Back up a step, before Bell's theorem

In summary: This is an interesting question. In summary, nonlocality is the apparent ability of particles to maintain the same state, regardless of whether or not they are being measured. It is apparently believed that this occurs because of the way quantum interference effects work.
  • #1
TedS
3
0
Hi, think of me as an armchair philosopher I suppose, who is very interested in the science of quantum right now.

Bell's theorem led to a finding of nonlocality. I need to back up a step and ask, why. Why is it apparently believed that particles don't have a definite state until they are measured? I can easily accept that we don't know any of their state until we measure them, but why don't they have that same state regardless? I am sort of lucky right now, in that it makes perfect sense to me that entangled particles, when measured, are found to have the same spin, etc. I suppose the right answer to my question will disabuse me of my comfort level :)

It's something to do with those interference patterns I suppose; maybe I just didn't get something. But isn't it possible for a particle to have state, and "simply" not be revealing it? Wouldn't that be a nice finding? (i.e., for those of you who don't really want to believe in nonlocality, nor in many worlds.) How is it disproven?

Thank you in advance for any responses, that can better my understanding.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
philosophy

Hello Ted and Welcome!

Here's my personal comment.
Others may disagree.

TedS said:
Why is it apparently believed that particles don't have a definite state until they are measured? I can easily accept that we don't know any of their state until we measure them, but why don't they have that same state regardless?

IMO a key question to ask is:

How can you possibly distinguish the "particles definite state" from your information about this state? :)

The way I see it, the distinction your are somehow trying to make from first impressions, seems to lack realistic basis.

All you can do without actually performing a measurement, is to ponder the set of "possible answers" you expect to get to a specific question. And this is exactly what QM is about.

This is I think, chould be very plausible even to a philosopher.

This may seem superficial, but if you think again. On what information are all your desicions and actions based? I presume on the information you have at hand, right? If you are badly informed, you make bad decisions. The conclusion itself might be dead one, but starting with a flawed premise, the inductions will be similarly affected.

Perhaps the basis of physical interactions at subatomic level can be understood in terms of responses to local information? All subsystmes in nature, respond to the environment based on their expectations, not on what is correct. There isn't even a sensible notion of objective measure of correct!

The closest you get is the "collective opinion".

The obsession to find out what things "really are" may be totally uncalled for! Simply because MAYBE all interaction in nature, are ruled by relative information anway! This suggest means that information is more fundamental than ontological backgrounds.

Objectivity may still emerge as a result of everybody and everything evolving together. Clearly agreement is more constructive, disagreement is destructive and inconsistecies simply aren't preserved in evolution.

/Fredrik
 
  • #3
An good example of the principle is game theory and economy.

Everybody know how strange the stock market is. The exchange rate of a company stock is not determined by the "real value" of the company, or what is going on at the company floor. It is largely determined by the market actors, expectations on this company! And what they THINK the case is, and is going to be, with this company.

So understanding modern economy, is as much to understand the expectations of the actors on each other! Its' bascailyl about the dynamics of mutual expectations.

This insight, is IMO, no too unlike the one in modern physics, especially if you see it from the philosophical perspective.

/Fredrik
 
Last edited:
  • #4
TedS said:
Bell's theorem led to a finding of nonlocality. I need to back up a step and ask, why.
Bell's two famous papers on this should answer your question.

Quantum nonlocality can be inferred without Bell's theorem through interpretation of what the physical meaning of the quantum theory might be.

Quantum nonlocality might or might not correspond to some sort of superluminal motion in the physical world. No one knows, and, as far as anyone does know, this is an unanswerable question.

Anyway, strictly speaking, quantum nonlocality refers to instantaneous-action-at-a-distance which is physically meaningless.
TedS said:
Why is it apparently believed that particles don't have a definite state until they are measured?
None of the models which involve definite pre-measurement states can account for all of the experimental data. That is, afaik anyway, all existing classical models are inadequate to a certain extent.

Does this mean that there are no definite pre-measurement states? As far as viable extant models are concerned ... yes. As far as nature is concerned ... no one knows -- and quantum theory doesn't provide any precise qualitative way of talking about what happens between emission and detection.


TedS said:
I can easily accept that we don't know any of their state until we measure them, but why don't they have that same state regardless?
There's just no way to know what is actually, qualitatively occurring in the deep reality beneath the level of the instruments.

As far as anyone can be concerned there's no way to objectively talk about definite physical particle states aside from the qualitative experimental results.

Quantum states are not (at least not necessarily) real physical states. They're part of the mathematical apparatus that's been developed to account for and relate the results of quantum experiments. They weren't intended to be a physical description of deep quantum reality -- and how or where quantum theory might actually correspond to reality beneath the instrumental level, hidden from our senses, is unknown (and if the principles of orthodox quantum theory are correct then it's unknowable).

TedS said:
I am sort of lucky right now, in that it makes perfect sense to me that entangled particles, when measured, are found to have the same spin, etc. I suppose the right answer to my question will disabuse me of my comfort level :)
Quantum entanglement is (apparently) a product of physical traits shared by spatially separated disturbances. These shared traits are produced via common origin, past interaction, or the imparting of a common torque (etc.) to spatially separated disturbances.

So, it should make sense to you that, for example, the angular momenta of opposite moving disturbances produced by the same atomic transition should be related so as to produce predictable, coincidental spin or polarization results.

TedS said:
It's something to do with those interference patterns I suppose; maybe I just didn't get something. But isn't it possible for a particle to have state, and "simply" not be revealing it? Wouldn't that be a nice finding? (i.e., for those of you who don't really want to believe in nonlocality, nor in many worlds.) How is it disproven?

Thank you in advance for any responses, that can better my understanding.
Keep in mind that certainly much of and maybe most of the quantum world has not been revealed to us.

There are some qualitatively definite physical things happening in that deep reality. It would be absurd to say otherwise. But so far physics has a very incomplete comprehension of just what those things might be.
 
Last edited:
  • #5
TedS said:
Bell's theorem led to a finding of nonlocality. I need to back up a step and ask, why. Why is it apparently believed that particles don't have a definite state until they are measured? I can easily accept that we don't know any of their state until we measure them, but why don't they have that same state regardless?
You could assume that, but what Bell's theorem proved was that you can't explain the statistics of different particles by assuming they have preexisting states which are influenced only by events in their past light cone--the only way to explain the statistics using hidden states is to imagine that a measurement of one particle can change the other particle's hidden state in an FTL manner (as I understand it this is essentially what's going on in the Bohmian interpretation of QM). For more on how Bell's theorem proves this, you might want to read this thread and this one.
 
  • #6
Wow, everyone, what awesome replies! It's great to find such an active site, that shares a key interest. I will enjoy reading each one, carefully, and readng those links also. It'll take me a little while.
 
  • #7
TedS said:
But isn't it possible for a particle to have state, and "simply" not be revealing it? Wouldn't that be a nice finding? How is it disproven?

Thank you in advance for any responses, that can better my understanding.

Welcome to PhysicsForums!

Ted, what you are describing is called "Realism". This was a position held by many scientists, including Einstein. Many of those same scientists, also including Einstein, believed that "action-at-a-distance" was not position. They therefore believed in "Locality". This was pre-Bell, of course, as your thread title mentions.

But it turns out that the "realistic" assumption has ramifications that were overlooked prior to Bell's 1964 paper. Consider the idea that photon spin is definite, but not revealed, as you describe. Then you would probably agree to something like the following:

Where Match(angle, angle) represents the likelihood of getting the same answer - either two "yes" or two "no". MisMatch(angle, angle) represents the likelihood of getting the different answers - one "yes" and one "no".

[1] Match(0 degrees,67.5 degrees) >= 0%

That's an easy one to agree to, all we are saying is that sometimes they will match and sometimes they won't.

If you can accept that, and you are a "realist", then you also believe that there is a definite, but unrevealed value, for 45 degrees as well. You believe in the existence of definite values for 3 angles (or more) simultaneously. Occasionally, the value at that angle (45 degrees) would either match the other two, or it would be different. Even if it was rarely different than the other two, its likelihood would always be in the range of 0% to 100%. Again, seems very simple and innocuous.

[2] Match(0 degrees,67.5 degrees) where also MisMatch(0 degrees, 45 degrees)
>= 0%


So all that is saying is that the various combinations of selecting 3 angles to consider are greater than or equal to 0%. That should be true of any combination of possible outcomes. That is, if you are a realist.

I won't repeat Bell's proof here - you can read it elsewhere or see the exact proof at my website - but it turns out that:

If Quantum Mechanics is correct, then the value of [2] above is actually LESS THAN ZERO, a seemingly impossible result. In fact the value turns out to be -10.36%. Experiments show that QM is correct. Therefore, you must reject the idea that there are definite values at 3 angles simultaneously.

Bell's Theorem and Negative Probabilities shows the proof, which is fully equivalent to the standard Bell proof.
 
Last edited:

Related to Back up a step, before Bell's theorem

1. What is Bell's theorem and why is it important?

Bell's theorem is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics that states that certain quantum systems cannot be explained by a local hidden variable theory. It is important because it challenges the classical idea of cause and effect and has implications for our understanding of reality and the possible existence of hidden dimensions.

2. What does it mean to "back up a step" before Bell's theorem?

To "back up a step" before Bell's theorem means to examine the foundations of quantum mechanics before considering Bell's theorem. This includes understanding the principles of superposition, entanglement, and the uncertainty principle.

3. Why is it necessary to back up a step before Bell's theorem?

It is necessary to back up a step before Bell's theorem because understanding the foundations of quantum mechanics is crucial for comprehending the implications of Bell's theorem. Without a solid understanding of these principles, it is difficult to fully grasp the significance of Bell's theorem.

4. What are some common misconceptions about Bell's theorem?

One common misconception about Bell's theorem is that it proves the existence of hidden variables or a deterministic universe. In reality, Bell's theorem suggests that the universe may not be deterministic and that there may be hidden variables at play, but it does not provide concrete evidence for either of these ideas.

Another misconception is that Bell's theorem disproves Einstein's theory of relativity. While it does challenge certain aspects of relativity, the two theories can coexist and do not necessarily contradict each other.

5. How does Bell's theorem impact our understanding of the universe?

Bell's theorem has significant implications for our understanding of the universe, particularly in the realm of quantum mechanics. It challenges our traditional understanding of cause and effect and suggests that there may be hidden dimensions or variables at play that we cannot fully comprehend. It also has implications for the development of quantum technologies and the potential for quantum computing.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
32
Views
878
Replies
50
Views
4K
Replies
80
Views
4K
  • Quantum Physics
7
Replies
220
Views
19K
Replies
1
Views
984
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
48
Views
5K
Replies
1
Views
808
Replies
58
Views
805
Replies
93
Views
5K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
47
Views
4K
Back
Top