to us is a syntactic algorithm for predicting experimental outcomes, then we have no closer connection to the physics than a non-physicist does. Where in SUACAM does it matter if it is our minds that are involved in that process, or someone else’s?
    [quote]Then you plan your experiment to check whether the prediction is right.[/quote]And that is neither calculating nor measuring, it requires some idea of what you wish to test. What part of the theory bothers you? Where is your doubt centered? These are crucial issues in science, but do not represent “shutting up”, they represent a discussion about what our goals are for our science, and where we regard the key payoffs. One particular example of this is when Poincare and Lorentz were trying to understand the Lorentz transform in terms of physical effects happening to rulers and clocks, causing them to seek experiments that could identify what that physical effect was, and then Einstein came along and said just make the speed of light a fundamental law and remove any need to find a physical effect on rulers and clocks. The experimental question shifted from seeking evidence for some physical effect, to simply testing the predictions of asserting that the speed of light is a law. Or another example, also involving Einstein, was the EPR paradox, where Einstein felt quantum mechanics was making absurd predictions, motivating experiments to test those predictions, leading to Bell’s theorem.

    These advances were the targets of specific thinking about laws, not just in terms of what calculations they allow, but also in terms of what they mean. Thinking about the deBroglie-Bohm versus the Copenhagen interpretation might also motivate new experiments, just as it motivated experiments on watching decoherence occur, or weak measurements. It seems to me the physicist is always up to his/her ears in their own interpretation of what these laws mean, this is central to not only the pedagogy of physics (which is nonunique), but also the motivations for what direction to take future tests (which is also nonunique).
    [quote] Either it is, and you haven’t learnt anything new or there is a discrepancy, and you have to refine your model, leading to new predictions and new experiments to check them. Science is a process, and I’m not sure, whether this will ever stop culminating in a final “theory of everything”.”I completely agree there, I’m just saying that the process is something more than SUACAM. If it weren’t, it shouldn’t matter to us who is doing the calculating and measuring, as long as we are privy to the outcomes. But we want to be privy to more than the theories and the observations that test them, we want to be privy to some kind of sense of what it all means, something we could call understanding that goes deeper than being able to make successful predictions using a syntactic algorithm. This will be a more personal connection, and will be non-unique, but is relevant to what we would regard is a “didactic sin” and what isn’t.

  22. Jimster41 says:

    “Yes, that’s the point of the article. Einstein’s famous formula is entirely derived from a model, where light is described by a classical em. wave, not by the quantum field. At Einstein’s time the only observable fact that makes the quantized field necessary is the Planck radiation law, contradicting the classical equipartition theorem, leading to the UV catastrophy of the older theories of black-body radition.

    The electron is “quantized”, because a bound state belongs, by definition, to the descrete spectrum of the Hamilton operator. E.g., you can take a hydrogen atom as a simple but very important example, which can be solved exactly (neglecting radiation corrections, for which you also need the quantization of the em. field leading to the Lamb shift, which can be calculated very accurately using perturbation theory).”

    Just two other questions:
    Lamb Shift was unknown at the time?

    Does the whole specific point here translate If talking about scattering probability amplitudes of say bound neutrons or protons, bombarded with the EM field, but using “electrons”. In other words it’s the free vs. bound that matters, not the energy scales or forces involved. IOW the point is general; you don’t have to posit quantization of the free field (?) a-priori to get quantized probability amplitudes for outcomes when that wave interacts with a bound system, which is by definition quantized?

  23. vanhees71 says:


    But then you realize you have exactly the same relationship to that system as non-scientists have with our current system. You have turned yourself into a non-physicist, in the name of doing SUACAM as efficiently as possible. So there has to be something more than SUACAM in physics!”
    I don’t understand, what you mean. It’s the very foundation of the scientific method to have a model (or even a theory) of (or a certain part of) nature, leading to quantitative predictions for the outcome of experiments. Then you plan your experiment to check whether the prediction is right. Either it is, and you haven’t learnt anything new or there is a discrepancy, and you have to refine your model, leading to new predictions and new experiments to check them. Science is a process, and I’m not sure, whether this will ever stop culminating in a final “theory of everything”.

  24. vanhees71 says:

    Yes, that’s the point of the article. Einstein’s famous formula is entirely derived from a model, where light is described by a classical em. wave, not by the quantum field. At Einstein’s time the only observable fact that makes the quantized field necessary is the Planck radiation law, contradicting the classical equipartition theorem, leading to the UV catastrophy of the older theories of black-body radition.

    The electron is “quantized”, because a bound state belongs, by definition, to the descrete spectrum of the Hamilton operator. E.g., you can take a hydrogen atom as a simple but very important example, which can be solved exactly (neglecting radiation corrections, for which you also need the quantization of the em. field leading to the Lamb shift, which can be calculated very accurately using perturbation theory).

  25. Jimster41 says:

    I think I know the answer but why is the bound electron quantized as a matter of course?

    Is the point of the article that the discrete scattering probability of the quantized bound electron when bombarded with light (EM radiation) can be explained without also a-priori quantization of that radiation into “photons”?

  26. Ken G says:

    “I’d rather call it SUACM=Shut up, calculate, and measure! That, closed to a circle, is physics ;-).”
    Ah, but I never knew a physicist who really did that. It sounds too much like the “messenger” I alluded to above– imagine there really was an “Einstein” program that took all the available data and used it to test a search protocol of various theories, ordered by complexity. The program throws out theories that fail, and adjusts the parameters of theories that succeed, and then outputs new experimental tests that are needed to push the theories into new domains. Then you the physicist set up the experiments that the Einstein program suggests, and report the outcomes to the program, which further culls its theories and suggests new tests. Progress in physics rapidly accelerates, as the program is capable of searching a vast space of possibilities very quickly.

    Then you decide to further increase efficiency by creating a “Faraday” program that takes the Einstein outputs directly and assembles robotic experiments per the Einstein requirements, and feeds the outcomes right back into the Einstein code. You the physicist just sit back and watch the outcome, which is a set of theoretical equations and models ordered in regard to complexity and accuracy. After awhile you find the equations and models have become too difficult for you to understand what they are saying, so you create a “Scientific American” program to create pedagogical explanations of the Einstein outputs, in some sense “dumbed down” to translate it from the syntactic machine language to a semantic human language, but without the deeper understanding necessary to come up with the theory in the first place because it is actually derived in a different language. You sit back with great pride in your accoplishment– a fully automated SUACAM system!

    But then you realize you have exactly the same relationship to that system as non-scientists have with our current system. You have turned yourself into a non-physicist, in the name of doing SUACAM as efficiently as possible. So there has to be something more than SUACAM in physics!

  27. samalkhaiat says:

    “… Which mental picture we form is a different matter – samalkhaiat probably cannot form a mental picture of the mind, as mind is as unobservable as the electron (we cannot see, hear, feel, smell or taste it), but we other mortals have our own mental pictures of it, which may or may not differ a lot from the scientific picture based on the physics we know.

    You are entitled to your opinions. Samalkhaiat, like almost everybody else, distinguishes between mental picturing from mental construction. Mathematics and mathematical models are abstract mental constructions which we (i.e. our brains) can not provide spatial or/and temporal pictures of them. :smile:Good for you, if you can SEE mathematics or SEE the mathematical representation of the electron.

  28. Spinnor says:

    “I still fail to grok Arnold’s interpretation of QM.”

    As you are no dummy I’m sure I will have even more trouble. Maybe Mr. Neumaier has something that is already written up that outlines his research, on the level of Scientific American?

  29. strangerep says:

    “I look forward to going through [Arnold’s] book, ” Good luck. I have been through many drafts of it, (mostly learning less well known ways of applying math to physics along the way). Although I have learned many things in the process I must admit that I still fail to grok Arnold’s interpretation of QM. One stumbling block is that Arnold’s book does not discuss Bell’s theorem nor its cousins, so all the standard objections about hidden variables flood into my mind when I hear an interpretation that sounds deterministic. Thus I retreat away from philosophy to the comparative safety of minimal SUAC. :wink:

  30. Spinnor says:

    “I have no recordings; sorry. But (since discussion of unpublished research is discouragaged here on PF) you are welcome to [URL=’http://www.physicsoverflow.org/’]ask questions regarding the content here[/URL], if they are significant, while comments on typos, suggestions for improvement, etc. are best sent to me by email (collecting them for a while before sending them).”

    They would have been good lectures I’m sure. Have you given any talks that were recorded on this material, maybe time for one?

    Thanks!

  31. TrickyDicky says:


    The controversy in this thread is about what ”proper thinking” about quantum mechanics entails. I found that I had to unlearn quite a lot to reach my present understanding; a better start than what the textbooks tell could have saved me a lot of work. On the other hand, one has to be careful what to throw away.

    Yes, stumbling upon the right starting point is essential..

  32. A. Neumaier says:

    “Do you by chance have video or audio recordings of your lectures that you would share?”
    I have no recordings; sorry. But (since discussion of unpublished research is discouragaged here on PF) you are welcome to [URL=’http://www.physicsoverflow.org/’]ask questions regarding the content here[/URL], if they are significant, while comments on typos, suggestions for improvement, etc. are best sent to me by email (collecting them for a while before sending them).

  33. Spinnor says:

    “I had already given a link in my answer; following it you’ll enter a new world view. Nothing is published, though – it saves me a lot of time not to prepare every insight for publication. I am collecting the material for a book. A [URL=’http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/0810.1019′]preliminary version of my book is here[/URL] – Chapters 8-10 make the case for my interpretation (though to be more elementary I avoid there to talk about quantum fields). According to my publishing contract, the final version of the book should be published in about two years from now.”

    I look forward to going through your book, thanks! From the preface of your book,

    “The book originated as course notes from a course given by the first author in fall 2007, …”

    Do you by chance have video or audio recordings of your lectures that you would share?

  34. Ken G says:

    “I had already given a link in my answer; following it you’ll enter a new world view. Nothing is published, though – it saves me a lot of time not to prepare every insight for publication. I am collecting the material for a book. A [URL=’http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/0810.1019′]preliminary version of my book is here[/URL] – Chapters 8-10 make the case for my interpretation (though to be more elementary I avoid there to talk about quantum fields). [/quote]It is certainly a splendid accomplishment!

  35. A. Neumaier says:

    ” Are there any references where I could read the details?” I had already given a link in my answer; following it you’ll enter a new world view. Nothing is published, though – it saves me a lot of time not to prepare every insight for publication. I am collecting the material for a book. A [URL=’http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/0810.1019′]preliminary version of my book is here[/URL] – Chapters 8-10 make the case for my interpretation (though to be more elementary I avoid there to talk about quantum fields). According to my publishing contract, the final version of the book should be published in about two years from now.

    “non-relativistic QFT would also have a deterministic interpretation consistent with observable non-relativistic physics”

    Yes, it has; nothing in my arguments depends on relativity – it doesn’t even depend on fields; just on being macroscopic. Neglecting most of the particles to get a tiny quantum system is the source of the randomness when observing a tiny system; as the system gets bigger, the noise mostly cancels out if you look only at the macroscopic variables. These macroscopic variables happen to be fields – but my book only treats the equilibrium case where the fields have constant values.

    One has this intrinsic source of randomness in every chaotic deterministic dynamics (even in small ones such as the Lorenz system): The tiniest approximation (and neglecting something always forces an approximation) is immensely magnified and changes the results after a short time to an extent that only statistical information remains reliably predictable. This is the reason both for randomness in quantum mechanics and for the success of statistical mechanics.

  36. A. Neumaier says:

    The opposite of didactical sin is didactical virtue – the ability to impart understanding, ultimately to the point that those taught can convince themselves of the truth of a claim by someone else. This means building upon the understanding that is already there and adding structure that helps to properly think about the topic to be taught.

    The controversy in this thread is about what ”proper thinking” about quantum mechanics entails. I found that I had to unlearn quite a lot to reach my present understanding; a better start than what the textbooks tell could have saved me a lot of work. On the other hand, one has to be careful what to throw away. As samalkhaiat mentioned, Bohr-Sommerfeld quantization is still useful today. Indeed, in its modern generalization it gives the correct result whenever a system is completely integrable (and a good first approximation when it is nearly so); this is the reason why it worked so well for the hydrogen atom (which is completely integrable in several of its incarnations). But one should throw out the idea that Bohr-Sommerfeld quantization works because of a planetary model in miniature. Thus when telling the history one should immediately add that Bohr obtained a correct result (fortunately for the early QM) although his model is in most aspects unacceptable by modern standards.

  37. atyy says:

    “One can repeat the experiment many times only for microscopic systems, since the assumptions underlying the statistical interpretation is that one can prepare a system independently and identically many times. It is impossible to do this for a macroscopic system, let alone for a quantum field that extends from the earth to the sun.

    Yes, in QFT everything is deterministic; God doesn’t play dice since he world was created according to a QFT. The randomness is in the inability to reproduce identical quantum conditions for a macroscopic system, together with the inherent chaoticity of the kinetic, hydrodynamic and elasticity equations for macroscopic matter.

    For the system under discussion in the main pat of this thread, it is the randomness in the photodetector that is responsible for the indeterminism.”

    Hmmm, I’m skeptical just because it seems so non-standard. Are there any references where I could read the details?

    The other reason I’m skeptical is that it seems that QFT can in principle solve the measurement problem (remove the observer that the usual Copenhagen-type interpretation needs). However, non-relativistic QM can also be formulated in the second quantized language, so presumable non-relativistic QFT would also have a deterministic interpretation consistent with observable non-relativistic physics?

  38. Ken G says:

    “I wouldn’t be surprised if 20 years from now a computer could get a Ph.D. in mathmatics at Princeton University, say. [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/FMathL.html#MathResS’]My research group is working towards making this happen[/URL]; though it is difficult to predict a precise timeframe.”Interesting– say the “Euler” code, rather than “Watson” or “Einstein.” It’s an important question– if we could create a code that can take a set of axioms in some syntactic form, and generate in some kind of order of increasing complexity all the theorems, again in syntactic form, that can be proven from those axioms, would we be satisfied by this? It speaks to the question of why we do math– do we just want to know what theorems are logically equivalent to what axioms, or do we wish to understand something? That gets us back to the OP and what is a “didactic sin,” in terms of what is a crime against understanding. I’m not sure that mathematical proofs are just our best means at arriving at the destination of theorems, or physical laws– it seems to me how we get there is important too. (Indeed, that’s what my signature statement below is about.)

    In the case of physics, we might imagine some “Einstein” code that generates unifying theories and tells us how to test them by experiment. Then we carry out the experiments, which can be viewed as running a kind of “Nature” program that determines the outcome of the experiment. In such a situation, we might feel like nothing but messengers, carrying the outputs from the Einstein and Nature programs back and forth like the operator in Searle’s “Chinese Box.” It seems to me we would be watching the progress of science, without actually participating in it, and more importantly, without really gaining any understanding– even if we do watch the creation of tremendous predictive power, and technological advancement. There’s something about science, and perhaps mathematics too, that is different from that.

  39. A. Neumaier says:

    I meant ”our minds are …” in the same sense that we say “water is ##H_2O##”. It is the way a physicist must consider it in order to say something physical about it.

    Clearly, whatever we can observe about the mind is an observation of macroscopic matter and hence observed by means of an observation of the corresponding quantum fields. Which mental picture we form is a different matter – samalkhaiat probably cannot form a mental picture of the mind, as mind is as unobservable as the electron (we cannot see, hear, feel, smell or taste it), but we other mortals have our own mental pictures of it, which may or may not differ a lot from the scientific picture based on the physics we know.

    In particular, that some part of the quantum fields that make up the universe, localized in a human head, can think about quantum fields is not more peculiar than that other parts of the same quantum fields that make up the universe, localized in a computer box, can play chess. The latter was unthinkable 100 years ago; within the 100 years to come computers will be able to do mathematics at the research level. As one can easily observe, mankind is making itself dispensable for every activity that it understands well enough, and this trend is easy to extrapolate into the future. I wouldn’t be surprised if 20 years from now a computer could get a Ph.D. in mathematics at Princeton University, say. [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/FMathL.html#MathResS’]My research group is working towards making this happen[/URL]; though it is difficult to predict a precise time frame.

  40. Ken G says:

    We might choose to model our minds that way, but it does not imply that our minds are that. For one thing, it has never been demonstrated that modeling our minds that way offers any advantages, but it is quite clear that the reverse arrangement, whereby we say that our minds come up with the quantum-field model, offers valuable modeling advantages (for example, advantages that usher in the issue of “didactic sins”).

  41. A. Neumaier says:

    “we do not understand, nor ever include, the roles our minds our playing when we do physics”
    Our minds are part of the initial state of the collection of quantum fields.

  42. A. Neumaier says:

    “That seems to be quite an original interpretation. In the usual view, the initial state of the system is the same on each run of the experiment, and one gets different outcomes because quantum mechanics only predicts probabilities, so we use a large number of runs. In your interpretation, it seems that everything is deterministic,so the random outcome on each run of the experiment is due to the initial state of the system being different on each trial?”

    One can repeat the experiment many times only for microscopic systems, since the assumptions underlying the statistical interpretation is that one can prepare a system independently and identically many times. It is impossible to do this for a macroscopic system, let alone for a quantum field that extends from the earth to the sun.

    Yes, in QFT everything is deterministic; God doesn’t play dice since he created world according to a QFT. The randomness is in the inability to reproduce identical quantum conditions for a macroscopic system, together with the inherent chaoticity of the kinetic, hydrodynamic and elasticity equations for macroscopic matter.

    For the system under discussion in the main part of this thread, it is the randomness in the photodetector that is responsible for the indeterminism.

  43. Ken G says:

    Thanks for the “like”, though I must say you raise a disturbingly valid point– could we ever program “Watson” to do physics, call it the “Einstein” program? Would it be able to suggest experiments and new theories, perhaps suggesting possible new unification schemes? Will we do science like that in a hundred years, where scientists become drones of the Einstein program, carrying out experiments that we are instructed to attempt, with no need for us to try and be creative or intuitive because the Einstein program has already prioritized all the possible directions for inquiry? Then doing physics will indeed feel like an exercise in pure syntax, a distressing possibility but I cannot say it won’t come true! (Perhaps then the “genius” will be in finding the proper syntax for the Einstein code!)

    The relevance to the issue of whether or not it is a didactic sin to teach “old” quantum notions like Bohr atoms and wave/particle duality is that if we turn physics over to the Einstein program, we won’t need to worry about any didactic sins at all, because we won’t need insight or intuition, we will only need to know how to run an experiment and check a theory handed to us by the Einstein program! So what this means is, there is close connection between pedagogical issues like what is a didactic sin, and the whole endeavor of science as a process of human insight and intuition, rather than simply a process of finding more predictive and more unifying theories that predict more observations. Somehow there is a connection between the process of advancing science, and the aesthetics of doing science in the first place. So what we regard as a didactic sin should be connected to what we regard as proper scientific aesthetics– not that the latter is a simple topic!

  44. Ken G says:

    That’s an interesting turn on the situation, but I think what you are saying is that mathematics is not formalizable either, because it requires having a mathematician to say “yes, that’s correct.” That part of math is never formalizable, because if the mathematician is following a program, you need another program to say “yes, that is the correct program for saying what is correct.” And so on. The syntax is inside of that, that part outside the syntax doesn’t count as it is simply assumed.

    What I meant as the non-syntactic element was the recourse to nature. One never knows how nature will respond to a given experiment, and what theory will accomodate the new discovery is not something you can formalize in the program. It is essentially the input of creativity, or genius, and if we could formalize that, we wouldn’t need to wait for the next one to come along!

  45. atyy says:

    “I always find discussions about interpretations to be quite interesting and insightful, but I do end up concluding that physics is not really a formal endeavor. Mathematics is formal, and physics borrows from mathematics in important and interesting ways, but physics is itself not formalizable. I think this is because we do not understand, nor ever include, the roles our minds our playing when we do physics. We know we don’t include this, and we hope it doesn’t matter that we don’t include this, but the fact that we don’t include it is an impediment to formalization in ways that do not appear in mathematics because mathematics is purely syntactic. Physics doesn’t work as a purely syntactic exercise, it is something we actually use, so we have to know how to use it.”

    Mathematics conceived as syntax is essentially physics, since what does one mean by syntax? It requires one to know what one means by the “same symbol”, which is of course a question of psychology and physics. Another way to see this is that syntax is essentially about what computers can do, which is physics.

  46. Ken G says:

    I always find discussions about interpretations to be quite interesting and insightful, but I do end up concluding that physics is not really a formal endeavor. Mathematics is formal, and physics borrows from mathematics in important and interesting ways, but physics is itself not formalizable. I think this is because we do not understand, nor ever include, the roles our minds our playing when we do physics. We know we don’t include this, and we hope it doesn’t matter that we don’t include this, but the fact that we don’t include it is an impediment to formalization in ways that do not appear in mathematics because mathematics is purely syntactic. Physics doesn’t work as a purely syntactic exercise, it is something we actually use, so we have to know how to use it.

  47. atyy says:

    “Ehrenfest’s theorem doesn’t involve the notion of measurement, hence can be interpreted independent of it. It includes the notion of an ensemble mean.

    According to quantum field theory, [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/physfaq/cei/’]an ensemble mean must be interpreted as a (in principle) measurable quantity; it cannot be interpreted a statistical average over many realizations[/URL]. The reason is that there is only one quantum field (of each kind), given by ##phi(t,x)##, say. We cannot obtain averages of it by repeated measurements as in experimentally performable repeated measurements either time passes, or the experiment is performed in different places. Thus averages correspond to weighted sums over fields at different arguments, rather than to different realizations of the field. Thus the ensemble means are at best (as Gibbs indeed introduced them before quantum mechanics was born) averages over fictitious repetitions that justify the application of the statistical calculus for their computation. But they are properties of the individual field – since there is only one of each kind.

    For example, quantum field correlations (2-point functions) are effectively classical observables; indeed, in kinetic theory they appear as the classical variables of the Kadanoff-Baym equations, approximate dynamical equations for the 2-point functions. After a Wigner transform and some further approximation (averaging over small cells in phase space), these turn into the classical variables of the Boltzmann equation. After integration over momenta and some further approximation (averaging over small cells in phase space), these turn into the classical variables of the Navier-Stokes equation, hydromechanic equations that – as every engineer knows – describe the behavior of macroscopic fluids. For macroscopic solids, one can use similar approximations to arrive at the equations of elasticity theory. The most detailed classical level, the Kadanoff-Baym equations, still contain the unsmeared ensemble means of field products.

    Now all macroscopic objects are objects describable by hydromechanics and elasticity theory; so their classical variables have the same interpretation. Thus the quantum-mechanical ensemble averages are classical variables. Moreover, because of the law of large numbers, $$langle f(x)rangle approx f(langle xrangle)$$ for any sufficiently smooth function ##f## of not too many variables. (These caveats are needed because high dimensions and highly nonlinear functions don’t behave so well under the law of large numbers.) Thus we get from Ehrenfest’s theorem the standard classical equations of motion for macroscopic objects.”

    “[USER=123698]@atyy[/USER]: Note that neither quantum jumps nor any other form of state reduction is needed in my explanation.”

    That seems to be quite an original interpretation. In the usual view, the initial state of the system is the same on each run of the experiment, and one gets different outcomes because quantum mechanics only predicts probabilities, so we use a large number of runs. In your interpretation, it seems that everything is deterministic,so the random outcome on each run of the experiment is due to the initial state of the system being different on each trial?

  48. A. Neumaier says:

    Ehrenfest’s theorem doesn’t involve the notion of measurement, hence can be interpreted independent of it. It includes the notion of an ensemble mean.

    According to quantum field theory, [URL=’http://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~neum/physfaq/cei/’]an ensemble mean must be interpreted as a (in principle) measurable quantity; it cannot be interpreted a statistical average over many realizations[/URL]. The reason is that there is only one quantum field (of each kind), given by ##phi(t,x)##, say. We cannot obtain averages of it by repeated measurements as in experimentally performable repeated measurements either time passes, or the experiment is performed in different places. Thus averages correspond to weighted sums over fields at different arguments, rather than to different realizations of the field. Thus the ensemble means are at best (as Gibbs indeed introduced them before quantum mechanics was born) averages over fictitious repetitions that justify the application of the statistical calculus for their computation. But they are properties of the individual field – since there is only one of each kind.

    For example, quantum field correlations (2-point functions) are effectively classical observables; indeed, in kinetic theory they appear as the classical variables of the Kadanoff-Baym equations, approximate dynamical equations for the 2-point functions. After a Wigner transform and some further approximation (averaging over small cells in phase space), these turn into the classical variables of the Boltzmann equation. After integration over momenta and some further approximation (averaging over small cells in phase space), these turn into the classical variables of the Navier-Stokes equation, hydromechanic equations that – as every engineer knows – describe the behavior of macroscopic fluids. For macroscopic solids, one can use similar approximations to arrive at the equations of elasticity theory. The most detailed classical level, the Kadanoff-Baym equations, still contain the unsmeared ensemble means of field products.

    Now all macroscopic objects are objects describable by hydromechanics and elasticity theory; so their classical variables have the same interpretation. Thus the quantum-mechanical ensemble averages are classical variables. Moreover, because of the law of large numbers, $$langle f(x)rangle approx f(langle xrangle)$$ for any sufficiently smooth function ##f## of not too many variables. (These caveats are needed because high dimensions and highly nonlinear functions don’t behave so well under the law of large numbers.) Thus we get from Ehrenfest’s theorem the standard classical equations of motion for macroscopic objects.

  49. atyy says:

    “Every classical system in Nature is just a simplified (slightly approximate) version of the corresponding quantum system, and the motion of the planetary system is well described by Ehrenfest’s theorem together with the quantum Hamiltonian for planets attracted by an inverse square law form.”

    Ehrenfest’s theorem is the way it is most often explained. But one thing I don’t understand is that Ehrenfest’s theorem seem to me to doesn’t include sequential measurements, which are necessary for observing a classical trajectory. Would a more proper way to get a continuously observed trajectory be to repeatedly observe and then collapse the wave function, say something like this approach [URL]http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0512192[/URL] to getting cloud chamber trajectrories?

  50. A. Neumaier says:

    “We are unfortunate because we cannot form a mental picture for the electron”

    Mental pictures have nothing to do with the senses. I have a mental picture of the electron but also of a 4-dimensional cube. On the other hand, our senses do not give a classical picture of the world; this classical picture can be perceived not by our senses but only by the mind, only for less than 400 years, and by people without school education not at all.

    I didn’t claim you post was wrong (it is just an opinion, not a collection of facts), but posted an opposing opinion that makes much more sense to me.

    In complete darkness [URL=’http://scholar.google.at/scholar_url?url=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.nemenmanlab.org%2F~ilya%2Fimages%2F4%2F43%2FRieke-baylor-98.pdf&hl=de&sa=T&oi=gga&ct=gga&cd=6&ei=wph5VbL9KcHWrgHs9oPYDA&scisig=AAGBfm3hjMA-K23TgyJykU91__ADJrSNzQ&nossl=1&ws=1025×1241′]we can see a single photon hitting our eye[/URL], since the eye has an excellent resolution.

    The shape of a photon is very flexible, in typical quantum optics experiments it has the form of one or (after passing a beam splitter) several rays. Its most general shape can be the energy density of any solution of the homogeneous Maxwell equation. The electron in an isolated hydrogen atom is shaped like a fuzzy ball – one can compute its charge density to verify this. Its most general shape is (ignoring radiative corrections) that of the charge density of any solution of the homogeneous Dirac equation.

    Every classical system in Nature is just a simplified (slightly approximate) version of the corresponding quantum system, and the motion of the planetary system is well described by Ehrenfest’s theorem together with the quantum Hamiltonian for planets attracted by an inverse square law form.

« Older Comments

Leave a Reply

Want to join the discussion?
Feel free to contribute!

Leave a Reply