Going from Galilei to Minkowski

  • I
  • Thread starter Harry83
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Minkowski
In summary, the main difference between Galilean and special relativity inertial frames is that in Galilean physics, there is no spacetime metric and thus no way to define an absolute velocity or preferred frame. In special relativity, the presence of a spacetime metric allows for a whole family of equivalent inertial frames and the relativity of simultaneity. The concept of "angle" between a time axis and a spatial vector makes no sense in the Galilean context, but can be defined using a metric in special relativity. The Galilean Spacetime geometry is one of the nine Cayley-Klein geometries and the degenerate metric can be seen as a projection operator.
  • #1
Harry83
Hi, I'm starting a double degree in math and physics and am still a relativity newbie. I'm a bit stuck figuring out what exactly means to drop absolute time and simultaneity when making the transition from Galilean spacetime to Minkowski spacetime. Judging from the purely mathematical perspective it looks to me more accurate to say that for timelike paths the change is from a unique preferred frame corresponding to aunique simultaneity slicing in the Galilean case to a whole family of equivalently preferred frames in special relativity corresponding to an infinity of possible simultaneity slicings determining the possible three velocities < c at each point while the conformal structure determined by the indefinite signature allows to keep the relativity principle. Is this about right?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Harry83 said:
a unique preferred frame corresponding to a unique simultaneity slicing in the Galilean case

This is not a correct description. The simultaneity slicing in the Galilean case is unique because the Galilean transformation leaves the time coordinate unchanged; it only affects the space coordinates. But it does not define a preferred frame, because all of the inertial frames related by Galilean transformations are equivalent with respect to Newton's Laws (just as all of the inertial frames related by Lorentz transformations are equivalent with respect to the laws of special relativity).
 
  • #3
This may be a little abstract...
But since you mentioned math...

Can you write the Galilean transformation as a matrix?
Can you find its eigenvectors and eigenvalues?

In the Lorentz transformations, the corresponding problem leads to different results. In both cases however, there are no timelike eigenvectors (hence no preferred frames).My preferred motivation is geometrical/physical.
How does one define circles in Spacetime geometry? Use a wristwatch.
 
  • #4
PeterDonis said:
This is not a correct description. The simultaneity slicing in the Galilean case is unique because the Galilean transformation leaves the time coordinate unchanged; it only affects the space coordinates. But it does not define a preferred frame, because all of the inertial frames related by Galilean transformations are equivalent with respect to Newton's Laws (just as all of the inertial frames related by Lorentz transformations are equivalent with respect to the laws of special relativity).
Thanks. You're quite right. There sure exists a whole family of equivalent inertial frames also in Galilean spacetime. I wanted to convey the idea of an absolute velocity and I mixed it up with the idea of preferred frame.
So basically is it fair to say that the main difference between that Galilean and SR inertial frames is that the former have a fixed orientation between the time and the space component while the latter don't?
And about absolute simultaneity versus the relativity of simultaneity, is this SR idea that rather than abandoning the simultaneity slicings they are just not unique anymore?
 
  • #5
robphy said:
This may be a little abstract...
But since you mentioned math...

Can you write the Galilean transformation as a matrix?
Can you find its eigenvectors and eigenvalues?

In the Lorentz transformations, the corresponding problem leads to different results. In both cases however, there are no timelike eigenvectors (hence no preferred frames).My preferred motivation is geometrical/physical.
How does one define circles in Spacetime geometry? Use a wristwatch.
Thanks. I think I clarified above about the preferred frame so it's a non-issue, but I find it interesting the comment about no timelike eigenvectors.
 
  • #6
Harry83 said:
is it fair to say that the main difference between that Galilean and SR inertial frames is that the former have a fixed orientation between the time and the space component while the latter don't?

Not really; it would be better to say that the whole concept of relating the "orientation" of the time axis to the spatial components makes no sense in the Galilean context, because there is no spacetime metric so there is no way to compute an "angle" between the time axis and a spatial vector.
 
  • #7
Harry83 said:
is this SR idea that rather than abandoning the simultaneity slicings they are just not unique anymore?

No, it's more than that, because in SR there is a spacetime metric, whereas in Galilean physics there isn't. See my previous post.
 
  • #8
PeterDonis said:
Not really; it would be better to say that the whole concept of relating the "orientation" of the time axis to the spatial components makes no sense in the Galilean context, because there is no spacetime metric so there is no way to compute an "angle" between the time axis and a spatial vector.

Note that there is also no "angle" (arc length along a unit circle) between a time axis and a spatial vector in special relativity (unless you want to use complex angles). In both Galilean and special relativity, one can use a metric / symmetric bilinear form (degenerate in the Galilean case) to define orthogonality between such vectors.

Whether or not one calls the Galilean structures "metrical", there is a substantial geometrical formalism that tries to mimic metrical geometry. The Galilean Spacetime is one of the nine Cayley-Klein geometries in the plane. The other eight are Euclidean, hyperbolic, elliptic, Minkowski, deSitter and anti-deSitter and the Galilean limits of the anti/deSitter Spacetimes.

To explore the affine Cayley-Klein geometries (where the parallel postulate holds), check out my visualization:
https://www.desmos.com/calculator/ti58l2sair

Play with the E slider.
Note how the tangents to the unit circles for the E=0 case coincide... this is absolute simultaneity.
 
Last edited:
  • #9
robphy said:
there is also no "angle" (arc length along a unit circle) between a time axis and a spatial vector in special relativity

The word "angle" was probably not the best choice of words. The point is that in SR, you can take an inner product between any two vectors, including the case where one is timelike and the other is spacelike. You can't do that in the Galilean case; you can only take inner products between spatial vectors.
 
  • #10
PeterDonis said:
The word "angle" was probably not the best choice of words. The point is that in SR, you can take an inner product between any two vectors, including the case where one is timelike and the other is spacelike. You can't do that in the Galilean case; you can only take inner products between spatial vectors.

The degenerate metric in Galilean Spacetime geometry looks like a projection operator.
The inner product of any timelike vector and any spacelike vector is zero in the Galilean case.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Newton–Cartan_theory#Classical_spacetimes
Trautman's "Comparison of Newtonian and Relativistic Theories of SpaceTime": http://www.fuw.edu.pl/~amt/CompofNewt.pdf
Ehlers' frame theory in "Examples of Newtonian limits of relativistic spacetimes": http://pubman.mpdl.mpg.de/pubman/item/escidoc:153004:1/component/escidoc:153003/328699.pdf
 
Last edited:
  • #11
robphy said:
The inner product of any timelike vector and any spacelike vector is zero in the Galilean case.

I'm not sure that's true. I understand that the two metrics satisfy an orthogonality condition, but that does not mean you can take a timelike vector and a spacelike vector and take their inner product, because to do that you would need a single metric that acts on both, and you don't have that: one metric acts only on timelike vectors and the other acts only on spacelike vectors.
 
  • #12
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure that's true. I understand that the two metrics satisfy an orthogonality condition, but that does not mean you can take a timelike vector and a spacelike vector and take their inner product, because to do that you would need a single metric that acts on both, and you don't have that: one metric acts only on timelike vectors and the other acts only on spacelike vectors.

In an affine space (like Euclidean, Galilean, and Minkowski), we have an underlying vector space.
We can add and scalar multiply... we can add timelike vectors to spacelike vectors, etc... indeed, there is no sense of timelike or spacelike without a metric-like structure.

A metric is a type (0,2) tensor field, as added structure to get a spacetime geometry.
One can add a future timelike vector and a past timelike vector to obtain a spacelike vector.
Due to linearity, the metric can't be restricted to only act on vectors of certain types.

Thus, a metric tensor takes two vectors (whatever their type [timelike, spacelike, etc]) and returns a real number (their inner product)... which could be positive, negative, or zero.
There is no problem if the inner product of any timelike vector with any spacelike vector gives zero
(in fact, that's why we have absolute simultaneity in the Galilean case)

... that's part of the degenerate nature of the geometry... and that's why additional structures are needed (for example, a spatial metric to give non-trivial information for pairs of spatial-vectors since the temporal metric gives zero for such pairs.)
 
  • #13
robphy said:
A metric is a type (0,2) tensor field, as added structure to get a spacetime geometry.

A geometry, yes. Not necessarily a spacetime geometry.

robphy said:
a metric tensor takes two vectors (whatever their type [timelike, spacelike, etc]) and returns a real number (their inner product)... which could be positive, negative, or zero.

A metric tensor takes two vectors and returns a real number. But in the case under discussion (Galilean "spacetime"), we have two metric tensors. One only takes spacelike vectors as input; the other only takes timelike vectors as input. So there is no way to get an inner product between a timelike and a spacelike vector in this case.

The sources you link to do not seem to me to claim at any point that there is an inner product between timelike and spacelike vectors in the Galilean case. They only say what I said above.
 
  • #14
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure that's true. I understand that the two metrics satisfy an orthogonality condition, but that does not mean you can take a timelike vector and a spacelike vector and take their inner product, because to do that you would need a single metric that acts on both, and you don't have that: one metric acts only on timelike vectors and the other acts only on spacelike vectors.
Galilei spacetime is not a pseudo-Euclidean 4D affine space but a bundle of 3D Euclidean spaces along the time axis as fiber. That's why there's "absolute time" and "absolute space" in Newtonian physics. It doesn't make sense to define time- and space-like vectors. The direction of time has to be imposed (i.e., the "time axis" is by definition oriented), i.e., you postulate a causality structure ("arrow of time").

Minkowski space is a pseudo-Euclidean 4D affine space. Also here you have to impose orientedness and postulate a causality structure. This is consistently possible because the signature of Minkowski space's fundamental bilinear form is (1,3) (or (3,1) depending on your preferred choice of convention). The physical (classical) symmetry group is the proper orthochronous Poincare group, i.e., the part of the full Poincare group that's continuously connected to the identity operation. Indeed, Nature precisely realizes this symmetry group and not any larger subgroup of the (quantum version of the) Poincare group since the weak interaction breaks C, P, and CP (and thus also T).
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and Orodruin
  • #15
vanhees71 said:
It doesn't make sense to define time- and space-like vectors.

The papers that @robphy linked to use that terminology, though it might be somewhat of an abuse of terminology compared to the relativistic case.
 
  • #16
PeterDonis said:
A geometry, yes. Not necessarily a spacetime geometry.

A metric tensor takes two vectors and returns a real number. But in the case under discussion (Galilean "spacetime"), we have two metric tensors. One only takes spacelike vectors as input; the other only takes timelike vectors as input. So there is no way to get an inner product between a timelike and a spacelike vector in this case.

The sources you link to do not seem to me to claim at any point that there is an inner product between timelike and spacelike vectors in the Galilean case. They only say what I said above.

There aren't two kinds of indices (one for spacelike and one for timelike)... so a tensor can act on a vector of any type.
As I said earlier, "Due to linearity, the metric can't be restricted to only act on vectors of certain types."

Now, it may be that a certain tensor applied to certain types of vector yield possibly uninteresting quantities (like zero).
But that doesn't stop or restrict applying the tensor to various vectors.
 
  • #17
vanhees71 said:
Galilei spacetime is not a pseudo-Euclidean 4D affine space.

Maybe this is all an argument about terminology.
In the end, whatever you want to call things, there are structures (some necessarily degenerate) that try to mimic the situation in a Lorentzian-signature spacetime.

By an affine space, I mean a vector space in which parallelism applies.
The Galilean spacetime has that vector space structure and satisfies the parallel postulate.

Note that a position-vs-time graph (from PHY 101) is a Galilean spacetime diagram.
The position-vs-time graph has a non-euclidean geometry.
Sloped lines are inertial worldlines, and vertical lines are planes of simultaneity.
I can give you a geometric construction suggesting that those sloped lines are orthogonal to those vertical lines.

Define the Galilean circle with a wristwatch... the curve constant interval equal to 1 from the origin.
(That's a hyperbola in Minkowski spacetime.)
Segments from the origin to the circle are unit radii.
Given the circle, the tangents to the circle are orthogonal to the radius.
You can see the limiting cases by playing with the E-slider https://www.desmos.com/calculator/ti58l2sair .
In the E=0 (1+1)-Galilean case, all tangents are collinear (unlike in the Euclidean and Minkowski case).
This collinearity reflects absolute simultaneity.

A major reference for this point of view is Yaglom's
https://archive.org/details/ASimpleNon-euclideanGeometryAndItsPhysicalBasis

I first heard about this from a book by Emch
https://www.elsevier.com/books/math...f-20th-century-physics/emch/978-0-444-87585-3

Cayley-Klein Geometry is a well-established topic
http://aip.scitation.org/doi/10.1063/1.1664490
http://nyjm.albany.edu/j/2006/12-8v.pdf
https://arxiv.org/abs/0707.2869
http://www.springer.com/us/book/9783642172854 (Richter-Gebert)
https://arxiv.org/abs/physics/9702030

One of my research projects is applying this to
a unified framework for kinematics and dynamics in Galilean and Special Relativity,
that could be used in an undergraduate physics class.
.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #18
robphy said:
There aren't two kinds of indices (one for spacelike and one for timelike)... so a tensor can act on a vector of any type.

There are upper and lower indices, which are distinct. Both of the papers you linked to carefully use only upper indices for the spatial metric and only lower indices for the temporal one. That indicates that the two operate on distinct domains. The Trautman paper uses the term "form" for something with lower indices, and "vector" for something with upper indices.

Also, on p. 417, Trautman says that the spatial metric "may be used to define the square of any form and of any spacelike vector, but not of timelike vectors". That indicates to me that there is also no way of forming an inner product between a spacelike and a timelike vector.

I'll have to take a look at the other references you give in post #17.
 
  • #19
PeterDonis said:
There are upper and lower indices, which are distinct. Both of the papers you linked to carefully use only upper indices for the spatial metric and only lower indices for the temporal one. That indicates that the two operate on distinct domains. The Trautman paper uses the term "form" for something with lower indices, and "vector" for something with upper indices.

Also, on p. 417, Trautman says that the spatial metric "may be used to define the square of any form and of any spacelike vector, but not of timelike vectors". That indicates to me that there is also no way of forming an inner product between a spacelike and a timelike vector.

I'll have to take a look at the other references you give in post #17.

The nonzero form is defined on Trautman-p416 [itex]t_{a}=(\partial_a t)[/itex].
Then, a vector [itex]v^a[/itex] such that [itex]v^at_a=0[/itex] is spacelike [and so must be tangent to the hypersurfaces of constant-t... since [itex]v^a[/itex] doesn't pierce the hypersurface (a la MTW's "bongs of a bell")];
if [itex]v^at_a \neq 0[/itex], then [itex]v^a[/itex] is timelike.
In short, if a vector has a nonzero t-component, it's timelike...otherwise it's spacelike.
[Application.. a future-directed unit-timelike vector (of the form [itex]\left( \begin{array}{c} 1 \\ V \end{array}\right)[/itex] can be 4-velocity of an observer traveling with velocity V... this vector, of course, is tangent to the worldline of the observer. In Galilean physics, V can take any finite value. We excluded infinite values... because that would correspond to being tangent to the constant-t hypersurface.. Let's not allow our observers to do that. (The unit magnitude is determined by the temporal metric.) Note the Galilean time-dilation factor between two observers is 1:
[itex]\left( \begin{array}{cc} 1 & V \end{array}\right)\left( \begin{array}{cc} 1 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 \end{array}\right)\left( \begin{array}{c} 1 \\ W\end{array}\right)=1[/itex]]


A temporal metric can be defined as [itex]t_{ab}=t_at_b=(\partial_a t)(\partial_b t)[/itex] (see Ehlers-p-A121-near Eq 3a)
Then for spacelike vector [itex]X^a[/itex] and timelike vector [itex]U^a[/itex],
[tex]X^at_{ab}U^b=(X^at_{a})t_{b}U^b=0[/tex] can be interpreted by saying that they are orthogonal with respect to this temporal metric...
i.e. their inner product via this temporal metric is zero.
(Of course, it's also zero if [itex]U^a[/itex] is spacelike.
In other words, the temporal metric annihilates spacelike vectors.)

For me, the temporal metric is primary
(since it shows up as a limiting case of the Minkowski spacetime metric, in my formulation.
My unified metric is [itex] M = \left( \begin{array}{cc} 1 & 0 \\ 0 & -\epsilon^2 \end{array}\right) [/itex] ).
 
Last edited:
  • #20
How about the inverse metric? See e.g. Dautcourt's "the Newtonian limit..."
 
  • #21
robphy said:
Maybe this is all an argument about terminology.
In the end, whatever you want to call things, there are structures (some necessarily degenerate) that try to mimic the situation in a Lorentzian-signature spacetime.

By an affine space, I mean a vector space in which parallelism applies.
The Galilean spacetime has that vector space structure and satisfies the parallel postulate.
I'd think that mathematically the Galilei-Newton spacetime manifold is a bundle. You have time along which you have a 3D Euclidean affine space pinned at any point of this (oriented) time axis.

Of course you can also get the Galileo-Newton spacetime by "deformation" of Minkowski spacetime, which is formally given by expansions around ##c \rightarrow \infty## (##c## speed of light in vacuo). This is sometimes useful when taking the non-relativistic limit of relativistic equations.
 
  • #22
haushofer said:
How about the inverse metric? See e.g. Dautcourt's "the Newtonian limit..."

Thanks.. this looks useful... for filling in the details suggested by those earlier references.

https://inis.iaea.org/search/search.aspx?orig_q=RN:23072570 (fuller reference)
"On the Newtonian limit of general relativity" by G Dautcourt -
Acta physica polonica. B, 1990
http://www.actaphys.uj.edu.pl/fulltext?series=Reg&vol=21&page=755 (journal article)

This preprint "On the Ultrarelativistic Limit of General Relativity" by G. Dautcourt
https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9801093
also looks useful with its section on differential geometry with a degenerate metric.

My interest in this line of thinking was motivated by this paper:
"If Maxwell had worked between Ampère and Faraday: An historical fable with a pedagogical moral"
by Max Jammer and John Stachel
American Journal of Physics 48, 5 (1980); https://doi.org/10.1119/1.12239

Formulate (possibly secretly and not necessarily with all the details laid out to the end-user)
the physics of PHY 101 in a Galilean-spacetime way (or at least a spacetime-friendly way)
so that the transition to Special Relativity is smoother and less drastic (rather than the more common way...
suggesting that much of what was learned must now be unlearned (or quickly refined) to understand Special Relativity).
While the history of how we came to understand relativity is interesting,
as JL Synge puts it...
"To understand a subject, one must tear it apart and reconstruct it in a form intellectually satisfying to oneself, and that (in the view of the differences between individual minds) is likely to be different from the original form. This new synthesis is of course not an individual effort; it is the result of much reading and of countless informal discussions, but for it one must in the end take individual responsibility. Therefore, I apologise, if apology is necessary, for departing from certain traditional approaches which seemed to me unclear, and for insisting that the time has come in relativity to abandon an historical order and to present the subject as a completed whole, completed, that is, in its essentials. In this age of specialisation, history is best left to the historians.

J.L. Synge in Relativity: The Special Theory (1956), p. vii
...alternatively, one can try a similar pre-"Quantum Physics" formulation.
 

FAQ: Going from Galilei to Minkowski

What is the significance of going from Galilei to Minkowski?

Going from Galilei to Minkowski was a major shift in our understanding of space and time. It marked the transition from classical mechanics to the theory of relativity, which has had far-reaching implications in the fields of physics and cosmology.

Who were Galileo and Minkowski?

Galileo Galilei was an Italian physicist, mathematician, and astronomer who made significant contributions to the development of classical mechanics. Hermann Minkowski was a German mathematician who made important contributions to the development of the theory of relativity.

How did Galilei's ideas lead to the development of Minkowski's spacetime?

Galilei's principle of relativity, which states that the laws of physics are the same for all observers in uniform motion, laid the foundation for the concept of spacetime. Minkowski built upon this idea and developed the mathematical framework for spacetime in the theory of relativity.

What is the key difference between Galilei's and Minkowski's theories?

The key difference between Galilei's and Minkowski's theories is their treatment of space and time. Galilei's theory treats space and time as separate entities, while Minkowski's theory combines them into a single entity known as spacetime.

How has the transition from Galilei to Minkowski impacted modern physics?

The transition from Galilei to Minkowski has had a profound impact on modern physics. It has led to a deeper understanding of the universe and has allowed for the development of theories such as general relativity and quantum mechanics. It has also played a crucial role in the development of technologies such as GPS and atomic clocks.

Similar threads

Replies
14
Views
1K
Replies
6
Views
2K
Replies
17
Views
2K
Replies
14
Views
900
Replies
51
Views
3K
Replies
5
Views
1K
Back
Top