Bohmian Prediction of Bell Inequality Violations

  • I
  • Thread starter Amadeo
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Variables
In summary, the paper discusses how Bohmian mechanics, an interpretation of quantum mechanics, can predict violations of Bell inequalities. It explores the implications of these predictions for understanding quantum entanglement and non-locality, suggesting that Bohmian trajectories provide a deterministic framework that aligns with experimental evidence showing discrepancies from classical physics. The authors argue that this perspective enriches the discourse on reality in quantum mechanics and the nature of correlations observed in entangled particles.
  • #36
stevendaryl said:
In my opinion the equivalence between Bohmian mechanics and standard QM is not as trivial as that.

Let me take as standard QM the following recipe (I think due to Von Neumann):
  1. We describe the system we are interested in as a wave function (or more generally, a density matrix, but I'm going to assume a pure state here).
  2. We let the wave function evolve under Schrodinger's equation until the time of measurement.
  3. We perform a measurement, which gives an eigenvalue of the operator corresponding to the observable being measured.
  4. The probability for each possible value is given by the Born rule (the square of the amplitude corresponding to that value)
  5. Afterwards, we use a collapsed wave function for future measurements.
The Bohmian model was created to give exactly the same results as this recipe except for two differences:

Point A: at step 3, the Bohmian model was only constructed to be equivalent to the standard recipe in the special case in which the experimenters measure particle positions.

Point B: the Bohmian model doesn't have step 5.

I can certainly believe that it's true that the Bohmian model makes the same predictions as the standard recipe, but because of points A and B, demonstrating this seems far from trivial. I know the hand-wavy argument that all measurements ultimately boil down to position measurements (or we can make it so, by arranging the experiment so that systems go one direction if they are in one state and a different direction if they are in another state).

Point B is, I think, complicated to prove rigorously. Suppose you have a multipart measurement. For example, we have two entangled particles, and we measure one property of one particle and then at a later time, we measure a different property of the other particle. The recipe above would say that we collapse the wave function at the first measurement, and then use the collapsed wave function to compute probabilities for the second measurement. An alternative approach is to consider the two measurements as a single compound measurement. Then we only need to apply the Born rule to the compound measurement, and we don't need the collapse rule. So the compound measurement approach would (I assume) give the same result as the Bohmian model (if point A is taken care of). But it's nontrivial (at least, I don't know of a trivial proof) to show that the one at a time measurements with a collapse in the middle gives the same result as the single compound measurement.
The business of collapse seems to me to be an ambiguity in the application of Bohmian mechanics. The wave function in Bohmian mechanics serves double duty: (1) It provides a "quantum potential" term to the equations of motion for a particle, and (2) Its square gives the initial probability distribution of the particle.

If you do a two-part measurement on a particle, then after the first measurement, you now have more information about where the particle is than you did at the beginning. That means that the probability distribution has changed. Does this additional information change the wave function? If so, then there is a collapse-like effect in Bohmian mechanics, as well. If not, then the correspondence between wave function and probability distributions would be broken.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
stevendaryl said:
If so, then there is a collapse-like effect in Bohmian mechanics, as well.
I have discussed something like this point with @Demystifier previously. He agreed that Bohmian Mechanics is contextual in addition to its usual description as nonlocal. I would say that contextuality implies a "collapse-like effect", which would then occur nonlocally in BM.

Of course, he'll probably prefer to weigh in on that himself. :smile:
 
  • #38
stevendaryl said:
Let me take as standard QM the following recipe (I think due to Von Neumann):
  1. We describe the system we are interested in as a wave function (or more generally, a density matrix, but I'm going to assume a pure state here).
  2. We let the wave function evolve under Schrodinger's equation until the time of measurement.
  3. We perform a measurement, which gives an eigenvalue of the operator corresponding to the observable being measured.
  4. The probability for each possible value is given by the Born rule (the square of the amplitude corresponding to that value)
  5. Afterwards, we use a collapsed wave function for future measurements.
You are missing the crucial part here, the entanglement with wave function of the measuring apparatus (or the environment). This is absolutely essential if you want to understand the von Neumann theory of measurement, the theory of decoherence, the many-world interpretation, and/or the Bohmian interpretation. Without that, in particular, you cannot understand where the effective collapse in Bohmian mechanics comes from, even though there is no true collapse. See e.g. my "Bohmian mechanics for instrumentalists", or my lecture http://thphys.irb.hr/wiki/main/images/e/e6/QFound4.pdf
 
  • #39
stevendaryl said:
at step 3, the Bohmian model was only constructed to be equivalent to the standard recipe in the special case in which the experimenters measure particle positions.
Kinda sorta. The Bohmian way of describing this is that all measurements end up coming down to measurements of particle positions. For example, if we measure the spin of a spin-1/2 particle using a Stern-Gerlach apparatus, our measurement result is ultimately where the particle is detected on the detector screen downstream of the S-G magnet. So we're really measuring a position, and then inferring a spin from it.
 
  • Like
Likes Doc Al
  • #40
DrChinese said:
I would say that contextuality implies a "collapse-like effect", which would then occur nonlocally in BM.
Contextuality arises due to entanglement with wave function of the measuring apparatus. The wave function of the measuring apparatus is also the most important thing to understand the "collapse-like effect". In fact, I claim, the entanglement with wave function of the measuring apparatus is the most underappreciated thing in all of quantum theory. It is so essential for proper understanding of quantum theory, and yet so few physicists are aware of that.
 
  • #41
Demystifier said:
You are missing the crucial part here, the entanglement with wave function of the measuring apparatus (or the environment). This is absolutely essential if you want to understand the von Neumann theory of measurement, the theory of decoherence, the many-world interpretation, and/or the Bohmian interpretation. Without that, in particular, you cannot understand where the effective collapse in Bohmian mechanics comes from, even though there is no true collapse. See e.g. my "Bohmian mechanics for instrumentalists", or my lecture http://thphys.irb.hr/wiki/main/images/e/e6/QFound4.pdf
My point is that it isn't trivial to show that the Bohmian model reproduces the same results as standard QM. It isn't an immediate consequence of the model's construction.

The operative word here is "trivial". I'm not denying that it's true, but I am denying that it's trivially true.:wink:
 
Last edited:
  • #42
stevendaryl said:
My point is that it isn't trivial to show that the Bohmian model reproduces the same results as standard QM. It isn't an immediate consequence of the model's construction.
Presumably, the work of showing that Bohmian mechanics is equivalent to standard QM, including the apparent collapse, is probably the same work in showing that MWI makes the same predictions as standard QM. That isn't obvious, either, because MWI doesn't have collapse, either.
 
  • #43
This actually relates to @PeterDonis claim (in another thread) that by definition, different interpretations of QM must have the same observable consequences. I think that for what's called different interpretations of QM, there actually can be different predictions, but for all practical purposes, it's impossible to observe the differences. For example, collapse versus no-collapse interpretations can in principle make different predictions, because no-collapse interpretations predict the possibility of interference effects involving macroscopically different alternatives. In practices, decoherence makes it impossible to measure such interference.
 
  • #44
stevendaryl said:
That isn't obvious, either, because MWI doesn't have collapse, either.
Collapse in standard QM, i.e., independent of any interpretation, is just a mathematical step that is taken after the result of a measurement is known, in order to make further predictions. This step is taken when using the MWI or the Bohmian interpretation. Where those interpretations differ from others is in how they explain why that mathematical step works, i.e., allows us to make accurate further predictions.

Some examples:

Copenhagen: Asking what happens "in reality" is a meaningless question. All we have is the mathematical machinery we use to make predictions. In that machinery, we apply the collapse postulate once we know the result of a measurement because that is what we have observed, empirically, to work.

"Objective collapse" interpretations: The mathematical step of applying the collapse postulate once we know the result of a measurement works because an actual, physical collapse process happens when a measurement result is determined.

MWI: The mathematical step of applying the collapse postulate once we know the result of a measurement works because decoherence separates the different "worlds" so they can't interfere with each other, and any observation of a particular result for a measurement limits all further predictions based on that observation to the particular "world" in which that result occurred. So the predictions obtained by applying the collapse postulate only apply to one particular branch of the wave function, not all of it.

Bohmian: Observing a measurement result doesn't change the wave function or the particle positions, but it does reveal information about them that was previously unknown. The mathematical step of applying the collapse postulate once we know the result of a measurement is the way we capture the information revealed by observing the measurement result in order to constrain our further predictions.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and DrChinese
  • #45
stevendaryl said:
My point is that it isn't trivial to show that the Bohmian model reproduces the same results as standard QM. It isn't an immediate consequence of the model's construction.

The operative word here is "trivial". I'm not denying that it's true, but I am denying that it's trivially true.:wink:
OK, but do you think it's true? And if you do, why don't you explain, in your own words, why it is true?
 
  • #46
stevendaryl said:
It isn't an immediate consequence of the model's construction.
It is if you include the required initial statistical distribution of particle positions in "the model's construction".
 
Back
Top