Carroll's Derivation of the Born Rule in MWI with Unequal Amplitudes

In summary, "Carroll's Derivation of the Born Rule in MWI with Unequal Amplitudes" explores how the Born Rule, which provides a framework for predicting the probabilities of different outcomes in quantum mechanics, can be derived within the Many-Worlds Interpretation (MWI) when considering states with unequal amplitudes. Carroll argues that by analyzing the structure of quantum states and their associated probabilities, one can reconcile the MWI's deterministic nature with the probabilistic outcomes observed in experiments. This derivation emphasizes the importance of amplitude ratios and interactions in determining the likelihood of various measurement results, ultimately supporting the viability of MWI as a coherent interpretation of quantum phenomena.
  • #36
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure this is true. Microscopic interactions are what decohere things in the first place. For example, in my gas in the box Schrodinger's cat-type experiment, microscopic interactions within the gas on the two different branches (volume changed, volume not changed) are what decohere the branches. Those same microscopic interactions can't also be creating coherent superpositions.
I don't see why not. What's the problem with an interaction creating new entanglements and at the same time spreading previous entanglements?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
kered rettop said:
What's the problem with an interaction creating new entanglements and at the same time spreading previous entanglements?
The same interaction can't be both coherent and decoherent. It has to be one or the other. (Technically it's a continuum, with "fully coherent" and "fully decoherent" as opposite endpoints, but the point is the same--the same interaction can't be at two different points on the continuum, or moving in two different directions. If the interaction is decohering--moving towards the "fully decoherent" endpoint--it can't also be moving towards the "fully coherent" endpoint. It has to be one or the other.)
 
  • #38
PeterDonis said:
The same interaction can't be both coherent and decoherent. It has to be one or the other. (Technically it's a continuum, with "fully coherent" and "fully decoherent" as opposite endpoints, but the point is the same--the same interaction can't be at two different points on the continuum, or moving in two different directions. If the interaction is decohering--moving towards the "fully decoherent" endpoint--it can't also be moving towards the "fully coherent" endpoint. It has to be one or the other.)
I'm not saying it's going in two directions at once, I'm saying there are two different terms for the change in coherence corresponding to different idealised models. Both apply at once in a more realistic model.
 
  • #39
kered rettop said:
I'm saying there are two different terms for the change in coherence corresponding to different idealised models. Both apply at once in a more realistic model.
I don't understand this. Can you be more specific? Math would help.
 
  • #40
PeterDonis said:
I don't understand this. Can you be more specific?
There are two idealised cases for the interaction between two molecules.

The first idealised case treats the molecules' joint state as separable and pure. After the interaction, the joint state is no longer separable, the molecules are entangled. The entanglement is a coherent state - which you interpreted as an increase in coherence of the whole system. I don't know how you quantify coherence but your claim sounds highly plausible to me. The interaction has increased the coherence.

The second idealised case treats the first molecule's state as entangled with a third. The first molecule interacts with the second, thus spreading the entanglement to include the second. This is the first step in decoherence - subsequent interactions propagate it through the entire system. The interaction has decreased the coherence.

The actual initial state will be a superposition of both these cases. So a single interaction will be a superposition of both, the decoherence of |> 1,3 occuring at the same time as the entangling of |>1|>2

PeterDonis said:
Math would help.
I seriously doubt it! :wink:
 
Last edited:
  • Skeptical
Likes weirdoguy
  • #41
kered rettop said:
The first idealised case treats the molecules' joint state as separable and pure.
In this case the interaction is not decohering anything. Decoherence in the environment means at least one of the interacting particles in the environment is already entangled with something else (because the decoherence is spreading entanglement that originally came from an external interaction, such as the environment interacting with a measuring device that has recorded a result). If either of the molecules is already entangled with something else, their joint state prior to the interaction cannot be pure.

It is possible in principle for two of the gas molecules to not be entangled with anything else--in principle we could at least prepare the gas in such a state at the start of the experiment. But any such state will not last very long. Even in the absence of external interaction, the gas will decohere itself as its molecules interact. So the chances of any two interacting molecules not being entangled with anything else will decrease with time. Given the number of molecules involved, I would expect the decoherence time to be very short.

kered rettop said:
The second idealised case treats the first molecule's state as entangled with a third.
And as you note, this decreases coherence. See above.

kered rettop said:
The actual initial state will be a superposition of both these cases.
No, it won't. You can't have a quantum state of any system that is a superposition of pure and not pure. That is mathematically impossible. (This illustrates why I said math would help: trying to actually write down the math to back up your claim in the quote above would, or should, have showed you why the claim is wrong.)

kered rettop said:
I seriously doubt it! :wink:
Your doubt is misplaced. See above.
 
  • #42
Saunders justifies his notion of very many branches in section 6 using a consistent histories formalism. Specifically, he constructs branching histories using a fine-grained projective decomposition of the identity (PDI) and n-tuples as sequences of properties constructed from this PDI.

Generally speaking, this is not possible, so I do not believe this section. Branching histories are instead obtained by e.g. using a coarse-grained PDI at an early time ##t_1##, and increasingly refined PDIs at later times. His argument might still be recoverable with some modification. I will see if this is the case when I have the some free time.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes jbergman
  • #43
Morbert said:
Saunders justifies his notion of very many branches in section 6 using a consistent histories formalism. Specifically, he constructs branching histories using a fine-grained projective decomposition of the identity and n-tuples as sequences of properties constructed from this PDI.

Generally speaking, this is not possible, so I do not believe this section. Branching histories are instead obtained by e.g. using a coarse-grained PDI at an early time ##t_1##, and increasingly refined PDIs at later times. His argument might still be recoverable with some modification. I will see if this is the case when I have the some free time.
What does PDI stand for?
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #44
jbergman said:
What does PDI stand for?
Projective decomposition of the identity. Updated the post to clarify
 
  • #45
Saunders constructs the states ##C_{\underline{\alpha}_n}(t_n)|\phi;0\rangle## for branch counting purposes, where ##C_{\underline{\alpha}_n}## is the ususal history operator: a chain of projectors
$$C_{\underline{\alpha}_n} = P_{\alpha_n}(t_n)\dots P_{\alpha_1}(t_1)$$He remarks that the states are orthogonal to one another if the ##\underline{\alpha}_n##s differ at any of the times ##t_1,\dots,t_n##. This is not generally true (see this paper for details). It is true if the history space has a branching structure, but this cannot be assumed for arbitrary n-tuples of properties. To describe a branching structure, it's useful to consider a truncated history operator ##C_{\underline{\alpha}_k}## where ##t_k < t_n## $$C_{\underline{\alpha}_k} = P_{\alpha_k}(t_k)\dots P_{\alpha_1}(t_1)$$$$C_{\underline{\alpha}_{k+1}} = P_{\alpha_{k+1}}(t_{k+1})C_{\underline{\alpha}_{k}}$$In a history space with a branching structure, if ##||P_{\alpha_{k+1}}(t_{k+1})C_{\underline{\alpha}_{k}}|\phi;0\rangle||^2## and ##||P_{\alpha_{k+1}}(t_{k+1})C_{\underline{\alpha'}_{k}}|\phi;0\rangle||^2## are nonzero, then ##C_{\underline{\alpha'}_{k}} = C_{\underline{\alpha}_{k}}## I.e. If the system has some property ##\alpha_{k+1}## at time ##t_{k+1}##, then it must have arrived at this property via the unique history ##C_{\alpha_{k}}##. Similarly, if you are walking out onto a branch of a tree, that branch only has one connection to the trunk (branches do not "recombine" when growing away from the trunk). One way to construct a branching history space is to use properties that are appropriate refinements of previous properties. I.e. $$\sum_{\alpha_{k+1};\alpha_{k+1}\subseteq\alpha_k}P_{\alpha_{k+1}} = P_{\alpha_k}$$One process that satisfies this is a process where at each time ##t_k## the property ##\alpha_k## includes an irreversible record by some environmental degrees of freedom. These environmental states would serve as the "memory states" Saunders mentions.
 
Last edited:
  • #46
Posted in error, deleted, decluttered and reposted. Apologies to @weirdoguy for breaking the threading model.

PeterDonis said:
In this case the interaction is not decohering anything. Decoherence in the environment means at least one of the interacting particles in the environment is already entangled with something else (because the decoherence is spreading entanglement that originally came from an external interaction, such as the environment interacting with a measuring device that has recorded a result). If either of the molecules is already entangled with something else, their joint state prior to the interaction cannot be pure.
...
No, it won't. You can't have a quantum state of any system that is a superposition of pure and not pure. That is mathematically impossible.
I can't believe I'm reading this! You can't just replace a state that I defined to be pure with one that is not and then imply that I'm trying to do the mathematically impossible with your alternative.
PeterDonis said:
(This illustrates why I said math would help: trying to actually write down the math to back up your claim in the quote above would, or should, have showed you why the claim is wrong.)
I did not say that I hadn't done the maths to the limit of my abilities. Of course I had. I am not a complete idiot. What I said was that I didn't think it would be helpful to post - per your post #39 - any maths in order to explain what I was saying.
 
Last edited:
  • #47
kered rettop said:
You can't just replace a state that I defined to be pure with one that is not and then imply that I'm trying to do the mathematically impossible with your alternative.
I can't believe I'm reading this. You appear to not grasp my actual point at all. You can't just "define" a state to be pure whenever you like. If you want to claim that a particular state has certain properties and is relevant to what we're discussing, you have to show that those things are the case. And to do that, you need to first explicitly write down the state. Just waving your hands does not work.

kered rettop said:
What I said was that I didn't think it would be helpful to post - per your post #39 - any maths in order to explain what I was saying.
And, as I said, your doubt about this was misplaced. If you had actually tried to write down explicitly the state you were waving your hands about, instead of just talking about it in words, it would have become clear to you that you were waving your hands about a state that is, in fact, mathematically impossible.
 
  • #48
kered rettop said:
a state that I defined to be pure
There is also a confusion of terminology in our discussion. The relevant distinction is not between "pure" and "mixed" but between non-entangled and entangled. I should have clarified that in post #41. An entangled state is still a pure state of the joint system. (If we trace over part of the system, we get a mixed state for the rest of the system, but we don't need to do that here.)
 

Similar threads

Replies
13
Views
3K
Replies
7
Views
1K
Replies
44
Views
6K
Replies
10
Views
1K
Replies
34
Views
3K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
0
Views
539
Back
Top