Answer: Cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] Real Numbers

In summary: Send 0 to 1/2, and 1 to 1/3.5. This can be effected by, f(0)=1/2, f(1/n)= 1/(n+2) for n >= 1.6. Then complete the definition of f by, f(x)=? for all x in ?
  • #1
MrJB
42
0
I'm fairly sure that the intervals (0,1) and [0,1] of real numbers have the same cardinality, but I can't think of a bijection between them. Any thoughts?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Let's start with a warmup exercise:

Can you find a bijection between the set of all nonnegative integers and the set of all positive integers?


Once you've answered that, can you think of a way to apply this very example to your problem? Or at least this technique?
 
  • #3
Well, for the warm-up, I'd define f(n)=n+1 as my map from the set of nonnegative integers to the set of positive integers. Thus, 0,1,2... would get mapped to 1,2,3... etc.
I don't see the connection to my problem though.
 
  • #4
I'm wondering why you want to find a bijection. Very rarely does one produce an explicit bijection to show that two sets have the same cardinality. One of the main tools is the Shroeder-Bernstein theorem: it says that if you have an injection from A into B and an injection from B into A, then there exists a bijection between A and B (note: this is an existence result; it doesn't tell us how to construct the bijection). You can apply it to your problem.

In regards to Hurkyl's hint, try using this to find a bijection between [0,1] and (0,1], for example.
 
  • #5
I was just curious what such a bijection might look like.

In regards to the Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem, the injection from (0,1) into [0,1] is obvious, and the injection from [0,1] into (0,1) I can define as f(x)=x/2+1/4. So there is a bijection between them.

I'm still lost on Hurkyl's hint. With the integers, my map just moved all the elements to the next integer, but with the reals there is no 'next' real.
 
  • #6
How about, say, the sets {1/n : n a positive integer} and {1/n : n a nonnegative integer} in [0,1]?
 
  • #7
MrJB said:
I'm still lost on Hurkyl's hint. With the integers, my map just moved all the elements to the next integer, but with the reals there is no 'next' real.
What this tells you is that, if you're given a countable set, you know how to make an individual point "appear" or "disappear".

Now, if you could find a countable subset of [0, 1], then you know how to make a point of that subset disappear...
 
  • #8
I think I can work with that...

So my map would take the set {1/n : n a positive integer} to {1/(n+1) : n a positive integer}. That is, 1,1/2,1/3... would map to 1/2,1/3,1/4... and the rest of the reals would map to themselves, thus defining a bijection from [0,1] to [0,1). Then I would repeat a similar technique to the other side.

Thanks.
 
  • #9
Yep. That is the basic technique for "removing" individual points from an infinite set. The core idea works in a wide variety of situations.
 
  • #10
Awesome.
You could use the same idea to 'remove' infinite sets of points too? If I wanted to map the closed unit disc to the open unit disc, I would map the sets of points with distances from the origin 1,1/2,1/3 to the sets of points with distances 1/2,1/3,1/4 from the origin?
 
  • #11
That certainly seems to work!
 
  • #12
MrJB said:
I'm fairly sure that the intervals (0,1) and [0,1] of real numbers have the same cardinality, but I can't think of a bijection between them. Any thoughts?

Thoughts on an example construction of f:[0,1] -> (0,1) that's bijective. (There are many such f's.)

1. The sets differ only at two points, 0 and 1.
2. Must find images for 0 and 1 somewhere in (0,1) while still keeping f bijective.
3. Let A={0,1,1/2,1/3,...,1/n,...}. (Something like this has already been suggested.)
4. Send 0 to 1/2, and 1 to 1/3.
5. This can be effected by, f(0)=1/2, f(1/n)= 1/(n+2) for n >= 1.

6. Then complete the definition of f by, f(x)=? for all x in ?

The final step is to actually verify that f is bijective.

Typically, it's easier to find two injections than one bijection.
This example brings the point out a little bit.
So yes, in many cases Schroeder-Bernstein has considerable practical value.
But, it's greatest value is theoretical, not practical.
I'd say there's something to be learned by actually constructing an f (like the one above), and demonstrating that's it's bijective.


EDIT: I'll complete the definition of f.
f(x)=x for all x in [0,1]-A. (Obviously there was a reason for A.)
 
Last edited:
  • #13
Try this: irrational numbers between 0 and 1 map into themselves.

The rational numbers between 0 and 1 are countable so the can be written in a list:
[itex]r_1, r_2, r_3, \cdot\cdot\cdot[/itex]. Now map [itex]r_1\rightarrow 0[/itex], [itex]r_2/rightarrow 1[/itex], [itex]r_3\right arrow r_1[/itex], [itex]r_4\rightarrow r_2[/itex],[itex]\cdot\cdot\cdot[/itex], [itex]r_n\rightarrow r_{n-2}[/itex].
 
  • #14
fopc said:
Thoughts on an example construction of f:[0,1] -> (0,1) that's bijective. (There are many such f's.)

1. The sets differ only at two points, 0 and 1.
2. Must find images for 0 and 1 somewhere in (0,1) while still keeping f bijective.
3. Let A={0,1,1/2,1/3,...,1/n,...}. (Something like this has already been suggested.)
4. Send 0 to 1/2, and 1 to 1/3.
5. This can be effected by, f(0)=1/2, f(1/n)= 1/(n+2) for n >= 1.

6. Then complete the definition of f by, f(x)=? for all x in ?

The final step is to actually verify that f is bijective.

Typically, it's easier to find two injections than one bijection.
This example brings the point out a little bit.
So yes, in many cases Schroeder-Bernstein has considerable practical value.
But, it's greatest value is theoretical, not practical.
I'd say there's something to be learned by actually constructing an f (like the one above), and demonstrating that's it's bijective.EDIT: I'll complete the definition of f.
f(x)=x for all x in [0,1]-A. (Obviously there was a reason for A.)
Still why would this be bijective? How do you know that step A 1/n->1/(n+1)
and step B f(x)=x for all x in [0,1] won't end up in the same number.
I know intuitively it makes sense, but it doesn't seem very mathematically rigorous.
 
  • #15
grossgermany said:
Still why would this be bijective? How do you know that step A 1/n->1/(n+1)
and step B f(x)=x for all x in [0,1] won't end up in the same number.
I know intuitively it makes sense, but it doesn't seem very mathematically rigorous.

I suspect you didn't read the EDIT.
It reads, f(x) = x for all x in [0,1]-A.

Not mathematically rigorous?
Well, I defined an f, and made a claim that f is a bijection; nothing more. I then suggested the need to demonstrate this by showing f is injective and surjective. There's hidden value here. It forces you to think about definitions.

You question that f is bijective (in particular you seem to doubt that it's injective). Well?

Finally, I apologize to Ernst. It should be Schröder.
 

FAQ: Answer: Cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] Real Numbers

What is the difference between (0,1) and [0,1] in terms of cardinality?

The cardinality of (0,1) is known as the cardinality of the interval (0,1), while the cardinality of [0,1] is known as the cardinality of the closed interval [0,1]. The main difference between these two is that the closed interval [0,1] includes its endpoints, while the open interval (0,1) does not.

How do we determine the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1]?

The cardinality of a set is determined by the number of elements in that set. In this case, we can use the concept of infinity to determine the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1]. Both intervals have an infinite number of real numbers between 0 and 1, but the closed interval [0,1] also includes 0 and 1 as elements, making it a larger set with a higher cardinality.

Is the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] the same as that of the set of all real numbers?

No, the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] is not the same as that of the set of all real numbers. The set of all real numbers has an uncountable infinite cardinality, while the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] is countable infinite. This means that there are more real numbers between 0 and 1 than just the numbers in these two intervals.

Can the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] be compared to the cardinality of other sets?

Yes, the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] can be compared to the cardinality of other sets. In fact, the cardinality of (0,1) and [0,1] is the same as that of the set of all rational numbers between 0 and 1. This is because both (0,1) and [0,1] have a countable infinite number of elements, just like the set of rational numbers.

Why is the concept of cardinality important in mathematics?

The concept of cardinality is important in mathematics because it helps us understand the size or magnitude of a set. It allows us to compare the number of elements in different sets and determine whether one set is larger or smaller than another. Cardinality is also used in various mathematical concepts, such as sets, functions, and infinity.

Similar threads

Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
126
Views
7K
Replies
18
Views
2K
Replies
9
Views
5K
Replies
1
Views
3K
Back
Top