- #1
solakis1
- 422
- 0
Is the set of the natural Nos complete?
Imean can any non empty subset of N ,bounded from above have a supremum in N??stainburg said:If you refer to metric space, set of nature numbers is complete. The reason is that \(\displaystyle \mathbb{N}\) is closed in \(\displaystyle \mathbb{R}^1\) and \(\displaystyle (\mathbb{R}^1,d)\) is complete. To see this, any Cauchy sequence in \(\displaystyle \mathbb{N}\) can be formed as \(\displaystyle \{\lfloor |a_n|\rfloor\}\), where \(\displaystyle \{a_n\}\) is arbitrary Cauchy sequence in \(\displaystyle \mathbb{R}^1\), hence converges in \(\displaystyle \mathbb{N}\).
Of course!solakis said:Imean can any non empty subset of N ,bounded from above have a supremum in N??
stainburg said:Of course!
Clearly, \(\displaystyle \text{sup}S\) exists in \(\displaystyle \mathbb{R}^1\).solakis said:How can we prove that??
I mean let S be any non empty subset of N ,bounded above by a.
PROOF:
If a belongs to S , there is nothing to prove,because then ,SupS=a
But if a does not belong to S then how do we prove that S has a supremum??
stainburg said:Hence \(\displaystyle S\) must contain the greatest nature number \(\displaystyle b\) which is less than \(\displaystyle a\) (because \(\displaystyle S\) is an ordered set).
If we take for example:stainburg said:Clearly, \(\displaystyle \text{sup}S\) exists in \(\displaystyle \mathbb{R}^1\).
First, if \(\displaystyle S\) is bounded above, then \(\displaystyle S\) must be finite (otherwise, we conclude \(\displaystyle a=\infty\), this is absurd). Hence \(\displaystyle S\) must contain the greatest nature number \(\displaystyle b\) which is less than \(\displaystyle a\) (because \(\displaystyle S\) is an ordered set). Hence \(\displaystyle b\) is an upper bound of \(\displaystyle S\).
Second, if \(\displaystyle b\neq \text{sup}S \), there must be a non-negative real number \(\displaystyle c<b\) such that \(\displaystyle \text{sup}S=c\), but \(\displaystyle b \in S\), a contradiction.
solakis said:So if we say that the upper bound of S is 234,how can we prove that S has a Sup ,without knowing what the S is.
solakis said:AS you can see all non empty bounded subsets of N HAVE a sup ,even the infinite (very big ones)
Maybe are our perception of what a proof is are different.stainburg said:I take your example. If we know 234 or 234.123 is an upper bound of S, S must contain its supremum (because S is finite ordered set). However, we don't know what S is, we cannot get sup S.
There is no largest number in N. If S\(\displaystyle \subset\)N is infinite, S cannot be bounded above.
Actually, I've proven sup S exists in S.
First of all the set of natural Nos we consider does not include zeroDeveno said:I'm not sure what the problem is, here.
Since $S$ is a bounded subset of $\Bbb R$ (bounded above by the real $\sup(S)$ and bounded below by 0), we have that $\sup(S)$ is an upper bound for $S$.
Let $a = \lfloor s \rfloor$. Since $S$ consists of only non-negative integers, it is clear that $a \in \Bbb N$ (we are tacitly assuming here that $S$ is non-empty, in which case, $s \geq 0$). Furthermore, from the definition of the floor function, we have:
$a \leq s < a+1$.
We'd like to prove that $s = a$.
So suppose $s > a$. Let $c = a + \dfrac{s - a}{2}$. We then have:
$a < c < s$.
Now suppose $x \in S$ is any element of $S$. We certainly have $x \leq s$ (since $s$ is an upper bound for $S$). Can it be that $x > c$?
If, so, we have $a < c < x < s < a+1$, which implies $S \cap (a,a+1) \neq \emptyset$, which is impossible because $\Bbb N \cap (a,a+1) = \emptyset$ (there are NO natural numbers between $a$ and $a+1$).
So, since $x > c$ leads to a contradiction, it MUST be the case that $x \leq c$. But the means that $c$ is an upper bound for $S$, since $x$ was chosen arbitrarily. Since $s = \sup(S)$, we cannot have $c < s$, since $s$ is the LEAST upper bound for $S$. So no such $c$ exists.
Now the existence of $c$ came from assuming that $s > a$, and since this leads to an impossible situation, it must be that $s > a$ is false. Since we have that $a \leq s$, it must be that $a = s$, which is what we set out to prove.
Hence we have determined that $\sup(S) \in \Bbb N$.
Now the set $T = \{0,1,\dots,a\}$ is finite, and we certainly have $S \subseteq T$. Hence $S$ is also finite. Since we have a finite set, we can (since $\Bbb N$ is ordered, and thus $S$ is, as well) determine $b = \max(S)$.
We'd like to show that $b = a$, or equivalently, that $a \in S$. Clearly, since $a = \sup(S)$, and $b \in S$, we have $b \leq a$.
Suppose $b < a$. Then $b \leq a-1$. Since for any $x \in S$ we have $x \leq b \leq a - 1$, this means that $a - 1$ is an upper bound for $S$. Since $a - 1 < a$ this contradicts $a$ being the least upper bound for $S$, so we conclude that $b < a$ is also impossible, so it must be that $b = a$.
In summary: $\sup(S) = \max(S) \in S$, so $\Bbb N$ is complete.
solakis said:First of all the set of natural Nos we consider does not include zero
Secondly ,please, before you give your version of proof read carefully all the previous posts
Thirdly we are considering the completeness of N in N and not in R i.e ,if you take N as a subset of R ,then any non empty subset of N ,bounded from above is a subset of R and thus has a supremum because R is complete
Forthly if you could write shorter proofs more justified witout using words that need extra definition it would be very much appriciated.
I don't know what the "floor function" is ,for example
Deveno said:Alternatively, here is a proof that doesn't use real numbers.
Suppose $S \subset \Bbb N$ is bounded above. This means there exists a natural number $k$ such that $x < k$ for all $x \in S$.
Consider the set $T = \{n \in \Bbb N: x < n, \forall x \in S\}$.
$T$ is non-empty, since $k \in T$. .
How do you conclude that for all xεS, \(\displaystyle x\leq m-1\)Deveno said:That's pretty much a non-issue, we can always use 1 as a lower bound for $S$ instead, which guarantees that $s$ will be positive.
Or, what? This seems to assume that:
1) I have not done so.
2) That what I have written somehow conflicts with what has transpired before.
This is true, BUT: We can use facts about real numbers to prove facts about natural numbers. What I have shown is that the REAL supremum of $S$ is, in fact, IN $S$, and thus is a NATURAL supremum of $S$.
The floor of $x$ is the greatest integer less than or equal to $x$ (we have to include "or equal to" because $x$ might just be an integer). If $m \geq x < m+1$, then $\lfloor x \rfloor = m$.
Alternatively, here is a proof that doesn't use real numbers.
Suppose $S \subset \Bbb N$ is bounded above. This means there exists a natural number $k$ such that $x < k$ for all $x \in S$.
Consider the set $T = \{n \in \Bbb N: x < n, \forall x \in S\}$.
$T$ is non-empty, since $k \in T$. So by the well-ordered property of the natural numbers, $T$ has a least element, $m$.
By construction, we have $x < m$, for all $x \in S$.
Hence $x \leq m - 1$, for all $x \in S$. We shall see that $\sup(S) = m-1$.
It is immediate that $m - 1$ is an upper bound for $S$, since for all $x \in S$, we have $x \leq m-1$.
Suppose we have $y \in \Bbb N$ with $y < m-1$ also an upper bound for $S$. Then, for any $x \in S$, we have:
$x \leq y < m-1$, that is: $m-1 \in T$, contradicting the fact that $m$ is the smallest element of $T$.
Therefore, any upper bound (in $\Bbb N$) is greater than or equal to $m-1$, so that $m - 1 = \sup(S)$.
Next, we need to show that $m - 1 \in S$. Suppose not. Then since we don't have $x = m-1$ for any $x \in S$ (since $m-1$ is assumed not in $S$), it must be that $x < m-1$ for all $x \in S$. Again, this means that $m-1 \in T$, contradicting our choice of $m$.
So we must have $m-1 \in S$, which shows that $\sup(S) \in S$, that is: $\Bbb N$ is complete.
solakis said:How do you conclude that for all xεS, \(\displaystyle x\leq m-1\)
Also if you prove that m-1 belongs to S then m-1 is the maximum (Since \(\displaystyle \forall x[x\leq m-1]\)) of S and that implies that m-1 is also the Supremum of S
IF S = {1} CAN YOU HAVE M-1??Deveno said:Because $m-1$ is "the next largest natural number" after $m$ (there aren't any in-between)..
Deveno said:And yes, for the natural numbers, maximum and supremum are the same concept. This is because the natural numbers are discrete (as a topological space it consists of isolated points). Put another way, we can only travel from one natural number to the next in discrete (discontinuous) jumps of one unit, there is no "density" to the natural numbers.
ThePerfectHacker said:You said you wanted it neatly presented without excessive words. Here is how to write it:
Let $A$ be an non-empty subset of $\mathbb{N}$ that has an upper bound. Define $B = \{ n \in \mathbb{N} ~ | ~ n \text{ is upper bound for }$A$ \}$. By well-ordering property $B$ has a minimal element call it $m$. Then $m = \sup A $ and $m\in A$.
solakis said:I did not say only "neatly" but neat and justified.Can you justify your claim that :SupA =m and mεA ??
solakis said:IF S = {1} CAN YOU HAVE M-1??
So your proof excludes the set {1}
Hence it is not a general proof
In any topological space if a set has a maximum then it has a supremum
Bacterius said:By construction $B$ contains all upper bounds of $A$, so the smallest element $m$ of $B$ is the least upper bound of $A$, that is, $m$ is the supremum of $A$.
Here is a proof that :Deveno said:That's pretty much a non-issue, we can always use 1 as a lower bound for $S$ instead, which guarantees that $s$ will be positive.
Or, what? This seems to assume that:
1) I have not done so.
2) That what I have written somehow conflicts with what has transpired before.
This is true, BUT: We can use facts about real numbers to prove facts about natural numbers. What I have shown is that the REAL supremum of $S$ is, in fact, IN $S$, and thus is a NATURAL supremum of $S$.
The floor of $x$ is the greatest integer less than or equal to $x$ (we have to include "or equal to" because $x$ might just be an integer). If $m \geq x < m+1$, then $\lfloor x \rfloor = m$.
Alternatively, here is a proof that doesn't use real numbers.
Suppose $S \subset \Bbb N$ is bounded above. This means there exists a natural number $k$ such that $x < k$ for all $x \in S$.
Consider the set $T = \{n \in \Bbb N: x < n, \forall x \in S\}$.
$T$ is non-empty, since $k \in T$. So by the well-ordered property of the natural numbers, $T$ has a least element, $m$.
By construction, we have $x < m$, for all $x \in S$.
Hence $x \leq m - 1$, for all $x \in S$. We shall see that $\sup(S) = m-1$.
It is immediate that $m - 1$ is an upper bound for $S$, since for all $x \in S$, we have $x \leq m-1$.
Suppose we have $y \in \Bbb N$ with $y < m-1$ also an upper bound for $S$. Then, for any $x \in S$, we have:
$x \leq y < m-1$, that is: $m-1 \in T$, contradicting the fact that $m$ is the smallest element of $T$.
Therefore, any upper bound (in $\Bbb N$) is greater than or equal to $m-1$, so that $m - 1 = \sup(S)$.
Next, we need to show that $m - 1 \in S$. Suppose not. Then since we don't have $x = m-1$ for any $x \in S$ (since $m-1$ is assumed not in $S$), it must be that $x < m-1$ for all $x \in S$. Again, this means that $m-1 \in T$, contradicting our choice of $m$.
So we must have $m-1 \in S$, which shows that $\sup(S) \in S$, that is: $\Bbb N$ is complete.
solakis said:Can you justify your claim that :
SupA =m and mεA ??
The Natural Numbers, also known as the counting numbers, are the set of positive integers starting from 1 and continuing infinitely. It includes all whole numbers greater than 0.
Yes, the set of Natural Numbers is complete. This means that it is a closed set, meaning that there are no numbers missing in between any two consecutive numbers. For example, there is no number between 3 and 4 in the set of Natural Numbers.
The completeness of the Natural Numbers is proven through the mathematical concept of induction. This is a method of proof that shows that a statement is true for all natural numbers by proving that it is true for the first number (usually 1) and then showing that if it is true for any given number, it must also be true for the next consecutive number. This process can continue indefinitely, proving the completeness of the set of Natural Numbers.
Yes, there are other sets that are considered complete, such as the set of Integers, which includes all whole numbers (both positive and negative) and 0. However, not all sets of numbers are complete. For example, the set of Rational Numbers (fractions) is not complete because there are infinitely many numbers between any two fractions.
The completeness of the Natural Numbers is important in mathematics because it allows for the creation and use of various mathematical operations, such as addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. These operations rely on the fact that the set of Natural Numbers is complete, as it ensures that there are no missing numbers in between any two consecutive numbers. This is essential for the development and application of various mathematical concepts and theories.