A new realistic stochastic interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

  • #246
iste said:
There is something kind of like that in the stochastic mechanical interpretation though from a very different perspective to yours. The particle is interacting with a background which is hidden insofar that it is not mentioned explicitly in quantum mechanics. It would be conservative interactions between particle and background which are related to the indivisibility.
sounds like leading to via, embedding things in a bigger system. Ie. embedd the non-markovian interactions in a much larger system that is markovian?
for eample https://arxiv.org/abs/2005.00103 ?

This "type" of solution, which is also analogous to how one tries to make true evolution, as a simple entropic dynamics, has the same conceptual flaws and IMO will not solve the problem, without creating more and often bigger problems, which cripples the "explanatory value" of the constructions.
iste said:
Yes; for Barandes, the external observer is explicitly modeled as part of the stochastic system.
Note sure what this means, did he elaborate more clearly on this somwhere that i missed when skimming?

For me "external observer" is an idealisation and fiction, it has a value to simplify models for small subsystem, but in realist, there are only internal obsevers.

But I think of "internal observers" as a kind of stochastic agents existing in and thus interacting with the environment, but the environment is unknown. But this observers is not "modelled" externally, only other internal observers can model other observers. And two internal observers have different views - non more right than the other one.

Rovelli has a nice quote in the context of this Relational QM (before he goes south...).

"Does this mean that there is no relation whatsoever between views of different observers? Certainly not..."

-- C. Rovelli, Relational Quantum Mechanics

"There is an important physical reason behind this fact: It is possible to compare different views, but the process of comparison is always a physical interaction"
-- C. Rovelli, Relational Quantum Mechanics

So the key question is again, what is the NATURE of this physical interaction? Rovellis answer, was - quantum mechanics. But this is a non-answer, as long as no-one understands quantum mechanics, but then again his interpretation served not to unifiy all interactions, it's mainly to build a quantum theory of gravity. (from there on he goes south IMO.. )

I think the key to the non-markovian nature here is the nature of this physical interaction. Embedding this in a bigger space, is cheating. We need to solve the problem without changing perspective, and that is how I envision a kind of stochastic process but taking place in an unknown space. So the space itself, is evolving as observer moves through it. Which is similar to how GR works. So there is interesting enough, conceptual similarities with the dynamics in space, and the evolution of space - and the stochastic processes in some space, and the evolution of this same space in the quantum foundations. Is it a coincidence? I suspect not? And this thing, is also I think exactly why the markovian divisibility isn't be true; there is "information" not only in the state, but in the state of the space as well, but I think not in the sense of a state embedded in a bigger one; that attempt of explanation totally misses the point of what is to be explained.

/Fredrik
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #247
Fra said:
sounds like leading to via, embedding things in a bigger system. Ie. embedd the non-markovian interactions in a much larger system that is markovian?
for eample https://arxiv.org/abs/2005.00103 ?

This "type" of solution, which is also analogous to how one tries to make true evolution, as a simple entropic dynamics, has the same conceptual flaws and IMO will not solve the problem, without creating more and often bigger problems, which cripples the "explanatory value" of the constructions.

I don't know. I don't think so. It's just the most natural way of looking at the stochastic mechanics if you want an unextravagant description. The particles move randomly. Ideally, something must be causing their movement - like a dust particle getting disturbed by the background of molecules in a glass of water. The stochastic mechanical "osmotic velocity" directly corresponds to a component of momentum in quantum mechanics and got an interpretation due to comparison with Einstein Brownian motion - "velocity acquired by a Brownian particle, in equilibrium with respect to an external force, to balance the osmotic force". The external force is then attributed the background, causing the particle random motion. The particle naturally is acting back on the background (because where else is it going to go?) like your dust particle would in a glass of water, and the interplay leads to the osmotic velocity assuming that it leads to an equilibrium which would also conserve particle energy on average in its exchanges with its background environment. The osmotic energy is then mathematically responsible for quantum behavior and is required for energy conservation. This osmotic energy is just the same as the Bohmian quantum potential apart from the fact it is explicitly derived from the assumption of a diffusion which is non-dissipative, i.e. frictionless, time-reversible (albeit without explicit insight into an underlying microscopic model like for the dust particle suspended in water molecules - conservative diffusion seemingly seems sufficient as a constraint).

In the end what it looks like (crudely speaking) is: Lagrangian mechanics + noise = quantum mechanics, hence if you tone down the randomness, or alternatively are talking about objects that are far too big (purposefully ignoring their fine-grained descriptions) to noticeably feel random fluctuations of the background, you just get deterministic classical behavior.

So this background interaction thing is just a notable interpretation for what the mathematics in stochastic mechanics is saying. The classical hydrodynamic fluid bath mentioned earlier is a tempting way of looking at the stochastic mechanical background interaction because of how artificially countering viscous dissipation in those models leads the bath (i.e. background) to retain a memory of the events that interact with the bath, and leads to quantum-like, and seemingly non-local behavior. At the same time its an extremely tenuous link: these models still seem very different to the stochastic mechanical one, very less than perfect quantum analogs, highly fine-tuned with additional distracting components, not clear how similar it actually is at all - I very much have doubt. But the sentiment is vaguely similar to that of Ed Nelson in his book 'quantum fluctuations': "The particle doesn't know whether the other slit is open [or closed], but the background field does", and this isn't necessarily instantaneous either since these stochastic mechanical models seem to take finite amount of time for the system to settle into quantum equilibrium and show interference effects.

Fra said:
Note sure what this means, did he elaborate more clearly on this somwhere that i missed when skimming?

Well the observer is just referring to the measurement-dependence in quantum mechanics, right? In the Barandes model, that is all explicitly incorporated into the stochastic system so you have your observer system and whatever is being measured and then perhaps whatever else may be relevant, depending on scenario. Even though the observer disturbs the system it is observing (and momentarily reinstates Markovianity according to Barandes), there is only ever one definite classical-looking outcome (or set of outcomes) occurring at any given moment in time. The observer-dependence is just a special case of a phenonena that is generic to any interaction between different stochastic systems in the Barandes picture.
 
  • Like
Likes nnunn and physika
  • #248
Nelson's stochastic electrodynamics works because, like Bohmian mechanics, it's defined in configuration space, not physical space, so nonlocality is built in. Unfortunately from the discussion so far, I have no sense of how Barandes's mechanics works, what it lacks, and why he would think it enough to reproduce all the effects of entanglement...
 
  • Like
Likes nnunn, DrChinese and jbergman
  • #249
mitchell porter said:
Nelson's stochastic electrodynamics works because, like Bohmian mechanics, it's defined in configuration space, not physical space, so nonlocality is built in. Unfortunately from the discussion so far, I have no sense of how Barandes's mechanics works, what it lacks, and why he would think it enough to reproduce all the effects of entanglement...

The assertion is that all quantum systems are equivalent to indivisible (also dubbed as 'generalized') stochastic systems - stochastic systems whose time-evolution cannot be arbitrarily divided up in terms of stochastic matrices for intermediate sub-intervals. Barandes' idea then is to show that any indivisible system is a subsystem of a unistochastic system, via something called the Stinespring Dilation Theorem. The unistochastic system can then be translated into a unitarily evolving quantum system in virtue of its definition. So the implication is that all of the behaviors of quantum systems should be expressible in terms of indivisible stochastic systems - or vice versa. For instance, the statistical discrepancy due to violations of divisibility  is interference, specifically corresponding to the kind of interference you would have for trajectories in the path integral formulation (I believe).

Barandes then describes a rudimentary entanglement entirely from the perspective of these indivisible stochastic systems that you can translate a quantum system into. Correlations from local interactions between different stochastic systems results in a non-factorizable composite system. The indivisibility of the composite stochastic system's transition matrix means that it cumulatively encodes statistical information so that the correlation is effectively remembered over time (even with spatial separation) until the composite system experiences a division event (i.e. decoheres and divisibility is momentarily restored) by interacting with another system. The mechanism of entanglement for the indivisibe stochastic system is then arguably due to non-Markovianity - memory - rather than some kind of overt communication.
 
  • Like
Likes nnunn and physika
  • #250
iste said:
Well the observer is just referring to the measurement-dependence in quantum mechanics, right? In the Barandes model, that is all explicitly incorporated into the stochastic system so you have your observer system and whatever is being measured and then perhaps whatever else may be relevant, depending on scenario. Even though the observer disturbs the system it is observing (and momentarily reinstates Markovianity according to Barandes),
The big problem in the inference picture not that the obserer distorts the system, but if you account for the systems back reaction on the observing context. This is trivial when the observing context is dominant. But when you add gravity, and want to understand unification without ad hoc fine tuning, this is the major problem; which I think suggest that we need to provide the other half of the story as well.

iste said:
Ideally, something must be causing their movement -
...
The external force is then attributed the background, causing the particle random motion.
I get what you are saying and agree, but this is half the answer. My reactions are due to that we often seem that alot ot approached supply exactly that - only half the answer. This half of the answer represents the conventional external perspective, where "the whole macroscopic environment" observes a small subsystem (the quantum system). This conceptual framework works for small subsystems, which is where QM is corroborated as it stands.

But when the systems get big enough to cause non-trivial feedback into the "baground observer, macroscopic envirionment"; we tend to fall back to semiclassical models.

So half answer, can make us understand the action of small subsystem, embedded in a dominant context where we have perfect control; and the smaller subsystems we need to explain, the more finetuning to de need to make in the embedding, even to the point nwhere we can't handle it.

So the missing part of the answer is; what about trying to describe the situation from the inside. Then explanatory models can not be rooted in fictional background contexts. Randomness in this inside view rather does not need explanation, as somehow randomness is the "nullhypothesis", because the starting point is a simple stupid agent INSIDE a black box; not OUTSIDE the black box. On the contrary deviation from randomness is what needs to be "explained". And this is the missing part for me... and I couldn't see Barandes offering any new grips on this...

In my view, I do not think in terms of that "something" must be causing the random motion; I see this as artifacts of the external view.

I prefer to think that inside view is that the randomness is simply a manifestation of that the observes can not predict it - the obserever is indifferent to the cause because the mechanism can not be distinguished. This should even mean that the observers actions uncouple with these details; suggesting that that the phenomenology of interactions change as the observational scale does. The problem is that the explanatory power of normal renormalization flow works so that knowledge of a complex detailed microstructure of the macrostate "explains" the reduced interactions as you goto the macroscale. So it's redutionist in nature. But it offers littel insight into the emergence logic.

/Fredrik
 
  • #251
iste said:
The assertion is that all quantum systems are equivalent to indivisible (also dubbed as 'generalized') stochastic systems - stochastic systems whose time-evolution cannot be arbitrarily divided up in terms of stochastic matrices for intermediate sub-intervals. Barandes' idea then is to show that any indivisible system is a subsystem of a unistochastic system, via something called the Stinespring Dilation Theorem. The unistochastic system can then be translated into a unitarily evolving quantum system in virtue of its definition. So the implication is that all of the behaviors of quantum systems should be expressible in terms of indivisible stochastic systems - or vice versa. For instance, the statistical discrepancy due to violations of divisibility  is interference, specifically corresponding to the kind of interference you would have for trajectories in the path integral formulation (I believe).

Barandes then describes a rudimentary entanglement entirely from the perspective of these indivisible stochastic systems that you can translate a quantum system into. Correlations from local interactions between different stochastic systems results in a non-factorizable composite system. The indivisibility of the composite stochastic system's transition matrix means that it cumulatively encodes statistical information so that the correlation is effectively remembered over time (even with spatial separation) until the composite system experiences a division event (i.e. decoheres and divisibility is momentarily restored) by interacting with another system. The mechanism of entanglement for the indivisibe stochastic system is then arguably due to non-Markovianity - memory - rather than some kind of overt communication.
I am in the process of skimming the paper and I for one would like to dig deeper into the math to see if what he is claiming is even correct before discussing the implications of it. Are you convinced that what he is claiming is true?
 
  • #252
Fra said:
The big problem in the inference picture not that the obserer distorts the system, but if you account for the systems back reaction on the observing context. This is trivial when the observing context is dominant. But when you add gravity, and want to understand unification without ad hoc fine tuning, this is the major problem; which I think suggest that we need to provide the other half of the story as well.


I get what you are saying and agree, but this is half the answer. My reactions are due to that we often seem that alot ot approached supply exactly that - only half the answer. This half of the answer represents the conventional external perspective, where "the whole macroscopic environment" observes a small subsystem (the quantum system). This conceptual framework works for small subsystems, which is where QM is corroborated as it stands.

But when the systems get big enough to cause non-trivial feedback into the "baground observer, macroscopic envirionment"; we tend to fall back to semiclassical models.

So half answer, can make us understand the action of small subsystem, embedded in a dominant context where we have perfect control; and the smaller subsystems we need to explain, the more finetuning to de need to make in the embedding, even to the point nwhere we can't handle it.

So the missing part of the answer is; what about trying to describe the situation from the inside. Then explanatory models can not be rooted in fictional background contexts. Randomness in this inside view rather does not need explanation, as somehow randomness is the "nullhypothesis", because the starting point is a simple stupid agent INSIDE a black box; not OUTSIDE the black box. On the contrary deviation from randomness is what needs to be "explained". And this is the missing part for me... and I couldn't see Barandes offering any new grips on this...

In my view, I do not think in terms of that "something" must be causing the random motion; I see this as artifacts of the external view.

I prefer to think that inside view is that the randomness is simply a manifestation of that the observes can not predict it - the obserever is indifferent to the cause because the mechanism can not be distinguished. This should even mean that the observers actions uncouple with these details; suggesting that that the phenomenology of interactions change as the observational scale does. The problem is that the explanatory power of normal renormalization flow works so that knowledge of a complex detailed microstructure of the macrostate "explains" the reduced interactions as you goto the macroscale. So it's redutionist in nature. But it offers littel insight into the emergence logic.

/Fredrik

Well its clear we have very different perspectives. I'm happy to endorse kinds of observer perspectives along the lines of those people who frame things in terms of statistical inference, Bayes, information theory... like Jaynes or Karl Friston in biology. There is even a version of stochastic quantum mechanics along these kinds of lines by Ariel Caticha. But these perspectives are not really radical like yours are of qbists or whoever else. I'm more along the lines of Barandes who think that: if you can explain stramge observer phenomena in quantum mechanics in a kind of mundane, stochastic way as a generic feature of physical interactions then there is no need to continue thinking about radical kinds of observers. But clearly these kinds of observers are a foundational part of your metaphysics.
 
  • Like
Likes jbergman and physika
  • #253
jbergman said:
I am in the process of skimming the paper and I for one would like to dig deeper into the math to see if what he is claiming is even correct before discussing the implications of it. Are you convinced that what he is claiming is true?

Do I know what he is saying is correct? Can I tell you anything about his math being correct and sound? Absolutely not. Am I convinced by his presentation and walkthrough of quantum phenomena in terns of an indivisible stochastic system? Yes. One thing I am sure of is that Nelsonian stochastic mechanics has shown that quantum theory can be expressed in terms of stochastic processes, so that helps brings more confidence in what Barandes is saying.
 
  • Like
Likes nnunn
  • #254
@iste #249, thanks... I won't be sure until I have seen how Barandes formulates something specific like a hydrogen atom, but this sounds like it's just quantum mechanics in which you only speak about observables? e.g. everything is expressed in terms of transition probabilities between observables. Which is fine except that I don't think it would add anything philosophically. For example, it wouldn't imply any particular position about the values of unobserved physical properties, and yet that's the issue at stake regarding the uncertainty principle, local hidden variables, and so on.
 
  • #255
mitchell porter said:
@iste #249, thanks... I won't be sure until I have seen how Barandes formulates something specific like a hydrogen atom, but this sounds like it's just quantum mechanics in which you only speak about observables? e.g. everything is expressed in terms of transition probabilities between observables. Which is fine except that I don't think it would add anything philosophically. For example, it wouldn't imply any particular position about the values of unobserved physical properties, and yet that's the issue at stake regarding the uncertainty principle, local hidden variables, and so on.

Yes, it is supposed to be the same as quantum mechanics but it would mean an underlying interpretations of particles in definite positions or configurations at every point in time even when not being observed. In his perspective, you can translate those indivisible transition probabilities into divisible transition amplitudes where you can construct and sum over paths just like in the path integral formulation - Barandes very briefly mentions the connection in one paper. So basically the perspective is saying the path integral trajectories are actual paths that particles take even when they are not observed. The uncertainty principle would be manifest in the long run statistics when repeating some experiment. Local hidden variables are avoided because even though there are definite outcomes, their statistics will still preclude the kinds of joint probability distributions required for those local beables, hidden variables, due to indivisibility and the fact that non-commuting properties, uncertainty principle still applies in a statistical sense.
 
  • Like
Likes physika and jbergman
  • #256
iste said:
Well its clear we have very different perspectives. I'm happy to endorse kinds of observer perspectives along the lines of those people who frame things in terms of statistical inference, Bayes, information theory... like Jaynes or Karl Friston in biology. There is even a version of stochastic quantum mechanics along these kinds of lines by Ariel Caticha. But these perspectives are not really radical like yours are of qbists or whoever else.
Ariel's nice papers on "physics from inference" along with ET jaynes is one of the papers that inspired me way back, he also used to have an idea to infer GR from inference, but I am indeed taking things one step further. On the technical side, the point where I diverge from Ariels and Jayens "choice of measure" of the observers ignorance is the real numbers. To introduce an uncountable embedding, is genereal, but brings alot of trouble and we loose control. From there on, alot of the mathematical conclusions rests on the real numbers as a good foundation.

This what I tried to mention before that I see there are essentialy 2 ways of emergence.
(1) "entropic" emergence, or regular stochastics; this is a top-down approach to
(2) some self-organisation; this is a botton-up approach

I don't think they are in conflict thougth, but to get the full answer we need to analyse both. The second think is what saves us from fine tuning.

Som objective bayesians focus more on first case, I thikn subjective bayesian more on second. The objective approach try to explain all this by fininding a microstructure where we can identify the observers, and explain objectively the conditional probabilities. But this requires a massive structure - that comes from where?

The subjective approach, can considers the observer to self-organize. In therms of comp sci, I suppose I think of the qbist agent as a evolutionary reinforced learner. The hypothesis is that, just like in biology, that the our elementaryt particles - and their properties - are emergent.

Ie ideas like this

The self-organization of selfishness: Reinforcement Learning shows how selfish behavior can emerge from agent-environment interaction dynamics

This would be a bottom up appraoch, but the top-down stochastic perspect may is be complementary in the case where one large observer observs a small subsystem. It doesn't have to be either or. They represent different perspectives.

"Selfishness" or "self-preservation" and emergent cooperation, are it seems the keys to emergence of type 2.

This is much more radical than the entropic style emergence of objective bayesian thinking.

So the connection to Baranders for me was this...

It seems tha this idea allows transforming from a hilbert space / hamiltonian perspective, to a stochastic perspective where the system evolution is randomg but probabilistically codified directly in transition probabilities? An for those pondering about unification, this makes us work directly with pondering how the transition probabilities emerge rather han indirectly how hamiltonians emerge?

I see this as preferred, but big questions still remains. It seems to me Baranders still assumes the existence of objectivity.

The second idea of emergence (2) is which I see as a way to explain the emergence of the transition probability matrixes baranders mentions. Then working with transittion probabilities, that are "attached" to agents/observers would perhaps be an easier ontology for applying evolutionary reinforced learning, than doing the same in hilbert space! which indeed seems less intuitive. So this this sense I see a value to baranders ideas, but it is only half the story...

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes iste
  • #257
iste said:
you can translate those indivisible transition probabilities into divisible transition amplitudes where you can construct and sum over paths just like in the path integral formulation - Barandes very briefly mentions the connection in one paper
So suppose there's a gap of two seconds between observations, and I want to think about what was happening one second after the first observation. Am I just not allowed to ask about probabilities for unobserved properties? Is that what indivisibility means?
 
  • #258
iste said:
an underlying interpretations of particles in definite positions or configurations at every point in time even when not being observed.
We already know what such an interpretation of QM looks like: it looks like Bohmian mechanics. Which is about as far from stochastic as you can get.
 
  • #259
martinbn said:
But is it useful? There is a difference between used and useful.
It's useful, it helped me to understand and accept the pragmatic instrumental interpretation.
 
  • #260
Demystifier said:
It's useful, it helped me to understand and accept the pragmatic instrumental interpretation.
I meant useful in a more objective way. Anything can be useful to someone, but is it useful to the subject. Can it be used to solve problems that otherwise cannot? Or at least can it be used to provide simpler solutions?
 
  • #261
martinbn said:
I meant useful in a more objective way. Anything can be useful to someone, but is it useful to the subject. Can it be used to solve problems that otherwise cannot? Or at least can it be used to provide simpler solutions?
It depends on what one means by "problems". BM provides a simpler (compared to standard QM) solution to some conceptual problems, even if it does not help in practical, technical and quantitative problems.
 
  • #262
Demystifier said:
It depends on what one means by "problems". BM provides a simpler (compared to standard QM) solution to some conceptual problems, even if it does not help in practical, technical and quantitative problems.
Can you give examples?
 
  • #263
mitchell porter said:
So suppose there's a gap of two seconds between observations, and I want to think about what was happening one second after the first observation. Am I just not allowed to ask about probabilities for unobserved properties? Is that what indivisibility means?
You can ask..

...but it means that you can not ask about probabilities midprocess AND presume that the answers necessarily forms a disjoint partition of sample space; so that you later can just use the law of total probability to divide the process.

This is also what IS implicitly assumed in bells ansatz wrt the hypothetical probablities for the hidden variables.

/Fredrik
 
  • #264
davidespinosa said:
Is there any actual discussion of Barandes' papers in this thread ?

It seems to me that the entire thread is off-topic, but I haven't read every single post.
Indeed, this thread seems to go into off-topic territory again :-)

Demystifier said:
It depends on what one means by "problems". BM provides a simpler (compared to standard QM) solution to some conceptual problems, even if it does not help in practical, technical and quantitative problems.
martinbn said:
Can you give examples?
How about
"... some Bohmians (Goldstein, Tumulka, et al) attacked that problem head on (https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0309021):
It is thus not unreasonable to ask, which mu, if any, corresponds to a given thermodynamic ensemble? To answer this question we construct, for any given density matrix rho, a natural measure on the unit sphere in H, denoted GAP(rho). We do this using a suitable projection of the Gaussian measure on H with covariance rho.
Sadly, Jozsa, Robb, and Wootters already constructed the same measure in 1994 (https://journals.aps.org/pra/abstract/10.1103/PhysRevA.49.668), as I learned from a follow up paper by the Bohmians (https://arxiv.org/abs/1104.5482)."
which I mentioned in
https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/the-interpretation-of-probability.1016226/post-6643974 ?

Back then, when I was trying to solve that problem, I googled around (hoping to find at least some "official name" of that problem) and found papers trying to also solve that problem, like:
https://www.uni-kassel.de/fb10-physik/uk003909/Papers/PRE_100_052105_2019.pdf
I wrote to one of the authors (because I still didn't even know a name, much less a solution), and he pointed me to one of their earlier publications, which investigated
A. Grid-based random phase approach
B. Eigenfunction-based random phase approach
C. Gaussian random phase wave packets / freely propagated random phase
wavepackets
https://pubs.aip.org/aip/jcp/articl...emtosecond-two-photon-photoassociation-of-hot (https://arxiv.org/abs/1201.1750)
A. and C. actually failed for them, because they were not aware that there was a way to do this "correctly" discovered by Jozsa, Robb, and Wootters in 1994, and rediscovered by some Bohmians in 2003.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #265
martinbn said:
Can you give examples?
One example where the mathematical formalism of BM could turn out to useful is reciprocity and time symmetry: The mathematical formalism of BM is still time symmetric, before the Bohmians came along and destroyed that symmetry by their attempts to interpret that formalism.

Most instrumentatistic interpretations (and especially Copenhagen) on the other hand have time asymmetry already baked in. Sometimes in a very transparent manner, where the past preparation has finite entropy, but the future measurements have potentially infinite entropy. But more often than not, the time asymmetry is completely entangled with the interpretation.
 
  • #266
gentzen said:
Indeed, this thread seems to go into off-topic territory again :-)



How about
"... some Bohmians (Goldstein, Tumulka, et al) attacked that problem head on (https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0309021):

Sadly, Jozsa, Robb, and Wootters already constructed the same measure in 1994 (https://journals.aps.org/pra/abstract/10.1103/PhysRevA.49.668), as I learned from a follow up paper by the Bohmians (https://arxiv.org/abs/1104.5482)."
which I mentioned in
https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/the-interpretation-of-probability.1016226/post-6643974 ?

Back then, when I was trying to solve that problem, I googled around (hoping to find at least some "official name" of that problem) and found papers trying to also solve that problem, like:
https://www.uni-kassel.de/fb10-physik/uk003909/Papers/PRE_100_052105_2019.pdf
I wrote to one of the authors (because I still didn't even know a name, much less a solution), and he pointed me to one of their earlier publications, which investigated
A. Grid-based random phase approach
B. Eigenfunction-based random phase approach
C. Gaussian random phase wave packets / freely propagated random phase
wavepackets
https://pubs.aip.org/aip/jcp/articl...emtosecond-two-photon-photoassociation-of-hot (https://arxiv.org/abs/1201.1750)
A. and C. actually failed for them, because they were not aware that there was a way to do this "correctly" discovered by Jozsa, Robb, and Wootters in 1994, and rediscovered by some Bohmians in 2003.
This is a lot to absorb but on first glance I cannot see anything specifically Bohmian here?

gentzen said:
One example where the mathematical formalism of BM could turn out to useful is reciprocity and time symmetry: The mathematical formalism of BM is still time symmetric, before the Bohmians came along and destroyed that symmetry by their attempts to interpret that formalism.

Most instrumentatistic interpretations (and especially Copenhagen) on the other hand have time asymmetry already baked in. Sometimes in a very transparent manner, where the past preparation has finite entropy, but the future measurements have potentially infinite entropy. But more often than not, the time asymmetry is completely entangled with the interpretation.
What problems does this help solve?
 
  • #267
martinbn said:
This is a lot to absorb but on first glance I cannot see anything specifically Bohmian here?
It is the topic of how to interact with Density Matrices in BM. There is also another approach to that topic, from the "same clique of Bohmians":
On the Role of Density Matrices in Bohmian Mechanics, with D. Dürr, R. Tumulka, and N. Zanghì, Foundations of Physics 35, 449-467 (2005), quant-ph/0311127
 
  • #268
gentzen said:
It is the topic of how to interact with Density Matrices in BM. There is also another approach to that topic, from the "same clique of Bohmians":
On the Role of Density Matrices in Bohmian Mechanics, with D. Dürr, R. Tumulka, and N. Zanghì, Foundations of Physics 35, 449-467 (2005), quant-ph/0311127
Ok, but how does this answer my question? You are just listing papers by bohmians. So they define what conditional density matrix is. My question remains, what problems does this solve?
 
  • #269
martinbn said:
This is a lot to absorb but on first glance I cannot see anything specifically Bohmian here?
martinbn said:
Ok, but how does this answer my question? ... My question remains, what problems does this solve?
Which question? I quoted the question from you which I tried to answer. From my perspective, the question didn't remain the same.

Maybe it helps you, if I selectively quote parts of the paper title and its abstract:

... photoassociation of hot magnesium atoms ...​

... model the thermal ensemble of hot colliding atoms ...

gentzen said:
One example where the mathematical formalism of BM could turn out to useful is reciprocity and time symmetry: ...
martinbn said:
What problems does this help solve?
I could go into more concrete details, but I am unsure whether it would not just trigger again your "a lot to absorb" reaction. As soon as it gets concrete, there is always much stuff to absorb.
 
  • #270
mitchell porter said:
So suppose there's a gap of two seconds between observations, and I want to think about what was happening one second after the first observation. Am I just not allowed to ask about probabilities for unobserved properties? Is that what indivisibility means?
I don't think so, but maybe someone more informed can answer. As I understand it, indivisibility is just a condition on the evolution of the transition matrix.

For instance, he describes ##\Gamma(n \delta t) = \Gamma(0)^n## as an example of a divisible evolution of the transition matrix.

I think the typical Unitary evolution we associate with QM can be formulated as indivisble evolution of the transition matrix.
 
  • #271
IMO the "conceptual value" added seems to mainly be that we can describe or "phrase" what makes "quantum inference" possible, simply in terms of conditional probabilites, without using the hilbert space ontology and complex wave functions.

One can view the non-commutativity in complex hilbers space, instead as a kind of "statistical dependence". I think that is good.

But all other hard problems remains and are not solved as far as I see.

/Fredrik
 
  • #272
Fra said:
Baranders still assumes the existence of objectivity

...So ?
 
  • #273
physika said:
...So ?
Most do, and use it like a constraint, so not unusual of course.

But for those having an observer centered starting point, usually try to explain effective objectivity in the sense of observer equivalence, via some emergent asymptotic process.

I had hoped Barandes had something of this up his sleves, but seems not.

/Fredrik
 
  • #274
martinbn said:
Can you give examples?
After decoherence, why does only one branch of the wave function becomes physically relevant? In other words, where does the collapse rule come from? The Bohmian answer to this conceptual question is much clearer than the standard one.
 
  • #276
Demystifier said:
After decoherence, why does only one branch of the wave function becomes physically relevant? In other words, where does the collapse rule come from? The Bohmian answer to this conceptual question is much clearer than the standard one.
This is a question about interpretations. I wanted to see an example of a problem that BM solves and QM, not some interpretation of QM, doesn't solve. Or at least gives an easier/better solution. More along the examples of @gentzen , but his examples are not clear to me.
 
  • #277
gentzen said:
Maybe it helps you, if I selectively quote parts of the paper title and its abstract:

... photoassociation of hot magnesium atoms ...​

... model the thermal ensemble of hot colliding atoms ...
Is this the example? Is this something that is handled in BM better than in QM?
 
  • #278
martinbn said:
Is this the example? Is this something that is handled in BM better than in QM?
Yes, it is the concrete example that I alluded to. The concrete problem is not easy, so just using the solution suggested by BM would fix A. and C., but this doesn't mean that it will be the best solution for this problem. The considered approaches were
A. Grid-based random phase approach
B. Eigenfunction-based random phase approach
C. Gaussian random phase wave packets / freely propagated random phase
wavepackets
I guess the best solution also depends on the gaps between the Eigenvalues, i.e. if there are some dominant Eigenvalues clearly separated from the rest, then it is better to handle those explicitly, and only use the canonical measure on the rest of the spectrum of Eigenvalues.

So the role of BM here is to add a specific perspective to your arsenal available when tackling concrete problems. For the concrete problem, there is no clear cut right or wrong, best or optimal. But for BM, there was an important question, where already the fact that it had a concrete answer was important, and in addition it turned out that the concrete answer was even practical to a certain extent. (If you look at the details, there is a rejection samping part caused by the required normalization of the Gaussian measure, i.e. the "adjusted" in "Gaussian adjusted projected measure". It would have been nice if that could have been avoided, but I guess it cannot.)
Another part of BM was that it made it easier to search for that solution, because it is a "canonical" problem in that context, so you expect that other people might have tried to tackle it already. For the concrete problem on the other hand, there was rather the expectation that even if other people had struggled with similar problems, it would be hard for you to find their publications.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes martinbn
  • #279
martinbn said:
This is a question about interpretations. I wanted to see an example of a problem that BM solves and QM, not some interpretation of QM, doesn't solve. Or at least gives an easier/better solution. More along the examples of @gentzen , but his examples are not clear to me.
I don't know such an example, but I also don't know an opposite example, for which standard QM is better than BM. Do you?
 
  • #280
There is indeed no physical problem that BM solves and QM not. However, David Bohm and Jeffrey Bub pointed out to their uneasy feeling with regard to the orthodox interpretation of QM. In their paper “A Proposed Solution of the Measurement Problem in Quantum Mechanics by a Hidden Variable Theory“ (Rev. Mod. Phys. 38, 453, 1966), they wrote:

It is not easy to avoid the feeling that such a sudden break in the theory (i.e., the replacement, unaccounted for in the theory, of one wave function by another when an individual system undergoes a measurement) is rather arbitrary. Of course, this means the renunciation of a deterministic treatment of physical processes, so that the statistics of quantum mechanics becomes irreducible (whereas in classical statistical mechanics it is a simplification – in principle more detailed predictions are possible with more information).
 
  • Like
Likes nnunn, Demystifier and Fra

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
42
Views
6K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
42
Views
3K
Replies
152
Views
8K
Back
Top