Exploring Foundations of Quantum Mechanics & QFT

In summary: Quantum field theory (the standard model, say) has very different interpretational questions hardly discussed by anyone, since it is too difficult for most, and the experts have more pressing problems to solve.Quantum theory is a general framework, with many sub-theories such QM, QFT, string theory, loop quantum gravity, etc. The problem of interpretation (the measurement problem, ontology, etc.) is inherent to the quantum theory as a whole. This problem is most easily expressed in QM because it is the simplest of the sub-theories, but the problem is there in other sub-theories as well.Could you clarify that a bit? Are these interpretational questions somehow connected with those of
  • #36
A. Neumaier said:
Which means that what really exists is uncertain (and as you inply, unknowable) . But then the notion of existence is a matter of speculation only (there is no way to decide), and one can as well do without it.
No. It is simply the same situation as with physical theories in general. The really true theory about everything is yet unknown. Together with this theory, it is also unknown what really exists. Potentially we may fail to identify the really true theory about everything. And, as a consequence, we will also fail to identify what really exists. (This is not unknowable, that would be too strong, but we can never be certain that we have identified the correct one if we have identified such a candidate for this.)

But this does not mean that it is speculation only. The theory of what really exists is part of the theory of everything, which is a physical theory which makes testable predictions.

Can one live with theories which are not realistic? As long as they make predictions, one can. If the predictions made are supported by empirical evidence, one can live with astrology too. But realistic theories have some some additional structure, the ontology, and some restrictions following from this, say, the evolution equations for really existing things should be well-defined and should not depend on things which do not really exist. Such restrictions for realistic theories are useful as guides for theory development. Compare this with the Lagrange formalism. Can classical theories survive without a Lagrange formalism? Certainly. Many theories don't have a Lagrange formalism. But if there exists a possibility, one will not simply ignore this, but prefer the variant which has a Lagrange formalism. Same here. We can live with theories which are not realistic, like Copenhagen QT. But if there is a realistic interpretation, we will prefer it.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
Elias1960 said:
what really exists. (This is not unknowable
How would you objectively decide whether you know?
Elias1960 said:
But this does not mean that it is speculation only. The theory of what really exists is part of the theory of everything, which is a physical theory which makes testable predictions.
What are the testable predictions of your Bohmian field ontology? Testable is only the part that is in the QFT books, and that has nothing to do with Bohmian mechanics.
Elias1960 said:
But realistic theories have some some additional structure, the ontology, and some restrictions following from this [...] Such restrictions for realistic theories are useful as guides for theory development.
Which such restriction follow from your Bohmian field ontology? I don't know any that would have guided quantum field theory development.
 
  • #38
A. Neumaier said:
But ontology in Bohmian mechanics is also relative to which fundamental configuration space is assumed for the universe. Which is strange since different configuration spaces (N-particles or fields) imply very different notions of what really exists.

An auxiliary thining tool that just helps to gain some intuition about quantum processes is not an ontology but a crutch. Most phycisists do not need such a crutch and still have enough intuition about quantum processes to turn them into technolocical successes.
I agree. Most physicists don't need the Bohmian crutch. But all physicists need some crutch, i.e. they need some more-or-less intuitive interpretation to have in mind because, in reality, no human physicist is a shut-up-and-calculate machine. So all physicists need a crutch, while physicists who construct various interpretations in general, and versions of Bohmian mechanics in particular, are crutch designers. Most physicists are satisfied with their old crutch and are not interested in learning how to use new ones, but those who learn how to use some new crutch (Bohmian or otherwise) would never change it for the old ones.
 
Last edited:
  • #39
Elias1960 said:
The theory of what really exists is part of the theory of everything, which is a physical theory which makes testable predictions.

I don't see how you can make this claim without knowing the theory of everything, which nobody does.
 
  • #40
A. Neumaier said:
How would you objectively decide whether you know?
I would not, I do not even plan to. Because I have some basic education in philosophy (scientific methodology) which tells me that we cannot verify our theories. We can only falsify them. Everything else (simplicity, predictive power, beauty, compatibility with principles like causality, realisms, and so on) may be useful as guiding my choices, but cannot be decisive. So I know that I cannot objectively find out if the theory I actually prefer is true.
A. Neumaier said:
What are the testable predictions of your Bohmian field ontology? Testable is only the part that is in the QFT books, and that has nothing to do with Bohmian mechanics.
No, it is also part of Bohmian mechanics. All the quantum predictions follow from Bohmian mechanics too.
A. Neumaier said:
Which such restriction follow from your Bohmian field ontology? I don't know any that would have guided quantum field theory development.
Of course, once the community which developed the SM has not been guided by BFT, but thoroughly ignored it, it would be very strange if the QFT development would have been nonetheless guided by BFT principles.

What would have plausibly changed if BFT would have been accepted much earlier? Once there is a real configuration space trajectory ##q(t)\in Q##, the average velocity which is part of the continuity equation
$$\partial_t \rho + \nabla (\rho \vec{v}) = 0 $$
which follows from the Schroedinger equation is something really causally influencing q. Once this requires FTL causal influences, one would have started to care about the possibility of some hidden preferred frame, without waiting many years for Bell's theorem and then even more years for all the experiments and even then not accepting the straightforward consequence (and rejecting realism and causality and embracing ... like many worlds). What would have been reached in this direction is, of course, unclear.

But the effective field theory paradigm could have been reached easier. To consider the cutoff at some critical length as a sort of approximation for a real more fundamental theory which really cuts higher momentum has the problem that such a cutoff does not have Lorentz symmetry. So to accept this would require to give up relativistic dreams.
 
  • #41
PeterDonis said:
I don't see how you can make this claim without knowing the theory of everything, which nobody does.
If the theory of everything does not make empirical predictions, nobody will accept it as a physical theory, even less as a theory of everything. (Or at least I hope so, the history of string theory suggests that this may be not the case.) And that it defines an ontology follows from realism. Else, realism would be wrong. In the context of my answer, realism was presupposed.
 
  • #42
Elias1960 said:
No, it is also part of Bohmian mechanics. All the quantum predictions follow from Bohmian mechanics too.
But all these predictions guided theorists without any need of Bohmian mechanics. So there is no additional guiding available from maintaining a Bohmian view. Occam's razor therefore does away with it.

Elias1960 said:
Once there is a real configuration space trajectory ##q(t)\in Q##, the average velocity which is part of the continuity equation
$$\partial_t \rho + \nabla (\rho \vec{v}) = 0 $$
which follows from the Schroedinger equation
But the Schrödinger equation plays no role in relativistic QFT. It is replaced by the representation theory of the Poincare group.
Elias1960 said:
Once this requires FTL causal influences, one would have started to care about the possibility of some hidden preferred frame, without waiting many years for Bell's theorem
But Bell's theorem assumes a preferred frame rather than deriving it. And theorists and experimenters were looking for evidence for preferred frames without any prodding from Bohmian mechnaics. You are full of wishful thinking about the latter's importance.
Elias1960 said:
But the effective field theory paradigm could have been reached easier. To consider the cutoff at some critical length as a sort of approximation for a real more fundamental theory which really cuts higher momentum has the problem that such a cutoff does not have Lorentz symmetry. So to accept this would require to give up relativistic dreams.
Hardly anyone is willing to give up the relativistic paradigm. Effective field theories work quite well within the relativistic paradigm, producing covariant effective fields from covariant underlying fields.
 
Last edited:
  • #43
Elias1960 said:
In the context of my answer, realism was presupposed.

Then you are just arguing in a circle. You can't assume realism and then use that to argue that the theory of everything must be a realist theory.
 
  • Like
Likes EPR
  • #44
If realism failed at the micro scale, what 'ontology' could anyone expect from a non-realist TOE?
 
  • #45
PeterDonis said:
Then you are just arguing in a circle. You can't assume realism and then use that to argue that the theory of everything must be a realist theory.
It was not intended to argue in this direction. The intention was only to explain what realists think. They think that there will be one true theory of everything, and this theory will be realistic, and so this theory will define the true ontology of the universe. All the various different incomplete and with large probability simply wrong theories we have today naturally given only incomplete and with large probability wrong theories about what it the true ontology of the world.

These are simply trivialities about what realists think, but it seemed necessary to describe them given that quite strange statement
This makes ontology model dependent - very strange for supposed realistic foundations, where there should be only one reality...
EPR said:
If realism failed at the micro scale, what 'ontology' could anyone expect from a non-realist TOE?
Of course, none. Even if it does not fail (a failure would require that there is no viable realistic theory/interpretation able to compete with the non-realistic theories, which is actually not the case) one cannot expect the definition of any ontology from a non-realist TOE.
A. Neumaier said:
But all these predictions guided theorists without any need of Bohmian mechanics. So there is no additional guiding available from maintaining a Bohmian view. Occam's razor therefore does away with it.
You don't know, and cannot know, the progress which could have been reached now if theorists after 1952 would have been guided by the Bohmian view. It could have been much larger than what has been reached now. So we have here a quite strange application of Occam's razor: Cut away all research directions which have never been seriously tried, given that we don't know the results they could have reached if seriously tried.
A. Neumaier said:
But the Schrödinger equation plays no role in relativistic QFT. It is replaced by the representation theory of the Poincare group.
Yes. So we have already identified one direction of research which was seriously harmed by the relativistic paradigm. What could have been reached by the development of the Schroedinger picture for QFT? We cannot know. (And according to your version of Occam's razor, we will never know, because research direction which have not given yet much because they were not tried yet have to be rejected forever.)
A. Neumaier said:
But Bell's theorem assumes a preferred frame rather than deriving it.
?
What is assumed in the many variants of Bell-like theorems is always Einstein causality. Then, together with Einstein causality
1.) The EPR criterion of reality, thus, an extremely weak notion of realism.
or
2.) Causality in a version containing Reichenbach's principle of common cause
or recently
3.) Nothing but the objective Bayesian interpretation of probability as the logic of plausible reasoning.

You have to reject them all, not (1) and not (2) and not (3), or, alternatively, you have to return to a preferred frame. So, it is a consequence of the violation of the Bell inequalities. And only one of the possible consequences, you can, as well, conclude that not (1) and not (2) and not (3) holds.
A. Neumaier said:
You are full of wishful thinking about the latter's importance.
No. I know very well that it was not at all important in the development of what we have now. The result is what has to be expected - no progress at all on the fundamental front, all the real progress restricted to more of the same (SM for QED) based on better particle accelerators, and some progress reached by Bell and his followers after seeing, accidentally, the impossible done by Bohm.
A. Neumaier said:
Hardly anyone is willing to give up the relativistic paradigm. Effective field theories work quite well within the relativistic paradigm, producing covariant effective fields from cova[r]iant underlying fields.
I agree. You can, without doubt, cut away all what is in conflict with the relativistic paradigm (which is not something related with experiment, but the metaphysical "there is no preferred frame" hypothesis) and the remains will work nicely too. They will give much less - but so what, your version of Occam's razor makes sure that we will never try what could have been reached following these research direction.

As a consequence, we can hardly expect any progress on the fundamental front. But so what, the SM and GR work fine, the unsolved problems (which will never be solved) will motivate grants going to relativists forever, and Neumaier's razor protects them from competition.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes weirdoguy
  • #46
Elias1960 said:
The intention was only to explain what realists think.

Then your statements should be prefixed with something like "this is what realists think: ..." or "realists believe that...". Stating it the way you did makes it seem like you think it's simply a fact that any interpretation or viewpoint must account for.
 
  • #47
Elias1960 said:
What could have been reached by the development of the Schroedinger picture for QFT?

You're confusing the Schrodinger picture with the Schrodinger equation. The latter is what @A. Neumaier referred to and is obviously non-relativistic. Its relativistic counterpart, the Klein-Gordon equation, was actually discovered first AFAIK, so it doesn't seem appropriate to say it was somehow neglected.

As for the Schrodinger picture in QFT, it is used, though not as much as other methods. See, for example, the work of Symanzik. So we do know what "could have been reached" using it: it's whatever has been done with it up to now.
 
  • Like
Likes A. Neumaier
  • #48
Elias1960 said:
the relativistic paradigm (which is not something related with experiment, but the metaphysical "there is no preferred frame" hypothesis)

No, the "relativistic paradigm" is the belief that Lorentz invariance is fundamental, so our fundamental theories should reflect that. "No preferred frame" is just the simple observation that we have no evidence for one, so there's no need to include one in our theories.
 
  • #49
Elias1960 said:
They will give much less - but so what, your version of Occam's razor makes sure that we will never try what could have been reached following these research direction.

As a consequence, we can hardly expect any progress on the fundamental front. But so what, the SM and GR work fine, the unsolved problems (which will never be solved) will motivate grants going to relativists forever, and Neumaier's razor protects them from competition.

The issue of how grants for scientific research are given or how particular directions of research are decided is way off topic for both this thread and this forum. We have a forum for STEM Career Guidance where topics like the grant and funding process can be discussed.
 
  • #50
Elias1960 said:
What could have been reached by the development of the Schroedinger picture for QFT? We cannot know.
Coleman, Jackiw and others used the Schroedinger picture for QFT to study solitonic degrees of freedom and instantons - without any input from Bohmian mechanics.

On the other hand, what did the Bohmian's do to develop this picture? Nothing at all. They just say that they have a realistic Schrödinger equation interpretation, and leave the rest to others, just as before. They are content to iterate their mantra that there is no need for them to do such work, as you did:
Elias1960 said:
No, it is also part of Bohmian mechanics. All the quantum predictions follow from Bohmian mechanics too.
and Demystifier did:
Demystifier said:
in IBM (instrumental Bohmian mechanics) electrons, photons etc. do not have trajectories. Only fundamental particles have trajectories. But we still can't observe those fundamental particles (we would need a stronger particle collider for that), so in practice we don't need to worry about details of those fundamental particles and their Bohmian trajectories. In practice we can use the standard instrumental QM/QFT, while Bohmian mechanics can be used for a conceptual explanation of those instrumental rules.
Thus we know that Bohmian mechanics (around almost as long as renormalized QED) has no innovative potential in QFT.
 
  • #51
PeterDonis said:
Then your statements should be prefixed with something like "this is what realists think: ..." or "realists believe that...". Stating it the way you did makes it seem like you think it's simply a fact that any interpretation or viewpoint must account for.
Sorry, I thought this was clear from the context of the discussion.
PeterDonis said:
No, the "relativistic paradigm" is the belief that Lorentz invariance is fundamental, so our fundamental theories should reflect that. "No preferred frame" is just the simple observation that we have no evidence for one, so there's no need to include one in our theories.
Agreement about the first sentence. I disagree about the second part. The observation would be "no empirical evidence for a preferred frame", the conclusion would be "no need for a preferred frame", both would essentially differ from "no preferred frame" because the central point of the latter is an explicit rejection of theories with a preferred frame even if they are viable. As we would do if we, following sentence 1, think that relativistic symmetry is fundamental instead of emergent in some large distance approximation.

PeterDonis said:
You're confusing the Schrodinger picture with the Schrodinger equation. The latter is what @A. Neumaier referred to and is obviously non-relativistic. Its relativistic counterpart, the Klein-Gordon equation, was actually discovered first AFAIK, so it doesn't seem appropriate to say it was somehow neglected.
I disagree here. The Klein-Gordon equation can be misunderstood as a "relativistic counterpart" of the Schroedinger equation only for the irrelevant one-particle case.

The Schroedinger equation is simply the evolution equation of the state in the configuration space representation of the Schroedinger picture. It becomes a functional equation if used in QFT. If we regularize it, say, by using a lattice approximation, we have a Schroedinger equation in QFT too, even if the original field equation is relativistic.
PeterDonis said:
As for the Schrodinger picture in QFT, it is used, though not as much as other methods. See, for example, the work of Symanzik. So we do know what "could have been reached" using it: it's whatever has been done with it up to now.
Strange logic. If some guy, famous for quite a lot of other things like the Callan-Symanzik equation and Euclidean field theory, has written 1981 a paper where he shows not much more than that it exists:
We show here that in renormalizable models, the Schrödinger wave functional exists to all orders in perturbation theory, and give what we believe to be strong arguments that the Schrödinger functional differential operator that appears in the Schrödinger equation does so as well
Symanzik, K. (1981). Schrödinger representation and Casimir effect in renormalizable quantum field theory. Nucl. Phys. B 190 [FS3], 1-44
and where he refers to the use of it before 1981 as
Soon after the invention of quantum field theory, its Schrödinger representation was also known, and it has been mentioned since in some textbooks [1]. Calculations, however, were first done in the interaction representation, which is formally related to the Schrödinger representation by a change of basis. Later, covariant four-dimensional formalisms (S-matrix calculus, Green functions, and in particular functional integrals) were used almost exclusively. Even more than the interaction representation, which preserves a certain conceptual role in scattering theory, the Schrödinger representation fell into disrepute, the more so since it seems to have been considered to be non-renormalizable, as the interaction representation indeed is [2, 3].
(so that we can be quite sure that his work before 1981 does not give much too - he would not have forgotten it, so that all what remains would be the few papers up to his death 1983, all of them without indication in the title that they are somehow related with the Schrödinger picture), we already know all what could have been reached by this method?

Ok, there may be other scientists who have used it. But even if that would be 5 or 10 or so, this would be a small minority thing, and if they failed, it would not prove that the method could not have been reached more. Because out of principle there is no way of knowing this if only a few outsiders have tried it. We can be sufficiently sure that string theory failed given the large amount of resources invested into string theory, but even in this case one cannot be certain that all what string theory could reach has been reached.

This type of argument started with Neumaier's statement
Which such restriction follow from your Bohmian field ontology? I don't know any that would have guided quantum field theory development.
So, again, all one can learn from history, from the real development of science, would be:
1.) A failure of what has been actually used by the mainstream to solve problems they tried to solve, as an argument against what used by the mainstream. This failure (QG, TOE) is quite obvious.
2.) A failure of alternative approaches if they would have rejected the use of methods which have actually been used and which have actually reached some success. There is no such rejection of QM/QFT methods related to the Bohmian approach, so this does not work.
3.) Some successes of outsiders who refused to follow the mainstream but have reached something. This exists, Bell's inequality and all what followed.

We can certainly not learn from history anything about the scientific results which could have been reached by alternative paradigms which have not been used by the mainstream, but were restricted to a few outsiders.
 
  • #52
Elias1960 said:
the central point of the latter is an explicit rejection of theories with a preferred frame even if they are viable

In other words, part of your definition of "the relativistic paradigm" is "not working on preferred frame theories". That seems more like a question for the people (if there are any) who are working on preferred frame theories: do they consider themselves to be working in "the relativistic paradigm" or not? I don't really have a preference either way as far as terminology is concerned.

Elias1960 said:
we have a Schroedinger equation in QFT too, even if the original field equation is relativistic

The whole point of Symanzik's work that you so blithely dismiss was to show that the Schrodinger equation in QFT is relativistic, in the sense of being Lorentz invariant, even though the Lorentz invariance is not manifest.

In any case, if you think the "Schrodinger picture", or any other line of research for that matter, is somehow not fully explored, the thing for you to do is to go explore it, not to complain about it here.
 
  • #53
A. Neumaier said:
what did the Bohmian's do to develop this picture? Nothing at all.

Elias1960 said:
We can certainly not learn from history anything about the scientific results which could have been reached by alternative paradigms which have not been used by the mainstream, but were restricted to a few outsiders.

As already noted, arguments about which interpretation, or line of research, or whatever, did or did not help to "develop" something, or whether or not we have "learned from history" are off topic.

Elias1960 said:
This type of argument started with Neumaier's statement

And it ends right now. Any further posts from anyone either dismissing a particular line of research, or complaining that a particular line of research has not gotten enough attention, are off topic and will be summarily deleted. Please keep to the thread topic, which is supposed to be simple factual information about what different QM interpretations say about QFT.
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #54
A. Neumaier said:
Thus we know that Bohmian mechanics (around almost as long as renormalized QED) has no innovative potential in QFT.
Does thermal interpretation has innovative potential in QFT?
 
  • #55
Demystifier said:
Does the thermal interpretation have innovative potential in QFT?
I didn't claim that, and I don't know. It is likely to have impact on the future relation between QM and QFT.

Why do you ask? @Elias60 was talking about the potential impact of Bohmian mechanics on QFT, and I had commented that history proved this impact to be nonexistent.
 
  • #56
A. Neumaier said:
I didn't claim that, and I don't know. It is likely to have impact on the future relation between QM and QFT.

Why do you ask? @Elias60 was talking about the potential impact of Bohmian mechanics on QFT, and I had commented that history proved this impact to be nonexistent.
I think that any interpretation has a potential impact, as long as the interpretation helps someone to get intuitive understanding. It does not need to be explicit in final research papers, because they are usually written in a form that does not depend on interpretation. But the interpretation is hidden in a thinking process that eventually resulted in the research paper.

For instance, in my paper http://de.arxiv.org/abs/1505.04088 I never mention Bohmian mechanics, but my intuition in this paper was significantly influenced by my IBM way of thinking.
 
  • #57
PeterDonis said:
In other words, part of your definition of "the relativistic paradigm" is "not working on preferred frame theories".
Yes.
PeterDonis said:
The whole point of Symanzik's work that you so blithely dismiss was to show that the Schrodinger equation in QFT is relativistic, in the sense of being Lorentz invariant, even though the Lorentz invariance is not manifest.
I blithely dismiss it? I quoted what was claimed, without questioning this claim.
Then, let's see: "relativistic" not found at all, "Lorentz" found once, in the following remark:
For most of our considerations, a plane ##\partial \Gamma## is sufficient, and then, for calculations, dimensional regularization is the most convenient: ##3 - \varepsilon## space dimensions (Re ##\varepsilon > 0##), one (euclidean or minkowskian) time dimension. This is as effective as introducing a lattice in space while keeping time continuous, but by itself does not break Lorentz invariance such that renormalization of the speed of light is not needed.
Does not look like the whole point of the paper, which the author himself describes as "We show here that in renormalizable models, the Schrödinger wave functional exists to all orders in perturbation theory".
In any case, the question what Symanzik has reached seems off-topic too, as well as what Coleman and Jackiw have reached here:
A. Neumaier said:
Coleman, Jackiw and others used the Schroedinger picture for QFT to study solitonic degrees of freedom and instantons - without any input from Bohmian mechanics.
So, let's concentrate on what follows from BM for QFT.

First of all, the BFT approach itself has to be based on a Schrödinger picture of QFT. If it would not exist, that would be bad news for BFT.

Then, it had to identify the correct choice for the configuration space. Different choices would define different, competing lines of development of BFT. So, if (for whatever reasons) the approach based on particle ontology (favored by Duerr et al) fails, those working with the field ontology would not be impressed at all, they would be even happy that their preference for the field ontology appears preferable. (But this choice may differ for bosons and fermions.)

Then, it has to look at the Schrödinger equation. Is it of the type which allows a dBB interpretation? This appears unproblematic. Beyond this, everything else is unproblematic.
A. Neumaier said:
On the other hand, what did the Bohmian's do to develop this picture? Nothing at all. They just say that they have a realistic Schrödinger equation interpretation, and leave the rest to others, just as before. They are content to iterate their mantra that there is no need for them to do such work, as you did:
That's a misinterpretation. The dBB approach does not lead to any restrictions in the use of mathematical methods developed by quantum theory. So, Bohmians will be happy about any progress reached with methods which do not rely on Bohmian trajectories too. They can be used as they are, there is no need to modify them or to reinvent them in some Bohmian version. Once the QM formalism can be derived from BM, all what can be reached based on the QM formalism can be reached using BM too.

This differs from the relativistic paradigm. This paradigm rejects those things which are not manifestly (fundamentally) Lorentz-covariant. So they are acceptable only as mathematical tools, only as long as there is no connection to reality.

To illustrate this, let's look at the role of regularizations. To get rid of the infinities in QFT, one has to regularize it. The usual way is to cut large momentum values. But "large momentum values" is nothing Lorentz-invariant. So, straightforward regularizations are theories which are not Lorentz-covariant. Sometimes one can circumvent this problem and find a regularization which is Lorentz-covariant. Say, one adds some large massive particles, and then invents such interactions with them that all the problematic terms are cancelled. But this are exceptions, not the rule. The most straightforward and simple way to regularize a field theory, a spatial lattice regularization, is obviously not Lorentz-covariant.

Once they are not covariant, they are, from the point of view of the relativistic paradigm, not even candidates for fundamental theories. Their only reasonable role is that of a dirty mathematical tool which allows to compute some intermediate results. These cannot be the final results - one has to consider some limit, which leads to some relativistic, Lorentz-covariant theory, else these intermediate results are worthless, and their agreement with observation is nothing but an unexplained accident.

If we restrict ourselves here to lattice regularization, this Lorentz-covariant limit can be reached only in the continuous limit of the lattice distance to zero. Unfortunately, even for renormalizable theories this limit either does not exist at all (Landau poles) or would be trivial (the interaction becomes zero). But, even if they were very uncomfortable with not having a really well-defined (and started research programs like algebraic QFT to solve these problems) this situation was more or less accepted: One could at least compute relations between the observables which had well-defined limits. Unfortunately, important fields (the gravitational field, and massive gauge fields) did not fit into this scheme. While there was found a way to handle massive gauge fields, there was not found a way to handle gravity.

So, the restrictions imposed by the relativistic paradigm created some problems with the quantization of gravity.

In a BM approach, there would not be any objection against the regularized theories. Any assumption that the theory has to be Lorentz covariant at the fundamental level is foreign to BM and with Bell's theorem it is known that one needs a preferred frame in BM. Instead, one would even require a regularization which reduces the degrees of freedom to a finite number, like lattice regularizations on a large cube do (instead of other regularization procedures like dimensional regularization, where it would be unclear if one could do any BM in the regularized theory). After this, there would be no BM-internal point to consider a continuous limit of that lattice theory. In particular, a lattice regularization of GR would be acceptable, and it would work for large distances (greater than Planck length) without any problems.

The approach which is now accepted by the mainstream is Wilsonian effective field theory: All the SM fields, as well as the field-theoretic version of GR, are only effective field theories. That means, there is some critical length, and below that critical length these theories have to be replaced by unknown different, more fundamental theories. The length is usually assumed to be the Planck length, but in principle it could be a different one.

Aside: Of course, Wilson had nothing to do with BM. At least AFAIK. But behind the Wilsonian approach there is an even more evil paradigm - the ether: There are sufficient similarities between classical condensed matter theories and the field theories of fundamental physics. Let's use these similarities by applying the methods used in one part shamelessly in the other part too. As a result, Wilson was able to apply renormalization techniques developed in fundamental physics for the SM in condensed matter theory and to reach quite nontrivial results there about phase transitions.

In the other direction, the empirical success was less obvious. But if one starts with some fundamental theory at Planck length, where all the imaginable terms would be of the same order, one finds that in the large distance limit the non-renormalizable terms are suppressed much more that renormalizable terms, so that this leads to the quite general prediction that we will observe renormalizable theories, except in the case where none exists, where the leading term will be a heavily suppressed (much weaker) non-renormalizable one. Which is gravity, which is indeed much weaker. So we have here also a qualitative but correct empirical prediction.
 
  • #58
AndreasC said:
Did I accidentally open some kind of can of worms here? That's what I'm sensing... I don't mind, debates are fun I guess...

Yes. Some in the QFT camp* tend to believe that it solves many foundational issues. On the other hand, I think they mostly remain in one form or another, although perhaps they get moved. Following Bell (as an example): QFT MUST be either non-local or non-realistic (or both). And personally, I don't see that double slit interference is any better explained, nor entanglement swapping between particles that have never interacted.

If we are holding the bag on these, then we are still deep in the swamp. Which is why this subforum exists in the first place. :biggrin:* With no objections to anything about QFT itself. And not intending to cast any dispersion on anyone.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC
  • #59
Oh god I just now realized how many new posts there are... For some reason I stopped getting notifications. And I don't even understand half of them lol.
 
  • #60
A. Neumaier said:
But all these predictions guided theorists without any need of Bohmian mechanics. So there is no additional guiding available from maintaining a Bohmian view. Occam's razor therefore does away with it.

OK, so as I've said I don't really know anything about any of this, however if I got what you're trying to say right and aren't misinterpreting you, I don't really agree with that proposal. Sure, results common between other interpretations and the Bohmian interpretation alone won't help you decide the Bohmian one is preferable or whatever (by virtue of them being common), but there isn't really any Occam's razor rule that tells you you must ditch the Bohmian picture because it wasn't involved in the development of QFT. I feel like many people abuse Occam's razor, it's a broad and in many cases ambiguous principle that only helps you filter out unnecessarily convoluted explanations. From what I've seen so far I wouldn't say there is something that sets BM apart as particularly unrealistic or unnecessarily convoluted without any merit compared to others, so I don't think Occam's razor is a good fit here. Maybe you think it is unrealistic and unnecessarily convoluted or whatever (and it may well be, I don't know enough to have an opinion) but that's a separate issue from QFT being developed without it.

Also sorry if my posts are a bit confusing or messy sometimes, English is not my first language.
 
Last edited:
  • #61
Elias1960 said:
If we restrict ourselves here to lattice regularization
This restriction is quite artificial. In particular, you cannot apply it to the standard model. Nobody working on the standard model is using this noncovariant regularization scheme. It is useful only in nonrelativistic QFT and partially in QCD. Even in QCD, there is lots of work done in covariant regularrizations.
AndreasC said:
many people abuse Occam's razor
... just like one can use an ordinary razor to murder someone ...
AndreasC said:
From what I've seen so far I wouldn't say there is something that sets BM apart as particularly unrealistic or unnecessarily convoluted
Well, from a mathematical point of view it is very unnatural and convoluted. It ditches not only relativity but also symplectic geometry (by dropping the symmetry between position and momentum) - both principles that lead to a huge amount of theoretical and practical insight into physics. If Bohmian mechanics were fundamental it would be surprising why these tools should have a place in the theory at all.
 
  • #62
A. Neumaier said:
This restriction is quite artificial. In particular, you cannot apply it to the standard model. Nobody working on the standard model is using this noncovariant regularization scheme. It is useful only in nonrelativistic QFT and partially in QCD. Even in QCD, there is lots of work done in covariant regularrizations.
You cannot apply? Sorry, no, you can apply. There would be simply no point of doing it if all what you want is to shut up and calculate. Please, just accept that for doing different things different technical means are appropriate. If it is easier to compute integrals with dimensional regularization, fine, let's use dimensional regularization if we want to compute those integrals. But if we want to understand why all this can be done on a certain mathematically well-defined base, then the simplest choice if a lattice regularization on a large cube, which gives you a finite-dimensional theory.

And if all you want is to shut up and calculate, minimal QM is fine, and the measurement problem or Schroedinger's cat is simply irrelevant. If you, instead, want an interpretation which does not give rubbish if applied to Schroedinger's cat, then it is better to have a continuous trajectory $q(t)\in Q$. Given that the Schroedinger equation gives you a continuity equation for ##|\psi(q)|^2##, this is not a problem at all. But with such a continuous trajectory you can describe the collapse by using the Schroedinger equation for the system and the measurement device, and then use the visible trajectory of the measurement device to compute the resulting effective wave function of the system.
$$\psi_{eff}(q_{sys}) = \psi_{full}(q_{sys}, q_{dev}(t)).$$
A. Neumaier said:
Well, from a mathematical point of view it is very unnatural and convoluted. It ditches not only relativity but also symplectic geometry (by dropping the symmetry between position and momentum) - both principles that lead to a huge amount of theoretical and practical insight into physics. If Bohmian mechanics were fundamental it would be surprising why these tools should have a place in the theory at all.
Very simple - once you can derive them starting from the theory, they have a place there. Mathematics is full of such surprises.

As someone who knows particle theory you should be aware how useful approximate symmetries are - even once they, as approximate symmetries, have no fundamental status at all, they can give as well huge amounts of theoretical and practical insights into physics, not? The question if some symmetry is useful has nothing to do with if it is fundamental or only emergent.
 
Back
Top