- #1
Gordon Watson
- 375
- 0
This thread is an offshoot of https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=403210 -- Joy Christian's disproof of Bell.
This thread is a response to:
Most of this case is based on simple maths -- so errors can be easily spotted and agreed, such errors perhaps having important lessons about BT.
So in this OP we set out to:
A: Deliver P1-P8; see Sakurai http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sakurai%27s_Bell_inequality which is our context.
B: Have them summing to unity.
C: Have them fully compatible with QM-style experiments; delivering accepted QM results.
D: Have them recognizing a topology [for want of a better word] associated with the spherical symmetry of the singlet state and measuring-device settings.
E: Have them challenging the basis of Bell's inequality.
F: Have them based on nothing more than high-school maths and logic; so no fancy maneuvers are involved -- and the discussion should be understood by most everyone.
NOTATION: The following short-hand notation is used.
Angles: ab denotes the angle between the orientations a and b, etc.
Functions: Cab denotes cos^2 s(ab), where s is the intrinsic spin of the relevant particle; here, as in Sakurai, s = 1/2; Sab denotes sin^2 s(ab); etc.
Reference orientation: Orientation c is taken as the reference orientation; so orientations a and b are defined with reference to c. This reference orientation arises from Bohr's responses to EPR, neatly captured in Jammer (The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: The Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics in Historical Perspective, 1974): "And just as the choice of a different frame of reference in relativity affects the result of a particular measurement, so also in quantum mechanics the choice of a different experimental setup has its effects on measurements, for it determines what is measurable."
Probabilities based on a local realistic hidden-variable analysis -- that theory not addressed here -- (P1-P8 identifiers after Sakurai, see above):
P1 = Cac.Cbc/2
P2 = Sac.Sbc/2
P3 = Cac.Sbc/2
P4 = Sac.Cbc/2
P5 = Sac.Cbc/2
P6 = Cac.Sbc/2
P7 = Sac.Sbc/2
P8 = Cac.Cbc/2
CONTINUATION: The reader should ascertain that the above Ps sum to one, yielding outcomes fully compatible with QM-style experiments; i.e., delivering accepted QM results.
PROVISO: Note that, in this example, the outcome-probabilities attaching to the ab settings are averages over the two ab possibilities. This follows from the topological fact re spatial relations here: ab may be constructed in two ways:
(1) ab = ac + bc.
(2) ab = ac - bc.
FOR DISCUSSION: It seems to me that this example of Bell's theorem is similar to a triangle-inequality where we can only ever measure two sides of any triangle (i.e., use a or b or c as the reference frame); see JesseM's comment above re QM and P1-P8. So any inference to a third side will be misleading. This is illustrated above where the ac and bc results are definitive because we took c as the datum; the ab result not so.
Which raises the question of the relevance of Bell's theorem to local realism? The above P1-P8 are based on a local realistic hidden-variable analysis; and yield relevant experimental outcomes; the HVs taken to be the orientation (in 3-space) of the total angular momentum of each particle, the particles pairwise correlated in the spherically symmetric singlet state.
And to this extent, the above analysis is on an equal footing with QM: Both predict that the Bell inequality will be violated.
E and OE,
JenniT
This thread is a response to:
THE SAKURAI LINK (above) SHOULD BE STUDIED AND UNDERSTOOD. This thread also has its basis in the following [somewhat edited] exchange:vanesch said:Maybe I'm simply not sophisticated enough, but there's a version of Bell's theorem which is so terribly elementary, that I don't see how you could "disprove" it. You could just as well try to disprove an elementary theorem in number theory or something.
The elementary version I'm talking about is the one in Sakurai
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sakurai%27s_Bell_inequality
The idea is simple: you pick 3 well-chosen axes in a couple of spin-1/2 analysers.
You consider that the population of pairs consists of 8 sub-populations, which are programmed to give (+++), (++-), (+-+) ... (---) for the 3 possible axes at Alice, and the opposite at Bob's. Each pair is randomly drawn from one of these 8 subpopulations, with a priori probabilities P1...P8. P1 + ... + P8 = 1 of course.
It is then shown that there cannot exist 8 positive numbers P1... P8 that will satisfy the statistical outcomes as predicted by quantum mechanics.
This proof is so simple that I don't consider it worth reading any paper that claims the opposite, honestly. You can just as well write a paper arguing that Pythagoras' theorem is wrong in Euclidean geometry, no ?
JesseM said:...<SNIP> ...
QM just gives mathematical functions which tell you the probability of some measurement result(s) given knowledge of some other measurement result(s).
JenniT said:Dear JesseM and vanesch, I agree with Jesse's point above.
Earlier in this thread, vanesch cited Sakurai and http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sakurai%27s_Bell_inequality
I'd be pleased to see the QM probabilities for the eight (8) probabilities (P1-P8) in the cited text.
Can you provide them, please?
Thank you, JenniT
So the above led me to start this thread. For it seems to me that a local realistic counter-example can be put on an equal footing with QM in predicting the Bell inequality to be violated.JesseM said:Those probabilities are for the various hidden-variable states, not for measurable outcomes (you can't measure more than one angle a, b, or c for a given particle). Since QM doesn't say anything about hidden-variable states which may or may not exist, only about measurable outcomes, QM does not assign probabilities to P1-P8. But what Bell shows is that we can imagine any possible combination of probabilities for P1-P8 in a hidden-variable theory (with the probabilities being in the range 0 ≤ Pn ≤ 1 and adding up to 1, of course), and the theory will always predict that the inequality P(a+, b+) ≤ P(a+, c+) + P(c+, b+) will be respected, but QM predicts this inequality is violated.
Most of this case is based on simple maths -- so errors can be easily spotted and agreed, such errors perhaps having important lessons about BT.
So in this OP we set out to:
A: Deliver P1-P8; see Sakurai http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sakurai%27s_Bell_inequality which is our context.
B: Have them summing to unity.
C: Have them fully compatible with QM-style experiments; delivering accepted QM results.
D: Have them recognizing a topology [for want of a better word] associated with the spherical symmetry of the singlet state and measuring-device settings.
E: Have them challenging the basis of Bell's inequality.
F: Have them based on nothing more than high-school maths and logic; so no fancy maneuvers are involved -- and the discussion should be understood by most everyone.
NOTATION: The following short-hand notation is used.
Angles: ab denotes the angle between the orientations a and b, etc.
Functions: Cab denotes cos^2 s(ab), where s is the intrinsic spin of the relevant particle; here, as in Sakurai, s = 1/2; Sab denotes sin^2 s(ab); etc.
Reference orientation: Orientation c is taken as the reference orientation; so orientations a and b are defined with reference to c. This reference orientation arises from Bohr's responses to EPR, neatly captured in Jammer (The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: The Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics in Historical Perspective, 1974): "And just as the choice of a different frame of reference in relativity affects the result of a particular measurement, so also in quantum mechanics the choice of a different experimental setup has its effects on measurements, for it determines what is measurable."
Probabilities based on a local realistic hidden-variable analysis -- that theory not addressed here -- (P1-P8 identifiers after Sakurai, see above):
P1 = Cac.Cbc/2
P2 = Sac.Sbc/2
P3 = Cac.Sbc/2
P4 = Sac.Cbc/2
P5 = Sac.Cbc/2
P6 = Cac.Sbc/2
P7 = Sac.Sbc/2
P8 = Cac.Cbc/2
CONTINUATION: The reader should ascertain that the above Ps sum to one, yielding outcomes fully compatible with QM-style experiments; i.e., delivering accepted QM results.
PROVISO: Note that, in this example, the outcome-probabilities attaching to the ab settings are averages over the two ab possibilities. This follows from the topological fact re spatial relations here: ab may be constructed in two ways:
(1) ab = ac + bc.
(2) ab = ac - bc.
FOR DISCUSSION: It seems to me that this example of Bell's theorem is similar to a triangle-inequality where we can only ever measure two sides of any triangle (i.e., use a or b or c as the reference frame); see JesseM's comment above re QM and P1-P8. So any inference to a third side will be misleading. This is illustrated above where the ac and bc results are definitive because we took c as the datum; the ab result not so.
Which raises the question of the relevance of Bell's theorem to local realism? The above P1-P8 are based on a local realistic hidden-variable analysis; and yield relevant experimental outcomes; the HVs taken to be the orientation (in 3-space) of the total angular momentum of each particle, the particles pairwise correlated in the spherically symmetric singlet state.
And to this extent, the above analysis is on an equal footing with QM: Both predict that the Bell inequality will be violated.
E and OE,
JenniT
Last edited: