Quantum mechanics and classical physics

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of quantum mechanics and its differences from classical mechanics. It is mentioned that whenever the action of a system is of the order of Planck's constant, quantum behavior is observed. The principle of superposition is highlighted as a key difference between the two theories. The existence of irreducible superpositions of product states is also discussed, along with the EPR paper and the debate about the reality of values of non-commuting observables versus the Bohr complementarity principle. The conversation also delves into the topic of spin and its classical counterparts, with some references provided. The incompatibility of classical and quantum mechanics is mentioned, with examples such as the Kochen-Specker theorem and Feynman's G
  • #1
jhe1984
100
0
Hi,

I was wondering if there is a standard "margin of error" concerning the level of divergence from classical physics we see when looking at atoms and particles in a quantum context. That is, I know it is the case that we can't pinpoint the exact next location of a particle, but is it the case that there is a general "range" that our predictions can become relatively accurate?

This might be a very fundamental point but I'm a newcomer.

Thanks.

JHE
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Whenever the action of the system you are considering is of the order of Planck's constant, you will generally get quantum behaviour. Although there are several quantum effects which have literally no classical counterpart, such as entanglement, spin etc.

edit: in fact the fact that the operators commute isn't that interesting - we have the canonical commutation relations in classical mechanics too. The most important point about QM is that we have amplitudes for systems which are complex numbers, and we add them and then only use their absolute value. This is, if you think about it, a very silly thing to do, but it works beautifully.
 
  • #3
masudr said:
Whenever the action of the system you are considering is of the order of Planck's constant, you will generally get quantum behaviour. Although there are several quantum effects which have literally no classical counterpart, such as entanglement, spin etc.

edit: in fact the fact that the operators commute isn't that interesting - we have the canonical commutation relations in classical mechanics too. The most important point about QM is that we have amplitudes for systems which are complex numbers, and we add them and then only use their absolute value. This is, if you think about it, a very silly thing to do, but it works beautifully.
Indeed, entanglement has no classical counterpart, but spin has (I know Feynman said it didn't but he has proven to be wrong there). The edit is a bit crazy: non commuting observables are at the hart of quantum mechanics (the classical Poisson bracket has nothing to do with ``observation´´, while the commutator obviously has). This issue gave rise to the famous 1935 EPR paper where Einstein Podolsky and Rosen argued the incompletess of quantum mechanics by providing a setup in which one could know the values of two non commuting observables at the *same* time through retrodiction (a possiblity Heisenberg himself was also aware of).
 
  • #4
The principle of superposition is at the heart of quantum mechanics. That's what gives it the marked difference from classical mechanics. The value of [itex]\hbar[/itex] does define the scale at which quantum effects are important, but it doesn't modify the quantum effects in any way. The commutator is not what gave rise to the EPR paper; instead it was the principle of superposition which lead to that.
 
  • #5
Careful said:
Indeed, entanglement has no classical counterpart, but spin has (I know Feynman said it didn't but he has proven to be wrong there)
What's classical about spin? Can you show me this proof?
 
  • #6
masudr said:
The principle of superposition is at the heart of quantum mechanics. That's what gives it the marked difference from classical mechanics. The value of [itex]\hbar[/itex] does define the scale at which quantum effects are important, but it doesn't modify the quantum effects in any way. The commutator is not what gave rise to the EPR paper; instead it was the principle of superposition which lead to that.
To be exact, it was the existence of irreducible superpositions of productstates which, when applied in a rather special situation, led to the debate about the reality of values of non commuting observables versus the Bohr complementarity principle (with its instantaneous wave function collapse). My comment was mainly about your claim that noncommuting operators aren't very interesting. The commutator did indeed not lead to the EPR paper, but was seriously involved in its outcome.
 
  • #7
Galileo said:
What's classical about spin? Can you show me this proof?
There exist some classical theories of spin which have very close *resemblance* to the properties of quantummechanical spin (as for example the correct gyromagnetic factor for the electron/Feynman claimed that no classical theory would be able to produce the number of two here). In classical GR, you might look at rotating Kerr charged shell models (see Rosquist 2004 on the Arxiv and references therein). If you want to, I dig up more, but to my knowledge there does not exist yet a full classical theory of spin which is known to reproduce ALL the EXPERIMENTAL results. However, the reasons why a classical theory of spin would not exist are shown to be incorrect. In the same way, it is not known to my knowledge that all the Feynman GEDANKEN experiments (with three SG apparatus in a row) do actually give the correct result (if someone would know the contrary and could provide me with references, I would be glad to receive those). It is however known that all evidence for spin is INDIRECT (ie SG experiments with electrons give no indication whatsoever) and one might conjecture that spin only occurs due to EM interactions in a multi particle bound state (actually some classical approaches are based upon this idea - I seem to remember that Bohr himself held this idea for quite some time).
 
  • #8
Careful said:
However, the reasons why a classical theory of spin would not exist are shown to be incorrect.

I'm pretty sure that is incorrect. There is a very nice article by David Mermin in which he shows a couple of configurations that simply cannot be described by classical physics. I'll try to find the reference.

Another, older and somewhat more complicated demonstration of the incompatibility of classical and QM is the Kochen-Specker theorem. I seem to remember that it was formulated in terms of spins, but that it has a more general applicability.

In the same way, it is not known to my knowledge that all the Feynman GEDANKEN experiments (with three SG apparatus in a row) do actually give the correct result

Maybe the exact experiments he depicts have not been performed, but *all* experiments in which people have applied the same rules he used come out as predicted by QM.
 
  • #9
masudr said:
The most important point about QM is that we have amplitudes for systems which are complex numbers, and we add them and then only use their absolute value.
The situation may be less clear-cut, and QM does not necessarily require complex amplitudes (or complex wavefunctions). Example (Shroedinger, Nature (1952), v.169, p.538): for any solution of the equations of the Klein-Gordon-Maxwell electrodynamics (a scalar charged field \psi interacting with electromagnetic field) there exists a physically equivalent solution with a real (not complex) field, which can be obtained from the original solution by a gauge transform. Thus, the entire range of physical phenomena described by the Klein-Gordon-Maxwell electrodynamics may be described using real fields only. Shroedinger's comment: "That the wave function ... can be made real by a change of gauge is but a truism, though it contradicts the widespread belief about 'charged' fields requiring complex representation."
 
  • #10
ahrkron said:
I'm pretty sure that is incorrect. There is a very nice article by David Mermin in which he shows a couple of configurations that simply cannot be described by classical physics.

Really, I am curious for this NO GO proof.

**Another, older and somewhat more complicated demonstration of the incompatibility of classical and QM is the Kochen-Specker theorem. I seem to remember that it was formulated in terms of spins, but that it has a more general applicability. **

The Kochen Specker theorems ASSUME a very particular -and entirely inadequate- view on reality (and measurement)! I know these theorems too (as well as their unfortunate impact), they are entirely worthless in my opinion (I am aware of the setup with 127 Stern Gerlach detectors - I thought that number got even better recently). No offense, but you should better read the FINEPRINT of theorems (I am not some silly person who is just proclaiming his hopes for local realism). Moreover, it is *not* the task of a classical theory of spin to be *equivalent* to the quantum mechanical one, it should simply explain the experimental outcome (and that is all).

** Maybe the exact experiments he depicts have not been performed, but *all* experiments in which people have applied the same rules he used come out as predicted by QM **

That is rather obvious ! The Dirac equation has been specifically DESIGNED for those particular experiments.
 
  • #11
akhmeteli said:
The situation may be less clear-cut, and QM does not necessarily require complex amplitudes (or complex wavefunctions). Example (Shroedinger, Nature (1952), v.169, p.538): for any solution of the equations of the Klein-Gordon-Maxwell electrodynamics (a scalar charged field \psi interacting with electromagnetic field) there exists a physically equivalent solution with a real (not complex) field, which can be obtained from the original solution by a gauge transform. Thus, the entire range of physical phenomena described by the Klein-Gordon-Maxwell electrodynamics may be described using real fields only. Shroedinger's comment: "That the wave function ... can be made real by a change of gauge is but a truism, though it contradicts the widespread belief about 'charged' fields requiring complex representation."
Good remark. It is clear that you can do that locally, but I assume you have to be very careful doing this when considering the Bohm Aharonov effect (where you get topological winding numbers). Your real wave equation would contain a term with a dirac function somewhere I guess.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Careful said:
It is clear that you can do that locally, but I assume you have to be very careful doing this when considering the Bohm Aharonov effect (where you get topological winding numbers). Your real wave equation would contain a term with a dirac function somewhere I guess.
I agree, extra care never hurts:-), but I believe that if we can do it locally, we can do it globally, provided we are talking about single-valued wave functions. In fact, what are we doing? If we have a wave function \psi=a*\exp(i*b), where a and b are real functions, then we replace \psi with a and add the 4-gradient of b times a constant to the 4-potential of electromagnetic field. If the gradient of b is singular somewhere, it is singular locally there as well. If \psi is continuous, problems may arise in the points where \psi=0. For example, if \psi approximately equals \rho*\exp(i*(\phi+\omega*t)) in the vicinity of such point, where \rho and \phi are the polar coordinates with the center in this point, and t is time, then the 4-gradient of b equals (\omega, 0, \frac{1}{\rho},0), where the last three components are spatial cylindrical coordinates. So we do have a singularity in the 4-potential, however its contribution to electromagnetic fields vanishes. Perhaps more serious problems can arise, say, if you have a singular distribution of charge or current, which is often considered in the context of the Aharonov-Bohm effect.
 
  • #13
akhmeteli said:
I agree, extra care never hurts:-), but I believe that if we can do it locally, we can do it globally, provided we are talking about single-valued wave functions. In fact, what are we doing? If we have a wave function \psi=a*\exp(i*b), where a and b are real functions, then we replace \psi with a and add the 4-gradient of b times a constant to the 4-potential of electromagnetic field. If the gradient of b is singular somewhere, it is singular locally there as well. .
No, it is a bit more subltle than that: *psi* is gobally twice differentiable (that is no problem) but your *b* is not necessarily single valued (if the problem were in 2D - then I would say there is a branch were b down = b up + 2*n*pi with n a natural number). Gauging b away would involve dirac distributions...
 
  • #14
Careful said:
No, it is a bit more subltle than that: *psi* is gobally twice differentiable (that is no problem) but your *b* is not necessarily single valued (if the problem were in 2D - then I would say there is a branch were b down = b up + 2*n*pi with n a natural number). Gauging b away would involve dirac distributions...
What I tried to say is the following: if the situation you describe does have place, there will be points in the infinitesimal vicinity of which this problem arises as well (e.g., if there are branches in 2D, then there is at least one branching point). That is why I said: if we can do it locally, we can do it globally. Because if we cannot do it globally, there must be (I believe) a point where it cannot be done locally. Where I was wrong - in the example that I gave I overlooked that the fields are zero only outside of the zero of the coordinat system (so the fields do represent distributions). I stand corrected.
 

FAQ: Quantum mechanics and classical physics

What is the difference between quantum mechanics and classical physics?

Quantum mechanics is a branch of physics that studies the behavior of particles at the atomic and subatomic level, while classical physics deals with the behavior of larger objects. Quantum mechanics uses mathematical equations to describe the probabilistic nature of particles, while classical physics uses Newtonian laws to describe the motion of objects.

How does quantum mechanics challenge our understanding of reality?

Quantum mechanics introduces the concept of superposition, where particles can exist in multiple states simultaneously. This challenges the classical notion of particles having a definite position and state at all times. Additionally, quantum mechanics also demonstrates the phenomenon of entanglement, where particles can be connected in such a way that their properties are dependent on each other, even when separated by large distances.

What is the role of uncertainty in quantum mechanics?

Uncertainty is a fundamental principle in quantum mechanics that states it is impossible to know the exact position and momentum of a particle simultaneously. This is due to the probabilistic nature of particles at the quantum level. The Heisenberg uncertainty principle quantifies this relationship, stating that the more accurately we know the position of a particle, the less accurately we can know its momentum and vice versa.

How does quantum mechanics explain the behavior of atoms and molecules?

Quantum mechanics provides a framework for understanding the behavior of atoms and molecules by describing how particles interact with each other and their surrounding environment. It explains phenomena such as electron energy levels, chemical bonding, and the emission and absorption of light. Without quantum mechanics, we would not have a complete understanding of these fundamental processes.

Can quantum mechanics and classical physics be reconciled?

There have been attempts to reconcile the principles of quantum mechanics and classical physics, such as the theory of quantum decoherence. However, there are fundamental differences in the two theories that make it difficult to fully reconcile them. Most scientists believe that, rather than trying to merge the two, we should continue to use both theories in their respective domains of applicability.

Similar threads

Back
Top