- #36
- 14,343
- 6,834
Yes, Eq. (42) is the Schmidt decomposition.comote said:Maybe I am missing something, but isn't equation (42) just the Schmidt decomposition?
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Schmidt_decomposition
Yes, Eq. (42) is the Schmidt decomposition.comote said:Maybe I am missing something, but isn't equation (42) just the Schmidt decomposition?
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Schmidt_decomposition
This, of course, is wrong, but if you are convinced that it is right, don't waste your time with us. Publish your new important result in a respectable journal, which will make you famous; you will destroy Bohmian interpretation, many-world interpretation, and theory of decoherence at once.andreab1987 said:Since in real measurements the eigenfunctions of the electron momentum are not eigenfunctions of the interaction hamiltonian, the value of c_q(t=0) is different from c_q(t), which means that the two probabilities are different.
In other words, the de-broglie bohm theory does not reproduce the standard quantum mechanics results (as it is said also in eq. 39). Since experiments confirm standard quantum mechanics, this is again sufficent to prove that both "quantum theory of measurement" and hidden variable theories are wrong.
Demystifier said:Yes, Eq. (42) is the Schmidt decomposition.
Demystifier said:I gave you some arguments, but you ignored them.
Let me also note that Eq. (42) plays an important role in decoherence theory, which, by the way, is an observational fact. If you don't know about decoherence, see e.g.
http://xxx.lanl.gov/pdf/quant-ph/0312059 [Rev.Mod.Phys.76:1267-1305,2004]
which is published in a VERY respectable journal, and has MANY citations. Pay particular attention to Eq. (2.1).
Demystifier said:But in (42) v does not need to be the wave function of the electron before the measurement. Instead, v_i are BASIS states in which the wave function of the electron before the measurement can be expanded.
Demystifier said:This, of course, is wrong, but if you are convinced that it is right, don't waste your time with us. Publish your new important result in a respectable journal, which will make you famous; you will destroy Bohmian interpretation, many-world interpretation, and theory of decoherence at once.
Decoherence is an experimental fact!andreab1987 said:You seem not to understand that pratically all physicists use only standard quantum mechanics and consider hidden variables, bohemian mechanics, dechoerence, many worlds only as phylosofical speculations, and not as scientific theories.
andreab1987 said:No it isn't.
In fact Schmidt theorem says that:
For any vector v in the tensor product , there exist orthonormal sets u and v ...
this means that the two orthonormal sets are in general different for any different vector v; in other words they depend on the choice of v, but there are no fixed orthonormal sets which can be used for every vector v.
In the case of eq. 42 the orthonormal sets is chosen with eigenvectors of the operator A corresponding to the quantity to be measured; so this orhonormal sets does not depend on the vector v, i.e. the wave function of the electron.
comote said:I see what you are saying, but I don't see where he is doing that. One could do the decomposition for each time and then normalize it at each time. I am not a fan of Bohmian Mechanics but I do want to understand where exactly it differs from standard QM.
andreab1987 said:You seem not to understand that pratically all physicists use only standard quantum mechanics and consider hidden variables, bohemian mechanics,
dechoerence,
many worlds only as phylosofical speculations, and not as scientific theories.
I came here with sincere interest to understand if there was something good in hidden variables theories, but I have understood that such theories are totally inconsistent and based on serious mistakes.
comote said:OK, so the error is in saying that the $\psi$ in eqn 42 and the $\psi$ in eqn 40 are the same?
This is certainly an error, but whose error? Certainly not of the author of Eqs. (40) and (42), because there is no claim in the paper that they are the same.comote said:OK, so the error is in saying that the $\psi$ in eqn 42 and the $\psi$ in eqn 40 are the same?
Have you seen the lirics after the Abstract ofyoda jedi said:Interesting...
bohemian mechanics
...lol... bohemian mechanics
Fair enough! ALL equations of standard QM are also equations of BM. In particular, whatever andreab may say, (42) IS an equation of standard QM. (In fact, decoherence can be thought of as an indirect EXPERIMENTAL proof that (42) is correct.)comote said:I am not a fan of Bohmian Mechanics but I do want to understand where exactly it differs from standard QM.
Demystifier said:This is certainly an error, but whose error? Certainly not of the author of Eqs. (40) and (42), because there is no claim in the paper that they are the same.
Jesus, I cannot believe that I have to explain this, but ...andreab1987 said:Actually the author claims they are the same; in fact read the first line after eq. 41
"According to standard QM, the probability of finding the state to have the value a of the observable Aˆ is equal to ..."
and then read the 5th line after eq. 42
"The probability for this to happen is, according to (42), ...
In fact, during a mathematical proof, you cannot change the meaning of the same symbols or functions.
By the way, if psi_a were not the same in eq. 40 and 42, the autor's proof would makes no sense at all.
Demystifier said:Jesus, I cannot believe that I have to explain this, but ...
the author uses the fact that c_a(t) and psi_a(x) are the same functions in both (40) and (42). Yet, he does not say that psi(x,t) in (40) is equal to Psi(x,y,t) in (42). Note the dependence on y in (42) absent in (40)!
Demystifier said:Jesus, I cannot believe that I have to explain this, but ...
the author uses the fact that c_a(t) and psi_a(x) are the same functions in both (40) and (42). Yet, he does not say that psi(x,t) in (40) is equal to Psi(x,y,t) in (42). Note the dependence on y in (42) absent in (40)!
Yes, I insist on that ...comote said:If you insist that the $\psi_a(x)$ in equations (40) and (42) are the same
For a general interaction between two subsystems, you are right that $\chi_a(y)$ do not need to be mutually orthogonal. But is it possible that, for some SPECIAL interaction, $\chi_a(y)$ turn out to BE orthogonal? I hope you can agree that it is possible.comote said:then you can not say that the $c_a(t)\chi_a(y)$ are orthogonal
Demystifier said:Have you seen the lirics after the Abstract of
http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/physics/0702069 [Am.J.Phys.76:143-146,2008] ?
comote said:I am not a fan of Bohmian Mechanics but I do want to understand where exactly it differs from standard QM.
SQM - wf Collapse - Non Linear.yoda jedi said:Bohmian Mechanics - Non Linear.
SQM - Linear.
Fine, it works for one specific choice of the measured observable A only.comote said:It seems to me, that you are still picking the [tex]\psi_a(x)[/tex] beforehand. Yes it would work, for one specific set of eigenvectors on a given product state, but not any measurement.
Demystifier said:And all this does not depend at all on hidden variables.
Demystifier said:SQM - wf Collapse - Non Linear.
RUTA said:At least that's what they told me here at the Hiley Symposium this week.
No, what I said IN THE POST ABOVE, does not depend on superluminal information exchange.RUTA said:But it does depend on superluminal information exchange, even in its Lorentz invariant manifestations. At least that's what they told me here at the Hiley Symposium this week.
SQM - wf collapse, but no modelyoda jedi said:SQM - wf Collapse.
which one ? specific model please...
Demystifier said:SQM - wf collapse, but no model
GRW, Penrose (or some other) specific model - no SQM
By SQM, I meant SQM with collapse, but without mathematical description of collapse in terms of a precise model. Instead, collapse is introduced as a vague postulate. Something like: "When a measurement is performed, the wave function collapses to an eigenstate of the measured observable."yoda jedi said:you mean SQM without collapse ?
Demystifier said:By SQM, I meant SQM with collapse, but without mathematical description of collapse in terms of a precise model. Instead, collapse is introduced as a vague postulate. Something like: "When a measurement is performed, the wave function collapses to an eigenstate of the measured observable."
The measurement I am talking here about is known also under the name non-demolition measurement:Demystifier said:Fine, it works for one specific choice of the measured observable A only.
But then for another choice of the observable B (B not equal to A), I choose ANOTHER basis [tex]\varphi_b(x)[/tex], so instead of (40) now I can write
[tex]\psi(x,t) = \sum_b d_b(t) \varphi_b(x) [/tex]
To measure B (rather than A) I have to apply a different interaction, so now (42) will no longer be true. Instead, with that different interaction, instead of (42) I will have
[tex]\Phi(x,z,t) = \sum_b d_b(t) \varphi_b(x) \xi_b(z)[/tex]
This is different from (42). Yet, it has the same FORM as (42).
The physical point is that there is no measurement without interaction, and each kind of measurement requires a different kind of interaction. Consequently, each kind of measurement will lead to a different wave function. Yet, as long as each of these measuremts is "ideal", the wave function after the interaction always takes the FORM (42).
And all this does not depend at all on hidden variables.