For exery x exists y equal to x

  • Thread starter haael
  • Start date
In summary: So, taking the hypotheses as a set of axioms, the conclusion is a logical consequence of the axioms.So, in summary, this statement in first-order logic with equality, \forall x \exists y . x = y, seems to be an obvious statement that follows from the other equality axioms. It can be proved using natural deduction, by taking the hypotheses as axioms and deriving the conclusion as a logical consequence.
  • #1
haael
539
35
I'm having problems with this statement in first-order logic with equality:

[tex]\forall x \exists y . x = y[/tex]

For every element x there exists element y equal to that one. This seems obviously correct.

My questions: Is this an axiom? If not, how to proove it from other equality axioms?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
haael said:
I'm having problems with this statement in first-order logic with equality:

[tex]\forall x \exists y . x = y[/tex]

For every element x there exists element y equal to that one. This seems obviously correct.

My questions: Is this an axiom? If not, how to proove it from other equality axioms?
I dunno. Quite often a set of axioms is rather arbitrary in that there are several different bu logically equivalent sets.
 
  • #3
haael said:
My questions: Is this an axiom?
That question doesn't really make sense. A set of statements defines a branch of mathematics...the branch in which all the statements are true. The individual statements are called axioms...for that branch of mathematics.

haael said:
If not, how to proove it from other equality axioms?
What are the other axioms?
 
  • #4
Let's say we work in a finite structure. For example let's have a structure with 4 elements {a, b, c, d} and relations on them.

What are the other axioms?

Equality is reflexive, symmetric and transitive:
[tex]\forall x. x = x[/tex]
[tex]\forall x,y. x = y \rightarrow y = x[/tex]
[tex]\forall x,y,z. x = y \wedge y = z \rightarrow x = z[/tex]

And for each relation R on each position when element x is substituted to the equal element y, the value of the relation doesn't change:
[tex]\forall x,y. x = y \rightarrow (R(..., x, ...) \leftrightarrow R(..., y, ...))[/tex]

The sentence in question has something to do with the identity function. I'm not sure, but it probably states that the identity function exists.
[tex]\forall x \exists y. id(x) = y[/tex]
[tex]\forall x. id(x) = x[/tex]
[tex]\forall x \exists y. x = y[/tex]

This does not follow from any axiom as far as I can tell, but can the identity function NOT exist? Isn't the existence of the identity function obvious? So it should be an axiom.
 
  • #5
It seems to me that if the set is non-empty, then the axiom you're concerned about can be proved from the others by an informal argument: Let z be an element of the set. The axiom ##\forall x~x=x## tells us that z=z. This implies that ##\exists y~z=y##. Since z is arbitrary, this implies that ##\forall x\exists y~x=y##.

If my argument can be turned into a formal derivation, then maybe the axiom should be viewed as saying that we're dealing with non-empty sets?

Not sure if this argument can be formalized in this system. I'm still not very good at formal logic. I'm trying to learn more about it though. I'd be interested in seeing how this is presented in your book. What book is it?

You seem to be thinking that "obvious" statements shouldn't be axioms. This suggests some kind of misunderstanding. In this context, all statements should be viewed as meaningless strings of text. There are rules that tell us which strings of text can be considered "formulas", and rules that tell us how to construct formulas from formulas. The axioms are just the formulas that appear on the list of formulas that defines the branch of mathematics that we're currently interested in.

Since you seem to be concerned about the last three axioms you listed, but not the first three, I'm guessing that you have chosen to view = as a meaningless symbol. (If we think of x=y as the statement that the symbols x and y represent the same thing, then the first three axioms are all obvious). Wouldn't it make just as much sense to view "id" as a meaningless symbol, instead of as "the identity function"? (I have to admit, I don't see the point of the "id" axioms. That's one of the reasons I'd like to see the book).

In ZFC set theory, the identity function on a set X is (usually defined as) a specific subset of the cartesian product X×X. It takes several axioms to ensure the existence of the cartesian product. The axiom of separation ensures the existence of the appropriate subset.
 
  • #6
Using natural deduction (a related proof by Hilbert style axioms is also possible):

1. ##\forall x\ x=x\vdash\forall x\ x=x## (Conclusion among hypotheses)
2. ##\forall x\ x=x\vdash x=x## (1, ##\forall##-elimination)
3. ##\forall x\ x=x\vdash\exists y \ x=y## (2, ##\exists##-introduction) (OK, since ##x## is free for ##y## in ##x=y##.)
4. ##\forall x\ x=x\vdash\forall x\ \exists y \ x=y## (3, ##\forall##-introduction) (OK, since the hypothesis in 3 does not contain ##x## freely.)

So, ##\forall x\ \exists y \ x=y## is a logical consequence of the equality axiom ##\forall x\ x=x##.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes haael
  • #7
Thanks. That was the answer I needed.
 

FAQ: For exery x exists y equal to x

1. What does the statement "For every x, there exists y equal to x" mean?

The statement means that for any given value of x, there is a corresponding value of y that is equal to x. In other words, there is at least one y value for every x value.

2. How is this statement different from "For every x, y equals x"?

The two statements are similar in meaning, but the first statement emphasizes the existence of a y value for every x value, while the second statement simply states that y is equal to x without mentioning the existence of y for every x.

3. Can you give an example of this statement being true?

Yes, for example, the statement "For every real number x, there exists a real number y equal to x" is true because for any real number x, there is always a corresponding real number y that is equal to x (such as x=3 and y=3).

4. Is this statement always true?

No, this statement is not always true. There may be cases where there is no y value that is equal to a given x value, making the statement false. However, this statement is generally true in most mathematical contexts.

5. How is this statement used in mathematics?

This statement is commonly used in mathematical proofs and theorems to show that there is a relationship between two variables, where the value of one variable is dependent on the value of the other. It is also used in set theory and logic to define the existence of elements in a set or to prove the existence of a solution to a problem.

Similar threads

Replies
15
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
11
Views
4K
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
8
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
464
Back
Top