Quantum Jumps and Schrodinger's Cat are predictable

In summary: No, the system is not predictable in that way. It is not like they can say "this atom will jump in 0.3 seconds, and this one in 1.2 seconds, etc.". The unpredictability in this case comes from quantum fluctuations and the way the system interacts with its environment. However, they are able to track the "flight" of the jump, meaning the path the system takes from the ground state to the excited state, and even reverse the jump mid-flight. But this does not mean they can predict when the jump will occur.This research is important because it shows that quantum jumps are not completely random and can be controlled to some extent. It also sheds light on the nature of quantum systems
  • #36
PeterDonis said:
I'm always highly skeptical of sensational-sounding claims on phys.org. I'm doubly skeptical when there isn't even a link to a paper (not even an arxiv preprint) in the article, which tells me that the article writer doesn't want me to look up the actual paper and find out that, while their article says "man bites dog!", the actual paper is more like "dog bites man, and now we have a more detailed model of the tooth marks".

Today is the first time that I have looked at the article, and I see that "A study announcing the discovery appears in the June 3 online edition of the journal Nature" in the phys.org article, and that a link to the Nature article appears at the bottom of the phys.org article.

Also, the article was not written by a phys.org writer; the article was supplied to phys.org by Yale University ("by Yale University" at the top, and "Provide by Yale University" at the bottom). I do think that it is valid to criticize phys.org for uncritically accepting the Yale-supplied hyperbole. This highights what is becoming a major problem: too often, university PR departments put out over-ther-top bs versions of research performed.
 
  • Like
Likes sysprog, dextercioby and DrClaude
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
What Einstein said concerning theorists is also valid for experimentalists: don't listen to their words (or in this case those of the popular press) but look at their deeds, i.e., read the Nature article (including the very valuable supplement). What has been observed are not "quantum jumps" (which do not exist according to modern QT since 1925/26) but the continuous spontaneous and induced transitions from one energy level of a system through coupling to external perturbations.

If confirmed, it's a great step forward, i.e., away from old-fashioned instantaneous "quantum jumps" of the old Bohr-Sommerfeld model to the empirical verification of the predictions of modern quantum theory.
 
  • #38
Bohr conceived of quantum jumps in 1913, and while Einstein elevated their hypothesis to the level of a quantitative rule with his AB coefficient theory, Schrödinger strongly objected to their existence. The nature and existence of quantum jumps remained a subject of controversy for seven decades until they were directly observed in a single system. Since then, quantum jumps have been observed in a variety of atomic and solid-state systems. Recently, quantum jumps have been recognized as an essential phenomenon in quantum feedback control, and in particular, for detecting and correcting decoherence-induced errors in
quantum information systems .
https://arxiv.org/abs/1803.00545

The authors definitely claim in the introduction that they have observed "quantum leaps" of popular science. As we have several times noted in this thread, quantum leaps do not exist in standard quantum mechanics. Erwin Schrödinger was right.

A. Neumaier brought up that quantum jumps and trajectories are a numerical method of quantum optics. But the authors seem to claim that the numerical method would prove the existence of quantum leaps.

I have to repeat my opinion that Nature has published a paper which is confusing terms of quantum mechanics. Nature made a mistake. The confused philosophical part of the paper should be removed and the authors should just report the experiment.
 
  • #39
Well, this is often the case with Nature papers. I find this disturbing too! The only point is that if you read the text, it becomes clear that the abstract and introduction is just "popular-science gibberish", and in the rest of the paper the science usually gets correctly stated. That's the difference to many popular-science articles, where often you don't even understand the science, if you are an expert in the field ;-)).
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #40
vanhees71 said:
What Einstein said concerning theorists is also valid for experimentalists: don't listen to their words (or in this case those of the popular press) but look at their deeds
I wonder if anyone knows the source of this saying.
Albert Einstein said:
If you want to find out anything from the theoretical physicists about the methods they use, I advise you to stick closely to one principle: don't listen to their words, fix your attention on their deeds.
I found in several places the precise wording quoted above, but nowhere an attribution to the precise source.

By the way, adhering to Einstein's advice, I was lead to my thermal interpretation of quantum physics!
 
  • #41
A. Neumaier said:
I found in several places the precise wording quoted above, but nowhere an attribution to the precise source.
Actually, a more thorough search lead me to a https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/184387.pdf, but it had another formulation, though with essentially the same meaning:
Albert Einstein said:
If you wish to learn from the theoretical physicist anything about the methods which he uses, I would give you the following piece of advice: Don't listen to his words, examine his achievements. For to the discoverer in that field, the constructions of his imagination appear so necessary and so natural that he is apt to treat them not as the creations of his thoughts but as given realities.
Maybe he said similar things at multiple occasions...
 
  • #42
vanhees71 said:
If confirmed, it's a great step forward, i.e., away from old-fashioned instantaneous "quantum jumps" of the old Bohr-Sommerfeld model to the empirical verification of the predictions of modern quantum theory.

I kind of disagree and this is the thing, which disappoints me a bit about this paper. If you have a look at the derivation of the dynamics of the "quantum jump", especially equations 11 and 14 in the SOM, you will find that the timescale of this continuous evolution is given by the effective transition time scale [itex]t_{mid}[/itex], which is given by [tex]t_{mid}=(\frac{\Omega_{BG}^2}{2\gamma_B})^{-1} \ln{(1+\frac{\Omega_{BG}^2}{\gamma_B \Omega_{DG}})},[/tex]
where [itex]\Omega_{BG}[/itex] and [itex]\Omega_{DG}[/itex] are the Rabi frequencies of the drives for the bright and dark state transitions, respectively and [itex]\gamma_B[/itex] is the loss rate of the bright state, which is proportional to its spectral width.
Now the interesting thing is that the dominant time scale for the "quantum jump" to the dark state is not given by the Rabi frequency for the driving field that couples the ground and the dark state, but the one that couples the ground and the bright state. This is explained quite easily by the authors by pointing out that this is the quantity that determines the mean time between clicks for the weak measurement in the bright channel. This mean time between clicks is given by:
[tex]t_{click}=(\frac{\Omega_{BG}^2}{\gamma_B})^{-1} [/tex].
So in fact, the time scale of the transition is given by:
[tex]t_{mid}=\frac{t_{click}}{2} \ln{(1+\frac{1}{t_{click} \Omega_{DG}})}.[/tex]
Now, [itex]\Omega_{DG}[/itex] is of course just the inverse of the time [itex]t_{dark}[/itex] a dark state Rabi cycle takes (up to some prefactors of 2 pi or 2 - I did not follow the normalization), so the whole time scale of the "quantum jump" is something like:
[tex]t_{mid}=\frac{t_{click}}{2} \ln{(1+\frac{t_{dark}}{t_{click}})}.[/tex]
In other words: You can and will change this time scale just by driving the bright transition more strongly because you expect more counts in this case. Basically, this just gives you the probability to be in the dark state after so-and-so-many non-counting events on the bright state transition, which is just a function of how many absent counts you need to get some level of certainty and how long it takes to get to this absent count level. It is not directly related to anything concerning the dark state transition. If you just ramp up the driving field of the bright state transition, so that [itex]t_{click}[/itex] becomes short, you can get arbitrarily close to an instantaneous jump again.
 
  • Like
Likes sysprog and vanhees71
  • #43
I don't think that you can come to an instantaneous jump again. There's nothing instantaneous in QT's time evolution.
 
  • #44
In practice: Yes, I agree.
The bare time evolution of the probability amplitude for dark state occupation happens on a slower time scale, anyway. So there should be some point at which a finite time scale of the "quantum jump" (or coupling to the environment or decoherence or whatever you want to call it) emerges. In fact, I would have loved to see a measurement series that just investigates this "mid-time" for several Rabi frequencies of the bright transition. I wonder why the authors did not do that. Either it would have spoiled the mass appeal slightly (because the fact that the timescale is actually not that meaningful physically is a bit downplayed in the manuscript), or non-linearities become non-negligible at high pump powers or at some point the electronics would become too slow to follow the experiment adequately. Still, it would be interesting to perform such an experiment.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #45
I guess it's also technically pretty difficult to cover all the possible time scales you discuss. I find it remarkable that one can nowadays start to resolve such quantum dynamics at all.

In some cases "timing" is even difficult to grasp theoretically. One example is the "tunnel time", i.e., the time it takes for a particle to tunnel through a potential barrier. I'm not sure whether this has been defined convincingly yet. At least it's a decade-long problem. Today, there's however some progress with the advent of "attosecond laser pules" to make it possible to measure such processes with the necessary time resolution. Of course the measured "tunnel times" also have to be analyzed taking into account the full experimental setup, then also providing the "correct" definition of "tunnel times", as measured by the specific experiment.
 
  • #46
vanhees71 said:
"quantum jumps" (which do not exist according to modern QT since 1925/26)
Why then did Schrödinger write in 1952 a paper with the title ''https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/685552.pdf" ?
Why then did accomplished quantum physicists again and again refer to quantum jumps?
Wigner 1937 said:
the reaction shall not involve a jump in the quantum state of the electrons [Footnote 2: The possibility of chemical reactions without quantum jumps in the state of the electronic system has been first realized by F. London]
(Wigner, Calculation of the Rate of Elementary Association Reactions, 1937)
Dirac 1940 said:
according to quantum mechanics we need, for a complete description of the universe, not only the laws of motion and the initial conditions, but also information about which quantum jump occurs in each case when a quantum jump does occur. The latter information must be included, together with the initial conditions, in that part of the description of the universe outside mathematical theory. [...] Quantum mechanics provides an escape from the difficulty. It enables us to ascribe the complexity to the quantum jumps, lying outside the scheme of equations of motion. The quantum jumps now form the uncalculable part of natural phenomena, to replace the initial conditions of the old mechanistic view.
(Dirac, The relation between mathematics and physics, 1940)
Herzberg 1944 said:
Radiation is emitted or absorbed by a transition of the electron from one quantum state to another - by a quantum jump - the energy difference between the two states being
emitted or absorbed as a light quantum of energy $h\nu'$ [...] Radiation results only through a quantum jump from such a state of positive energy to a lower state of positive or negative energy. [...] In addition, there is the rule that, so long as the interaction of the electrons is not very large, only those quantum transitions take place for which only one of the emission electrons makes a jump—that is, only one alters its $l$ value, the alteration being in accordance with the selection rule (I, 29):
$\Delta l = \pm 1$. [...] Transitions in which teo or more electrons jump at the same time are considerably weaker but are not forbidden by any strict selection rule. [...] one electron making the quantum jump (transition between even and odd terms) . [...] Such a radiationless quantum jump was first discovered by Auger, and is called after him the Auger effect
(Herzberg, Atomic spectra and atomic structure, 1944; then the bible for spectroscopy)

That the term ''quantum jump'' does not figure everywhere in the literature is simply because a ''transition'' between energy levels - an ubiquitous term in spectroscopy and photochemistry - is just a quantum jump called by a different name. It even occurs in the modern definition of the second:
The second is the duration of 9 192 631 770 periods of the radiation corresponding to the transition between the two hyperfine levels of the ground state of the Cesium 133 atom.
(http://physics.nist.gov/cuu/Units/second.html)

Thus without quantum jumps no modern high precision measurement of time!
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #47
A. Neumaier, I think that in an earlier message I already wrote that the probability amplitudes (complex values) of a wave function develop smoothly in time.

A simple example is a single particle in a double potential well. We prepare the particle to be in the well A. Slowly, the probability amplitude leaks to the well B beside A. We measure the system and find the particle in B.

Should we say that the particle "jumped" from A to B? That language is not used in quantum mechanics. There is no definite path of the particle. It may "tunnel" to B if the wall between A and B is high, but that word is misleading, too.
 
  • #48
Well, I don't know, why Schrödinger at all wrote against the clear evidence of their own theory.

I'd also be very interested to learn, where in the measurement of time, using atomic clocks like the "cesium fontain" or even more accurate measurements with more modern quantum-optical equipment (e.g., "frequency combs") you need to invoke "quantum jumps". I've no clue!
 
  • #49
Heikki Tuuri said:
A. Neumaier, I think that in an earlier message I already wrote that the probability amplitudes (complex values) of a wave function develop smoothly in time.

A simple example is a single particle in a double potential well. We prepare the particle to be in the well A. Slowly, the probability amplitude leaks to the well B beside A. We measure the system and find the particle in B.

Should we say that the particle "jumped" from A to B? That language is not used in quantum mechanics. There is no definite path of the particle. It may "tunnel" to B if the wall between A and B is high, but that word is misleading, too.

How is this even related to the topic at hand? This has absolutely nothing to do with quantum jumps or quantum trajectories (or more formal: Monte Carlo wave function methods). The scenario is a totally different one. Consider for example simple emission from a two-level system. We all know that in non-qed quantum mechanics the excited state should be stable in the absence of external fields. Now one may perturb the system, which puts it into a superposition state of the excited state and the ground state, where the probability amplitudes for occupation of these states oscillate in time. One can either do this via external fields, which yields stimulated emission or one can consider QED and the properties of the vacuum state, which yields spontaneous emission. Anyway, you recover a picture similar to the classical one. In classical physics, you get electromagnetic radiation from accelerating charges. Here you get a state with time-dependent probability amplitudes for different charge configurations which in turn couple to probability amplitudes for photon emission.
So in a nutshell, a correct description of the system will more or less be similar to a dressed state picture, where the state of the atom is necessarily entangled with the state of the light field. This also means that you do not have to do a measurement on the atom to get it into an eigenstate. Performing a measurement on the photon is sufficient. For a local experimentalist sitting next to the atom, information about the light field is usually unavailable. So he has an open system and an environment perturbing his atom, which frequently "resets" his system to one of the eigenstates. This would be an example of a quantum jump. And at more than 1000 citations (https://www.osapublishing.org/josab/abstract.cfm?uri=josab-10-3-524), this is also far from being non-mainstream. The are also some good explanations demonstrating what is not meant by quantum jumps. The introduction of this paper by Wiseman ( https://journals.aps.org/pra/abstract/10.1103/PhysRevA.60.2474 ) for example is a good read.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #50
Exactly, we just have to read the first paragraph of the introduction of the above cited PRA paper to set the records straight:

Wiseman et al, PRA 60, 2474 (1999)
The quantum jump, the effectively instantaneous transi-
tion of an atom from one state to another, was the first form
of nontrivial quantum dynamics to be postulated [1]. Of
course Bohr’s theory did not survive the quantum revolution
of the 1920s. In particular, the idea of jumps appeared to be
in sharp conflict with the continuity of Schro¨dinger’s wave
mechanics [2]. In the aftermath of the revolution, quantum
jumps were revived [3] with a new interpretation as state
reduction caused by measurement. But Wigner and Weis-
skopf [4] had already derived the exponential decay of spon-
taneous emission from the coupling of the atomic dipole to
the continuum of electromagnetic field modes. That is, they
did not require the hypothesis of quantum jumps. Later, more
sophisticated theoretical techniques, such as the master equa-
tion, were developed for dealing with the irreversible dynam-
ics of such open quantum systems [5-7]. In the master equa-
tion description, the atom’s state evolves smoothly and
deterministically. Perhaps as a consequence, interest in quan-
tum jumps as a way of describing of atomic dynamics faded.
Indeed, for a textbook treatment of "quantum jumps" (neglecting however spontaneous emission) see the famous Wigner-Weisskopf treatment of decays, nicely covered in

O. Nachtman, Elementary Particle Physics, Springer
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #51
vanhees71 said:
Exactly, we just have to read the first paragraph of the introduction of the above cited PRA paper to set the records straight:
[...]

Indeed, for a textbook treatment of "quantum jumps" (neglecting however spontaneous emission) see the famous Wigner-Weisskopf treatment of decays, nicely covered in

O. Nachtman, Elementary Particle Physics, Springer

Well, you might want to become a politician. I have rarely seen a quote taken so out of context. ;)

The relevant part is of course:
Wiseman said:
However, it was the electron shelving experiments of Itano and co-workers [10] which refocused attention on the conditional dynamics of individual atoms. Subsequent work on waiting time distributions [11,12] led to a renewal of interest in quantum jump descriptions [13]. It was shown by Carmichael [14] that quantum jumps are an implicit part of standard photodetection theory. This link between continuous quantum measurement theory and stochastic quantum evolution for the pure state of the system was considered by many other workers around the same time and subsequently [15–24]. Independently, Dalibard, Castin, and Mölmer [25] derived the same stochastic Schro¨dinger equations, driven by the need for efficient methods for numerically simulating moderately large quantum systems. This technique, called Monte Carlo wave-function simulations, has been applied to great advantage in describing the optical cooling of a fluorescent atom [26–30]. Regardless of the motivation for their use, the evolution of systems undergoing quantum jumps and other stochastic quantum processes is known widely as quantum trajectories [14].

Of course you do not need quantum jumps (apart from the meaning that the energies of the states taken on are of course discrete) to describe basic introductory textbook physics, but also of course Wigner-Weisskopf is of absolutely no use beyond weak coupling. And strong coupling /dressed states are the topic of the cited paper and also of the major part of quantum optics within the last 30 years or so. As soon as you need to take the environment seriously, you need a more sophisticated description. And the number of real working physicists working on still reproducing basic textbook physics is somewhat small...
 
  • #53
If we isolate the system the atom & the electromagnetic field around it, it is a very ordinary quantum system whose wave function evolves in a smooth way. In that sense there are no "jumps". It is just like the double well thought experiment which I brought up, but there are more variables in the wave function.

However, you can probably find mathematical descriptions where the wave function is computed as an interference pattern of various "paths". That is, you compute a path integral in the Feynman style. Maybe in those descriptions something will come up which you could call "jumps".

In the case of the double well, the slow leak of the probability amplitude to the neighboring well might have a description as a process where a particle moves over the potential wall, and you might call that a "jump". If the wall is high, we call it "tunneling".
 
  • #54
Cthugha said:
Well, you might want to become a politician. I have rarely seen a quote taken so out of context. ;)

The relevant part is of course:Of course you do not need quantum jumps (apart from the meaning that the energies of the states taken on are of course discrete) to describe basic introductory textbook physics, but also of course Wigner-Weisskopf is of absolutely no use beyond weak coupling. And strong coupling /dressed states are the topic of the cited paper and also of the major part of quantum optics within the last 30 years or so. As soon as you need to take the environment seriously, you need a more sophisticated description. And the number of real working physicists working on still reproducing basic textbook physics is somewhat small...
My only point is that according to quantum mechanics there are no discontinous jumps for the occupation probabilities. These are smooth functions of time according to quantum dynamics, and that's made very clear in the introductory paragraph of the paper, explaining clearly what's meant by "quantum jumps" in the context of modern QT. The rest of the paper deals with precisely this dynamics for their case of an "open quantum system". Of course, that's not governed by Wigner-Weisskopf approximations, but that's where you first learn on hand of a simple example that there are no instantaneous jumps in QT.
 
  • #55
Heikki Tuuri said:
If we isolate the system the atom & the electromagnetic field around it, it is a very ordinary quantum system whose wave function evolves in a smooth way.

Well, a lot of experimentalists would be very thankful if you told them how to do the isolation in practice. Coupling to an uncontrollable environment is an experimental reality. Just ignoring this by saying that one could do the isolation in practice is like optimizing a farm for point-like cows in vacuum or like saying that there is no need for thermodynamics because you can in principle perform a microscopic calculation of the behaviour of [itex]10^{23}[/itex] particles. Technically that is of course correct, but you do not get far with it.

vanhees71 said:
My only point is that according to quantum mechanics there are no discontinous jumps for the occupation probabilities. These are smooth functions of time according to quantum dynamics, and that's made very clear in the introductory paragraph of the paper, explaining clearly what's meant by "quantum jumps" in the context of modern QT. The rest of the paper deals with precisely this dynamics for their case of an "open quantum system". Of course, that's not governed by Wigner-Weisskopf approximations, but that's where you first learn on hand of a simple example that there are no instantaneous jumps in QT.

Sure, I do not disagree with that. Unless you want to enforce a microscopic description of the measurement problem, there is nothing jump-like in QT. Here, I consider Carmichael's approach as quite nice because it allows one to avoid the measurement problem to some degree simply by taking the ensemble average and "picking" all the subensembles that are compatible with the measurement history.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #56
"The problem of quantum jumps is that quantum physicists are always jumping to conclusions."
-Matt Leifer
 
  • Haha
  • Like
Likes Demystifier and vanhees71
  • #57
Cthugha said:
Well, a lot of experimentalists would be very thankful if you told them how to do the isolation in practice. Coupling to an uncontrollable environment is an experimental reality. Just ignoring this by saying that one could do the isolation in practice is like optimizing a farm for point-like cows in vacuum or like saying that there is no need for thermodynamics because you can in principle perform a microscopic calculation of the behaviour of [itex]10^{23}[/itex] particles. Technically that is of course correct, but you do not get far with it.
Sure, I do not disagree with that. Unless you want to enforce a microscopic description of the measurement problem, there is nothing jump-like in QT. Here, I consider Carmichael's approach as quite nice because it allows one to avoid the measurement problem to some degree simply by taking the ensemble average and "picking" all the subensembles that are compatible with the measurement history.
There's nothing jumplike in the measurement problem. The only problem with some Copenhagen flavors of "interpretation" is the introduction of the collapse, which is neither needed nor physically consistent. That's why I follow the minimal statistical interpretation which, with a grain of salt, is just Copenhagen without collapse. Although I cannot be sure about this, because of Bohr's very murky style of writing intermingling always unsharp philosophy with science, this seems to be more or less Bohr's point of view.
 
  • #58
vanhees71 said:
the introduction of the collapse, which is neither needed nor physically consistent. That's why I follow the minimal statistical interpretation
Some form of collapse is necessary, for example to be able to say which state is prepared after passing a polarization filter. The minimal statistical interpretation has no rule for telling which state is prepared.

The collapse (in the general form of nonorthogonal projections related to POVMs) is also physically consistent as it correctly describes the net dynamics of an important class of open systems, including the system under discussion in this thread. There is no conflict with the unitary Schrödinger dynamics since the latter is claimed to be valid only for isolated systems, i.e., strictly speaking only for the universe as a whole. (There is no other truly isolated physical system.)
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #59
Which state is prepared after a polarization filter has nothing to do with collapse. It's through LOCAL interactions as described by relativistic QFT. That's utmost important in the context of entanglement and experiments at far-distant places on entangled systems (like the paradigmatic experiments with polarization-entangled photons in various setups).

I agree with the second statement, though I have still no clue, what the "universe as a whole" should be, let alone how to describe it adequately within QT. This is the one pressing real physical problem of contemporary physics!
 
  • #60
vanhees71 said:
Which state is prepared after a polarization filter has nothing to do with collapse. It's through LOCAL interactions as described by relativistic QFT.
The effective collapse is needed for this on the level of ordinary quantum mechanics, as tested in foundational experiments. Thus it is a rule needed to be able to work with quantum mechanics in practice.

Moreover, if you give the argument from QFT in more detail, you'll see that you need a collapse argument along the way. Please justify how to do it without the collapse!
 
  • #61
vanhees71 said:
There's nothing jumplike in the measurement problem. The only problem with some Copenhagen flavors of "interpretation" is the introduction of the collapse, which is neither needed nor physically consistent. That's why I follow the minimal statistical interpretation which, with a grain of salt, is just Copenhagen without collapse. Although I cannot be sure about this, because of Bohr's very murky style of writing intermingling always unsharp philosophy with science, this seems to be more or less Bohr's point of view.

Well, I do not disagree - at least I think so (and for the record: as an experimentalist I try to avoid discussing interpretations unless they advance to the point where they stop being mere interpretations and make predictions that can be tested experimentally or suggest a mathematical formalism that is easier to handle or results in computational speed-up).

In this field of physics people are usually interested in experiments involving conditional probabilities based on measurement outcomes of photon detection events, so there is some need to take measurements into account explicitly. If your take on this is that one should evaluate this using unitary evolution of the system, determine the probabilities for the outcomes of the first measurement, consider the unitary evolution of this system from the possible eigenstates again, determine the probabilities for the outcome of the second measurement again and so on and so forth: yes, this works. If you additionally assume that the measurement process (or decoherence or whatever you may call it) in this case is essentially a low-probability game - which means that you rather do not have a single photon interact with a single absorber in a manner that you drive the probability amplitude for absorption up to 1, but rather that you have this single photon interact with thousands of absorbers, where each of them is driven to absorption probabilities of, say, 0.03 and one of them finally "clicks": yes, this is still a fast but continuous process and you can still get the correct probabilities for this by following all the subensembles microscopically.

However, in terms of actual modeling, this approach is quite cumbersome. For open systems and a huge environment, I think it is only natural that people try to treat the environment in a more effective way and the quantum jump formalism is a natural one - treating the wavefunction instead of the density matrix saves a lot of time. Many people consider the "quantum jump" as a rather Bayesian update of our information about the system instead of being inherent. I always thought that within an open systems scenario, where one does not have access to the full information about the system, this is the closest thing to the bare minimal interpretation you can get.
 
  • #62
vanhees71 said:
I agree with the second statement, though I have still no clue, what the "universe as a whole" should be, let alone how to describe it adequately within QT.
Well, since it is only a single system, in is not covered by the statistical interpretation. This explain why you cannot describe it adequately within your interpretation framework.

With the thermal interpretation, there is no difficulty to describe it adequately, i.e., in a way matching all experiments known. For this, one doesn't have to solve all problems of quantum gravity.
 
  • #63
vanhees71 said:
"quantum jumps" (which do not exist according to modern QT since 1925/26)
From where did you get your account of history?

In his 1927 paper ''Das Adiabatenprinzip in der Quantenmechanik'', where Born derived the general rules for the scattering of a single particle that form until today the standard introduction to scattering, he writes (p.170 and p.172):
Max Born said:
Datum scheint mir eine dringliche Aufgabe festzustellen, wie wir die mathematisch so glänzende Wellenmechanik mit der experimentell so fruchtbaren Vorstellungsweise der Quantensprünge vereinbar ist. Die Frage lautet also: In welchen Fällen lassen sich die Ergebnisse der Wellenmechanik in der Sprache der Quantensprünge interpretieren? [...]
Der Einzelprozeß, der ''Quantensprung'', ist also nicht kausal festgelegt, wohl aber die a-priori-Wahrscheinlichkeit für sein Auftreten; und zwar wird diese durch einen Integrationsprozeß der
Schrödingerschen Differentialgleichung bestimmt, der dem entsprechenden der klassischen Mechanik ganz analog ist und der zwei stationäre Zeitintervalle mit endlicher Zwischenzeit in gegenseitige Beziehung setzt. Der Sprung geht also über einen beträchtlichen Abgrund; was
während des Sprunges passiert, läßt sich schwerlich mit den Begriffen der Bohrschen Theorie beschreiben, ja vielleicht überhaupt nicht in elner Sprache, die unserem Anschanungsvermógen Bilder suggeriert.[...]
Das Quadrat ##|b_{nm}|^2## ist gemäß unserer Grundhypothese die Wahrscheinlichkeit dafür, daß das System sich nach Ablauf der Störung I am Zustand ##m## befindet.
Thus he identified - more than a year after your suggested fake history - the quantum jump with the
unpredictable outcome of a scattering experiment - a jump from being in one energy eigenstate to being in another energy eigenstate, thereby consolidating his probability interpretation!

It pays to read the originals to see what was really claimed when!
 
  • #64
A. Neumaier said:
The effective collapse is needed for this on the level of ordinary quantum mechanics, as tested in foundational experiments. Thus it is a rule needed to be able to work with quantum mechanics in practice.

Moreover, if you give the argument from QFT in more detail, you'll see that you need a collapse argument along the way. Please justify how to do it without the collapse!
To the contrary, may I ask you to tell me, where you need a collapse? You cannot use standard QED and propose the collapse argument, because that's contradicting each other.

Formally the interaction of the electromagnetic fields with matter is given by the corresponding in-medium photon polarization (aka dielectric function). No need for any collapse ;-).
 
  • #65
Cthugha said:
Well, I do not disagree - at least I think so (and for the record: as an experimentalist I try to avoid discussing interpretations unless they advance to the point where they stop being mere interpretations and make predictions that can be tested experimentally or suggest a mathematical formalism that is easier to handle or results in computational speed-up).

In this field of physics people are usually interested in experiments involving conditional probabilities based on measurement outcomes of photon detection events, so there is some need to take measurements into account explicitly. If your take on this is that one should evaluate this using unitary evolution of the system, determine the probabilities for the outcomes of the first measurement, consider the unitary evolution of this system from the possible eigenstates again, determine the probabilities for the outcome of the second measurement again and so on and so forth: yes, this works. If you additionally assume that the measurement process (or decoherence or whatever you may call it) in this case is essentially a low-probability game - which means that you rather do not have a single photon interact with a single absorber in a manner that you drive the probability amplitude for absorption up to 1, but rather that you have this single photon interact with thousands of absorbers, where each of them is driven to absorption probabilities of, say, 0.03 and one of them finally "clicks": yes, this is still a fast but continuous process and you can still get the correct probabilities for this by following all the subensembles microscopically.

However, in terms of actual modeling, this approach is quite cumbersome. For open systems and a huge environment, I think it is only natural that people try to treat the environment in a more effective way and the quantum jump formalism is a natural one - treating the wavefunction instead of the density matrix saves a lot of time. Many people consider the "quantum jump" as a rather Bayesian update of our information about the system instead of being inherent. I always thought that within an open systems scenario, where one does not have access to the full information about the system, this is the closest thing to the bare minimal interpretation you can get.
My very general point is precisely this: You don't have interpretational problems in the lab. Of course, the design of an experiment may be technically very challenging, but for this you use just quantum theory as it is used in practice, and there's no interpretational problem, which is obvious for the simple reason that the so designed experiments work as predicted. For me a physical theory has only a problem, if reproducible experiments contradict unanimously its predictions.

Of course you are right in saying that it's impossible to treat these interactions in full microscopic detail. That's where the methods of quantum statistics and corresponding coarse-graining procedures come into the game. I'm not an expert in quantum optics, but reading in some textbooks and also the one or the other research paper, I've the impression that many things simply boil down to use effective (linear or non-linear) constitutive relations to describe the electromagnetic response of the "matter" to describe lenses, beam splitters and all that and then apply it to single-photon states. Obviously this works very well, and I don't see any fundamental problem in it.

Also theoretical condensed-matter physics is a "whole industry" to find models to derive such effective phenomenological "constitutive relations", and also this is quite successful.

So from a physicist's point of view there's no fundamental problem with quantum theory, when applied to macroscopic systems and to the interaction of microscopic systems with macroscopic systems, and measurement devices are nothing else than macroscopic systems.
 
  • #66
A. Neumaier said:
From where did you get your account of history?

In his 1927 paper ''Das Adiabatenprinzip in der Quantenmechanik'', where Born derived the general rules for the scattering of a single particle that form until today the standard introduction to scattering, he writes (p.170 and p.172):

Thus he identified - more than a year after your suggested fake history - the quantum jump with the
unpredictable outcome of a scattering experiment - a jump from being in one energy eigenstate to being in another energy eigenstate, thereby consolidating his probability interpretation!

It pays to read the originals to see what was really claimed when!
I didn't claim this in a science historical sense. Of course in the early time of modern quantum theory the probabilistic interpretation had to be formulated first. That at such early stages the full understanding was not reached is natural. The same is true for the theory of relativity. In some cases it took more than 50 years to gain the correct understanding (e.g., for thermodynamics and the transformation properties of the thermodynamical quantities).

Nevertheless I've also read some of these old papers, and there already the full theory is present, and there's simply nothing like quantum jumps. It's all described by partial differential equations, where nothing jumps. Already writing down a differential equation for the time evolution implies that there are no jumps. I have to read the specific paper you quote from, but of course born talks about "quantum jumps", because that was the common Bohr theory, and of course the successes of the Bohr theory had to be also consolidated in the new theory.
 
  • #67
vanhees71 said:
To the contrary, may I ask you to tell me, where you need a collapse? You cannot use standard QED and propose the collapse argument, because that's contradicting each other.

Formally the interaction of the electromagnetic fields with matter is given by the corresponding in-medium photon polarization (aka dielectric function). No need for any collapse ;-).
In-medium photon polarization does not tell what happens to a single photon. It gives a finite-time description of fields only.
 
  • #68
vanhees71 said:
Already writing down a differential equation for the time evolution implies that there are no jumps.
Well, the jump of a person over an obstacle is also described by a differential equation. Nevertheless it is a jump. That a jump takes time is obvious.
vanhees71 said:
Born talks about "quantum jumps", because that was the common Bohr theory
And why does Herzberg 20 years later (see #46) still talk about quantum jumps as synonymous with electronic transitions?
 
Last edited:
  • #69
A. Neumaier said:
In-medium photon polarization does not tell what happens to a single photon. It gives a finite-time description of fields only.
It gives an accurate description of what happens to the single photons used all the time in the quantum opticians' labs. As far as I can see, all the phantastic results can be understood by an effective theory describing the single-photon matter interaction by (even quite standard) constitutive laws like indices of refraction etc. Of course you also need some "non-linear optics" due to strong laser fields and to understand parametric fluorescence (parametric downconversion), which is the most important technique to provide stable and efficient sources of polarization (as well as momentum) entangled photon pairs.
 
  • #70
A. Neumaier said:
Well, the jump of a person over an obstacle is also described by a differential equation. Nevertheless it is a jump. That a jump takes time is obvious.

And why does Herzberg 20 years later (see #46) still talk about quantum jumps as synonymous with electronic transitions?
It's, because physicists just use their jargon. It's very clear what they mean, but only among physicists. One has to read the papers to understand what's really meant, when physicists write about "quantum jumps", "wave particle dualism", and all that jargon from the short era of "old quantum mechanics", which was obsolete only 25 years after its discovery by Planck and Einstein.

Given, how long Aristotelian physics survived, that's however not that bad a record to getting the facts straight. Nevertheless the use of these outdated notions by physicists even in scientific papers and (even worse) introductory textbooks is indeed a bad habit, but what can you do...

Another example is the claim by almost all HEP physicists that the Higgs mechanism is some spontaneous symmetry breaking. I'm pretty sure that a majority of these people know that this is self-contradicting due to Elitzur's theorem, but it seems very hard to convince people just to call it "Higgsing a local gauge symmetry" than to call it "spontaneous breaking of local gauge symmetry". As I said, it's a bad habit...
 

Similar threads

Replies
143
Views
8K
2
Replies
46
Views
6K
Replies
11
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
14
Views
2K
Replies
17
Views
4K
Replies
6
Views
1K
Back
Top