Cartesian Products and Families of Sets .... Searcoid, Section 1.2 .... ....

In summary, Searcoid discusses the concept of a product of sets, and explains that it is represented by a family of sets with unique identifiers. He goes on to explain that when defining a product, one must take into account the fact that some sets in the family may be identical. He also provides a definition for the co-domain of a function, and explains that the image of a function may be smaller than the set of all possible choices.
  • #1
Math Amateur
Gold Member
MHB
3,998
48
I am reading Micheal Searcoid's book: "Elements of Abstract Analysis" ... ...

I am currently focused on understanding Chapter 1: Sets ... and in particular Section 1.2 Relations and Functions ...

I need some help in fully understanding some remarks by Searcoid in his sub-section on products ...

The subsection on products reads as follows:View attachment 7513
https://www.physicsforums.com/attachments/7514
In the above text by Searcoid we read the following:

" ... ... Suppose \(\displaystyle (X_i)_{ i \in I }\) is a family of sets . Then \(\displaystyle \bigcup (X_i)\) is a set by Axiom IV, whence \(\displaystyle ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I\) is a set by (1.2.11) and \(\displaystyle \{ x \in ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I \ \lvert \ \forall j \in I , x_j \in X_j \}\) ... ... "I do not understand the form and nature of \(\displaystyle ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I\) ... ... what is meant by this? Can someone please give a simple and clear explanation ... and perhaps an example or two ...

Further, likewise I do not understand the form and nature of \(\displaystyle \{ x \in ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I \ \lvert \ \forall j \in I , x_j \in X_j \}\) ... ... again, what is meant by this? Can someone please give a simple and clear explanation ... and perhaps an example or two ... Help will be much appreciated ... ...

Peter=========================================================================================Section 1.2.11 is mentioned in the above quote ... so I am proving the text of the same ... as follows:https://www.physicsforums.com/attachments/7515
View attachment 7516Searcoid's sub-section on families of sets may also be relevant so I am providing the same ... as follows:https://www.physicsforums.com/attachments/7517
https://www.physicsforums.com/attachments/7518
Hope someone can help ...

Peter
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Hi Peter,

I will try to explain this at an intuitive, although not rigorous, level.

If $A$ and $B$ are sets, $A^B$ represents the set of functions from $B$ to $A$. The notation is justified by the fact that, if both sets are finite, with $|A|=m$ and $|B|=n$, then $A^B$ is a set of $m^n$ elements.

When we are trying to define the Cartesian product of a family of sets, we must take into account the fact that some of these sets may be identical. For example, if we look at $A\times A$, we cannot simply consider the set $\{A,A\}$, because this is just $\{A\}$ : in a set, each element occurs exactly once. We must somehow be able to distinguish the first $A$ from the second $A$.

To do this, instead of considering simply a set of sets, we consider a family of sets. We must assume that each set in the family is uniquely identified by some label or index; the set of indexes, denoted by $I$ in this case, is called the indexing set. We write $X_i$ for the set corresponding to the index $i\in I$, and we denote the family by $(X_i)_{i\in I}$. Note that:
  • The same set may occur more than once in the family: we may have $X_i = X_j$ for $i\ne j$.
  • In many examples, you would have $I=\{1, 2, \dots\}$, but $I$ can be any set, even an uncountable set like $\mathbb{R}$. Here, to illustrate the concepts, I will only use the first case, but the possibility of the second case is one of the reasons for this elaborate definition.

We want elements of the Cartesian product to be the analog of ordered tuples. This means that, for each element of the Cartesian product, we must take one element for each set in the family. Now, a set $X_i$ of the family is identified by its index $i$, and we will denote the corresponding element by $x_i$, with $x_i\in X_i$.

This means that, for each index $i$, we choose exactly one element $x_i$. This is the definition of a function $f$ defined on the set $I$, such that $f(i)=x_i$.
The co-domain of that function is the set of all possible elements to choose from, and this is $\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$. This shows that we have a function $f:I\to\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$, and the set of all these functions is $\left(\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i\right)^I$, as explained at the beginning of this answer.

If, for example, $I = \{1, 2, \dots\}$ an element of the Cartesian product would be a function defined on $I$ such that $f(i) = x_i\in X_i$, and we can write that simply as a sequence $(x_1, x_2,\dots)$.

Note that, altough the co-domain of $f$ is the whole set $\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$ (the set of all possible choices for the $x_i$), the image of $f$ may be smaller if the sets are not all the same. Indeed, we can only take $x_i$ in the corresponding set $X_i$, and this explains the definition $\{ x \in ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I \ \lvert \ \forall j \in I , x_j \in X_j \}$.

Does this begin to clarify things ? Feel free to write back if you require further help.
 
  • #3
castor28 said:
Hi Peter,

I will try to explain this at an intuitive, although not rigorous, level.

If $A$ and $B$ are sets, $A^B$ represents the set of functions from $B$ to $A$. The notation is justified by the fact that, if both sets are finite, with $|A|=m$ and $|B|=n$, then $A^B$ is a set of $m^n$ elements.

When we are trying to define the Cartesian product of a family of sets, we must take into account the fact that some of these sets may be identical. For example, if we look at $A\times A$, we cannot simply consider the set $\{A,A\}$, because this is just $\{A\}$ : in a set, each element occurs exactly once. We must somehow be able to distinguish the first $A$ from the second $A$.

To do this, instead of considering simply a set of sets, we consider a family of sets. We must assume that each set in the family is uniquely identified by some label or index; the set of indexes, denoted by $I$ in this case, is called the indexing set. We write $X_i$ for the set corresponding to the index $i\in I$, and we denote the family by $(X_i)_{i\in I}$. Note that:
  • The same set may occur more than once in the family: we may have $X_i = X_j$ for $i\ne j$.
  • In many examples, you would have $I=\{1, 2, \dots\}$, but $I$ can be any set, even an uncountable set like $\mathbb{R}$. Here, to illustrate the concepts, I will only use the first case, but the possibility of the second case is one of the reasons for this elaborate definition.

We want elements of the Cartesian product to be the analog of ordered tuples. This means that, for each element of the Cartesian product, we must take one element for each set in the family. Now, a set $X_i$ of the family is identified by its index $i$, and we will denote the corresponding element by $x_i$, with $x_i\in X_i$.

This means that, for each index $i$, we choose exactly one element $x_i$. This is the definition of a function $f$ defined on the set $I$, such that $f(i)=x_i$.
The co-domain of that function is the set of all possible elements to choose from, and this is $\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$. This shows that we have a function $f:I\to\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$, and the set of all these functions is $\left(\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i\right)^I$, as explained at the beginning of this answer.

If, for example, $I = \{1, 2, \dots\}$ an element of the Cartesian product would be a function defined on $I$ such that $f(i) = x_i\in X_i$, and we can write that simply as a sequence $(x_1, x_2,\dots)$.

Note that, altough the co-domain of $f$ is the whole set $\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$ (the set of all possible choices for the $x_i$), the image of $f$ may be smaller if the sets are not all the same. Indeed, we can only take $x_i$ in the corresponding set $X_i$, and this explains the definition $\{ x \in ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I \ \lvert \ \forall j \in I , x_j \in X_j \}$.

Does this begin to clarify things ? Feel free to write back if you require further help.
Castor28 ... I am most grateful for this helpful and informative post ... thanks!

I am now reflecting on what you have written ...

... will certainly write back if I have further issues ...

Thanks again for your help!

Peter
 
  • #4
castor28 said:
Hi Peter,

I will try to explain this at an intuitive, although not rigorous, level.

If $A$ and $B$ are sets, $A^B$ represents the set of functions from $B$ to $A$. The notation is justified by the fact that, if both sets are finite, with $|A|=m$ and $|B|=n$, then $A^B$ is a set of $m^n$ elements.

When we are trying to define the Cartesian product of a family of sets, we must take into account the fact that some of these sets may be identical. For example, if we look at $A\times A$, we cannot simply consider the set $\{A,A\}$, because this is just $\{A\}$ : in a set, each element occurs exactly once. We must somehow be able to distinguish the first $A$ from the second $A$.

To do this, instead of considering simply a set of sets, we consider a family of sets. We must assume that each set in the family is uniquely identified by some label or index; the set of indexes, denoted by $I$ in this case, is called the indexing set. We write $X_i$ for the set corresponding to the index $i\in I$, and we denote the family by $(X_i)_{i\in I}$. Note that:
  • The same set may occur more than once in the family: we may have $X_i = X_j$ for $i\ne j$.
  • In many examples, you would have $I=\{1, 2, \dots\}$, but $I$ can be any set, even an uncountable set like $\mathbb{R}$. Here, to illustrate the concepts, I will only use the first case, but the possibility of the second case is one of the reasons for this elaborate definition.

We want elements of the Cartesian product to be the analog of ordered tuples. This means that, for each element of the Cartesian product, we must take one element for each set in the family. Now, a set $X_i$ of the family is identified by its index $i$, and we will denote the corresponding element by $x_i$, with $x_i\in X_i$.

This means that, for each index $i$, we choose exactly one element $x_i$. This is the definition of a function $f$ defined on the set $I$, such that $f(i)=x_i$.
The co-domain of that function is the set of all possible elements to choose from, and this is $\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$. This shows that we have a function $f:I\to\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$, and the set of all these functions is $\left(\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i\right)^I$, as explained at the beginning of this answer.

If, for example, $I = \{1, 2, \dots\}$ an element of the Cartesian product would be a function defined on $I$ such that $f(i) = x_i\in X_i$, and we can write that simply as a sequence $(x_1, x_2,\dots)$.

Note that, altough the co-domain of $f$ is the whole set $\bigcup_{i\in I}X_i$ (the set of all possible choices for the $x_i$), the image of $f$ may be smaller if the sets are not all the same. Indeed, we can only take $x_i$ in the corresponding set $X_i$, and this explains the definition $\{ x \in ( \bigcup (X_i) )^I \ \lvert \ \forall j \in I , x_j \in X_j \}$.

Does this begin to clarify things ? Feel free to write back if you require further help.

Hi Castor28 ... thanks again for your help ... you clarified things a great deal ...Now ... based on what I have understood from your post we have ... (I think ...? ... please comment ,,,)\(\displaystyle ( \bigcup ( X_i ))^I = \{ x \ \mid \ I \rightarrow \bigcup ( X_i ) \}\)

... ... where \(\displaystyle x\) is a function or a set of ordered pairs no two of which have the same first member ... ...Now ... in the set \(\displaystyle \prod_i X_i = \{ x \in ( \bigcup ( X_i ))^I \ \mid \ \forall j \in I , \ x_j \in X_j \} \)we have that ...\(\displaystyle x_j = x(j)\) is the value of the function \(\displaystyle x\) at \(\displaystyle j\)so we would have the following (for a finite Cartesian Product ... and where, for example we take \(\displaystyle I \) as the set \(\displaystyle \{1,2, \ ... \ ... \ n \}\) )\(\displaystyle x(1) = x_1 \in X_1\), \(\displaystyle x(2) = x_2 \in X_2\), ... ... ... \(\displaystyle x(n) = x_n \in X_n\).Therefore the set/function \(\displaystyle x\) is the following set of ordered pairs ... ...\(\displaystyle x = \{ (1, x_1), (2, x_2), \ ... \ ... \ ... \ (n, x_n) \}\)and the function \(\displaystyle x\) constitutes one element belonging to \(\displaystyle \prod_i X_i\) ... ...Other elements come from other functions \(\displaystyle y, z,\) ... ... belonging to the set \(\displaystyle ( \bigcup ( X_i ))^I\) ... ... Is the above interpretation of Searcoid correct?Somehow I think it would have been more 'natural' if we had arrived at an element \(\displaystyle x\) of \(\displaystyle \prod_i X_i\) having the form of a \(\displaystyle n\)-tuple ... ... \(\displaystyle (x_1, x_2, \ ... \ ... \ ... \ x_n)\) rather than a set of ordered pairs ... can you comment ...

... BUT ... ... the aim of the exercise, I think, is to show that the Cartesian Product is a set ...is that a correct interpretation of what Searcoid is doing? ... can you comment ...Thanks again for your help ...

Peter
 
Last edited:
  • #5
Hi Peter,

Yes, your interpretation is correct.

Somehow I think it would have been more 'natural' if we had arrived at an element \(\displaystyle x\) of \(\displaystyle \prod_i X_i\) having the form of a \(\displaystyle n\)-tuple ... ... \(\displaystyle (x_1, x_2, \ ... \ ... \ ... \ x_n)\) rather than a set of ordered pairs ... can you comment ...

The interpretation as ordered $n$-tuples is more natural, but you need a formal definition of an $n$-tuple to prove that is it a set. The usual way to define the ordered pair $(a,b)$ is $\{\{a\},\{a,b\}\}$, which is already cumbersome; this could be extended to a finite $n$-tuple, but it would not be very practical.

The alternative way to define an $n$-tuple is as a function, which is what we did here. In the case of sequences (finite or infinite), these definitions are equivalent. However, as I mentioned, you can define Cartesian products of uncountable families. In that case, the function approach is still valid, but the ordered $n$-tuple representation does not make sense. For example, $\prod_{i\in\mathbb{R}}X_i$, where $X_i= \mathbb{R}$ is the Cartesian product of copies of $\mathbb{R}$ indexed by $\mathbb{R}$ (this is just the set of functions from $\mathbb{R}$ to itself). You cannot represent an element as an ordered $n$-tuple or an infinite sequence.

... BUT ... ... the aim of the exercise, I think, is to show that the Cartesian Product is a set ...is that a correct interpretation of what Searcoid is doing? ... can you comment ...

I looks like it. However, as I don't have the book, I cannot guess the intentions of the author: this should be interpreted in the context of the rest of the book.
 
  • #6
castor28 said:
Hi Peter,

Yes, your interpretation is correct.
The interpretation as ordered $n$-tuples is more natural, but you need a formal definition of an $n$-tuple to prove that is it a set. The usual way to define the ordered pair $(a,b)$ is $\{\{a\},\{a,b\}\}$, which is already cumbersome; this could be extended to a finite $n$-tuple, but it would not be very practical.

The alternative way to define an $n$-tuple is as a function, which is what we did here. In the case of sequences (finite or infinite), these definitions are equivalent. However, as I mentioned, you can define Cartesian products of uncountable families. In that case, the function approach is still valid, but the ordered $n$-tuple representation does not make sense. For example, $\prod_{i\in\mathbb{R}}X_i$, where $X_i= \mathbb{R}$ is the Cartesian product of copies of $\mathbb{R}$ indexed by $\mathbb{R}$ (this is just the set of functions from $\mathbb{R}$ to itself). You cannot represent an element as an ordered $n$-tuple or an infinite sequence.
I looks like it. However, as I don't have the book, I cannot guess the intentions of the author: this should be interpreted in the context of the rest of the book.
Thanks castor28 ... really appreciate your help and guidance ...

I now have a much better understanding of the issues of my initial post ...

Thanks again.

Peter
 

FAQ: Cartesian Products and Families of Sets .... Searcoid, Section 1.2 .... ....

What is a Cartesian product?

A Cartesian product is a mathematical operation that takes two sets and combines them to create a new set. This new set contains all possible ordered pairs of elements from the two original sets.

How is a Cartesian product represented?

The Cartesian product is represented using the symbol "x". For example, if set A = {1, 2} and set B = {a, b}, then the Cartesian product A x B = {(1, a), (1, b), (2, a), (2, b)}.

What is the cardinality of a Cartesian product?

The cardinality of a Cartesian product is equal to the product of the cardinalities of the two original sets. In other words, if set A has m elements and set B has n elements, then the Cartesian product A x B will have m x n elements.

How is a Cartesian product different from a union of sets?

A Cartesian product combines elements from two different sets to create new ordered pairs, while a union of sets combines all elements from both sets without creating ordered pairs.

What is the relationship between Cartesian products and families of sets?

A family of sets is a collection of sets, and the Cartesian product can be applied to any two sets in the family. This allows for the creation of new sets within the family, and the process can be repeated multiple times to create larger and more complex families of sets.

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Back
Top