- #1
dmuthuk
- 41
- 1
I am trying to show that "if every countable subset of a totally ordered set [tex]X[/tex] is well ordered, then [tex]X[/tex] itself is well ordered". My argument is by contradiction. Informally, if we have a nonempty subset [tex]E[/tex] of [tex]X[/tex] which does not have a smallest element, then we can produce an infinite decreasing sequence in [tex]E[/tex] whose image is a countable subset of [tex]X[/tex] that doesn't have a smallest element and is therefore not well ordered.
I am having some doubts about how to make this argument more precise. I was thinking of something as follows: Let [tex]f:\mathcal{P}(X)\to X[/tex] be a choice function for [tex]X[/tex] and let [tex]x_0\in E[/tex]. Then, define a sequence recursively by letting [tex]x_{n+1}=f(s(x_n)\cap E)[/tex]. (Note: [tex]s(x_n)=\{x\in X: x<x_n\}[/tex].) Clearly, the image of this sequence has no smallest element. But, the question is can we really define a sequence in this way? For the Recursion Theorem to work, doesn't the function [tex]f[/tex] have to be a map from a set to itself?
I am having some doubts about how to make this argument more precise. I was thinking of something as follows: Let [tex]f:\mathcal{P}(X)\to X[/tex] be a choice function for [tex]X[/tex] and let [tex]x_0\in E[/tex]. Then, define a sequence recursively by letting [tex]x_{n+1}=f(s(x_n)\cap E)[/tex]. (Note: [tex]s(x_n)=\{x\in X: x<x_n\}[/tex].) Clearly, the image of this sequence has no smallest element. But, the question is can we really define a sequence in this way? For the Recursion Theorem to work, doesn't the function [tex]f[/tex] have to be a map from a set to itself?