Proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy.

  • MHB
  • Thread starter solakis1
  • Start date
In summary, if we are given the following rules of propositional calculus, we can use them to solve the problem given the definition given earlier.
  • #1
solakis1
422
0
given the definition: \(\displaystyle A\leq B\Longleftrightarrow A<B\vee A=B\) Where A,B are reals ,then prove:

\(\displaystyle A\leq B\vee B\leq A\)

Proof: From trichotomy we have : (a<bva=b)vb<a=> [(a<bva=b)vb<a]vb=a =>(a<bva=b)v(b<avb=a).

And here is where i get stuck.

According to which law in propusitional calculus can we substitute (a<bva=b) and (b<avb=a) with \(\displaystyle A\leq B\) and \(\displaystyle B\leq A\) according to the above definition??
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Hi,

It's just the definition at the beginning of your post.
 
  • #3
Replacing $A<B\lor A=B$ with $A\le B$ is not a question of object calculus, but of metacalculus (our natural language). For example, if you decide to write $f$ instead of $5$, you don't need a new arithmetic identity to conclude that $f+1=6$. The arithmetic "does not see", so to speak, your abbreviation. From its standpoint the equation is $5+1=6$. It's only your way of writing this equation that changed.

Similarly, if $B\le A$ is defined as $B<A\lor B=A$, then this is simply an abbreviation that makes out writing shorter. This definition is transparent on the object level, and the formulas you derive still contain $B<A\lor B=A$.

Another option is to treat $\le$ as a primitive predicate symbol and not a definition. Then one must posit an axiom
\[
B\le A\leftrightarrow B<A\lor B=A.
\]
Suppose a formula $F$ that contains a subformula $B<A\lor B=A$ is derivable. Then $F'$, which is obtained from $F$ by replacing $B<A\lor B=A$ with $B\le A$ is also derivable. This is a metatheorem that is proved by induction on $F$.
 
  • #4
Evgeny.Makarov said:
Replacing $A<B\lor A=B$ with $A\le B$ is not a question of object calculus, but of metacalculus (our natural language). For example, if you decide to write $f$ instead of $5$, you don't need a new arithmetic identity to conclude that $f+1=6$. The arithmetic "does not see", so to speak, your abbreviation. From its standpoint the equation is $5+1=6$. It's only your way of writing this equation that changed.

Similarly, if $B\le A$ is defined as $B<A\lor B=A$, then this is simply an abbreviation that makes out writing shorter. This definition is transparent on the object level, and the formulas you derive still contain $B<A\lor B=A$.

Another option is to treat $\le$ as a primitive predicate symbol and not a definition. Then one must posit an axiom
\[
B\le A\leftrightarrow B<A\lor B=A.
\]
Suppose a formula $F$ that contains a subformula $B<A\lor B=A$ is derivable. Then $F'$, which is obtained from $F$ by replacing $B<A\lor B=A$ with $B\le A$ is also derivable. This is a metatheorem that is proved by induction on $F$.

Thank you, I always get mixed up with theorems and metatheorems.
But do you mean that except the rule of equivalence substitution ,no other rules of propositional calculus can be used to solve the problem??
 
  • #5
solakis said:
But do you mean that except the rule of equivalence substitution ,no other rules of propositional calculus can be used to solve the problem?
If $\le$ is a primitive predicate symbol and inequality is defined by an axiom, then you do need the rule of equivalence substitution. However, this rule is a metatheorem and uses various inference rules of the underlying calculus to build a new derivation. Which rules exactly are used depends on the calculus.
 
  • #6
Evgeny.Makarov said:
. Which rules exactly are used depends on the calculus.

Suppose we are given the following rules:

Double negation
conjunctio introduction
conjunction elimination
disjunction introduction
disjunction elimination
conditional proof
contradiction
bicondtional introduction
biconditional elimination.

How would we solve the problem
 

FAQ: Proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy.

How do you prove A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy?

To prove A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy, you must first establish that the elements A and B are comparable. This means that either A ≤ B or B ≤ A must be true. Then, you can use the transitive property to show that if A ≤ B and B ≤ A are both true, then A = B.

What is Trichotomy in relation to proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A?

Trichotomy is a property of a relation on a set that states that every two elements in the set are either comparable or not. In the context of proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A, Trichotomy means that for any elements A and B, either A ≤ B or B ≤ A must be true.

Can you use other properties besides Trichotomy to prove A ≤ B or B ≤ A?

Yes, there are other properties that can be used to prove A ≤ B or B ≤ A. For example, if the relation on the set is reflexive, you can use the reflexive property to show that A ≤ A, which then implies A ≤ B or B ≤ A. Additionally, if the relation is transitive, you can use the transitive property to show that if A ≤ B and B ≤ C, then A ≤ C, which then implies A ≤ B or B ≤ A.

What is the importance of proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy?

Proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy is important because it establishes a fundamental property of ordered sets. It allows us to compare elements in a set and determine their relationship to one another. This is useful in many areas of mathematics and science, including calculus, algebra, and statistics.

Can you give an example of proving A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy?

Sure, let's say we have a set of integers and the relation between them is "less than or equal to." To prove A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy, we can take any two integers, say 3 and 5. Since 3 is less than 5, we can say that either 3 ≤ 5 or 5 ≤ 3, which satisfies the condition of Trichotomy. Then, we can use the transitive property to show that if 3 ≤ 5 and 5 ≤ 3, then 3 = 5. Therefore, we have proven that A ≤ B or B ≤ A from Trichotomy for this set of integers.

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
806
Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
702
Replies
1
Views
823
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
26
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
2K
Back
Top