- #1
- 8,520
- 16
Discussion continued from [post=3248292]this post[/post] on another thread...
The reason 1) and 2) apply to classical EM is that if you specify the local electromagnetic field vector at every point in a region of spacetime (along with local properties of any particles in that region), that's a complete specification of the physical state of that region as far as EM is concerned, and the state of any point can only be causally influenced by the state of regions in the past light cone of that point. So if you have spacetime regions 1,2,3 as illustrated on this page of Bell's paper, and A represents the outcome of some experiment in region 1 with detector setting a while B represents the outcome of some experiment in region 2 with detector setting b, while c represents a complete specification of the local variables (here electromagnetic field vectors and particles) at every point in region 3 (Bell also uses λ to represent the state of hidden variables in region 3 but we don't need that here), then P(A|B,a,b,c) should be equal to P(A|a,c), equivalent to the step Bell makes in going from equation 6.9.2 to 6.9.3 on this page. In other words, if you already know the information c about region 3 then your estimate of the probability of A occurring in region 1 should in no way change given additional knowledge about the result B from a region 2 at a spacelike separation from 1. Again, tell me if you disagree with any of this. If not you should agree that P(A,B|a,b,c)=P(A|a,c)*P(B|b,c), and from this you can derive a Bell inequality (the CHSH inequality) just as Bell does in the paper.
Bell's proof does not involve any notions of "particles" or "waves" whatsoever, it only involves observed experimental results combined with the idea that the theory generating them is local realistic. Again, do you agree or disagree that according to my definition of "local realism" in 1) and 2) (which seems to be the same as Bell's definition of local causality in the "nouvelle cuisine" paper), classical electromagnetism would be a local realistic theory?A. Neumaier said:His particles are local but e/m waves are not.
The reason 1) and 2) apply to classical EM is that if you specify the local electromagnetic field vector at every point in a region of spacetime (along with local properties of any particles in that region), that's a complete specification of the physical state of that region as far as EM is concerned, and the state of any point can only be causally influenced by the state of regions in the past light cone of that point. So if you have spacetime regions 1,2,3 as illustrated on this page of Bell's paper, and A represents the outcome of some experiment in region 1 with detector setting a while B represents the outcome of some experiment in region 2 with detector setting b, while c represents a complete specification of the local variables (here electromagnetic field vectors and particles) at every point in region 3 (Bell also uses λ to represent the state of hidden variables in region 3 but we don't need that here), then P(A|B,a,b,c) should be equal to P(A|a,c), equivalent to the step Bell makes in going from equation 6.9.2 to 6.9.3 on this page. In other words, if you already know the information c about region 3 then your estimate of the probability of A occurring in region 1 should in no way change given additional knowledge about the result B from a region 2 at a spacelike separation from 1. Again, tell me if you disagree with any of this. If not you should agree that P(A,B|a,b,c)=P(A|a,c)*P(B|b,c), and from this you can derive a Bell inequality (the CHSH inequality) just as Bell does in the paper.
Which Bell inequality are you saying is violated?A. Neumaier said:My slides contain a setting in which the Bell inequalities can be violated although everything is described by the classical Maxwell equations. So whatever Bell's arguments are, they cannot be valid in this setting.