- #36
- 8,943
- 2,949
The business of collapse seems to me to be an ambiguity in the application of Bohmian mechanics. The wave function in Bohmian mechanics serves double duty: (1) It provides a "quantum potential" term to the equations of motion for a particle, and (2) Its square gives the initial probability distribution of the particle.stevendaryl said:In my opinion the equivalence between Bohmian mechanics and standard QM is not as trivial as that.
Let me take as standard QM the following recipe (I think due to Von Neumann):
The Bohmian model was created to give exactly the same results as this recipe except for two differences:
- We describe the system we are interested in as a wave function (or more generally, a density matrix, but I'm going to assume a pure state here).
- We let the wave function evolve under Schrodinger's equation until the time of measurement.
- We perform a measurement, which gives an eigenvalue of the operator corresponding to the observable being measured.
- The probability for each possible value is given by the Born rule (the square of the amplitude corresponding to that value)
- Afterwards, we use a collapsed wave function for future measurements.
Point A: at step 3, the Bohmian model was only constructed to be equivalent to the standard recipe in the special case in which the experimenters measure particle positions.
Point B: the Bohmian model doesn't have step 5.
I can certainly believe that it's true that the Bohmian model makes the same predictions as the standard recipe, but because of points A and B, demonstrating this seems far from trivial. I know the hand-wavy argument that all measurements ultimately boil down to position measurements (or we can make it so, by arranging the experiment so that systems go one direction if they are in one state and a different direction if they are in another state).
Point B is, I think, complicated to prove rigorously. Suppose you have a multipart measurement. For example, we have two entangled particles, and we measure one property of one particle and then at a later time, we measure a different property of the other particle. The recipe above would say that we collapse the wave function at the first measurement, and then use the collapsed wave function to compute probabilities for the second measurement. An alternative approach is to consider the two measurements as a single compound measurement. Then we only need to apply the Born rule to the compound measurement, and we don't need the collapse rule. So the compound measurement approach would (I assume) give the same result as the Bohmian model (if point A is taken care of). But it's nontrivial (at least, I don't know of a trivial proof) to show that the one at a time measurements with a collapse in the middle gives the same result as the single compound measurement.
If you do a two-part measurement on a particle, then after the first measurement, you now have more information about where the particle is than you did at the beginning. That means that the probability distribution has changed. Does this additional information change the wave function? If so, then there is a collapse-like effect in Bohmian mechanics, as well. If not, then the correspondence between wave function and probability distributions would be broken.