Supervenience Thesis, Valid or Not?

  • Thread starter Q_Goest
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Thesis
In summary, the supervenience thesis is a fundamental axiom in cognitive science that states that phenomenal properties supervene on physical properties. It is widely accepted among philosophers, although some may refer to it simply as supervenience. The concept can be explained using the terminology of A and B things, where A represents mental or phenomenal states and B represents physical states. However, there are debates about the necessity of the supervenience relation and its implications on issues such as mental causation. Some argue that it is ontologically innocent, while others disagree and see it as an additional ontological commitment. Overall, the validity of the supervenience thesis remains a central issue in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind.
  • #1
Q_Goest
Science Advisor
Homework Helper
Gold Member
3,012
42
For those interested in cognitive science, the supervenience thesis seems to be one of those fundamental axioms which goes unsaid. If it needs to be said however, I think Tim Maudlin1 summed it up best:
Of course, the thesis that physically identical brains would support phenomenally identical states of consciousness is not analytic. But some such physicalist assumption underlies all contemporary research into perception and neuro-physiology. Furthermore, it seems to be an essential thesis for the computationalist. For computational structure supervenes on physical structure, so physically identical brains are also computationally identical. Hence, any mental property that can be given a purely computational analysis ought to be shared by physically identical brains.

In sequel, a somewhat stronger claim about supervenience shall be employed. States of awareness and sensory events take place in time; they are fairly precisely datable. One can assert that Sam had a toothache at 12:05 or that Sheila spent five minutes wondering about Fermat’s last theorem. A natural, indeed nearly inescapable, explanation for this is that conscious events and episodes supervene on concurrent physical events and processes. One’s phenomenal state at a time is determined entirely by one’s brain activity at that time. Hence, two physical systems engaged in precisely the same physical activity through a time will support the same modes of consciousness (if any) through that time. Let us call this the supervenience thesis.
Seems that all other philosophers have the same views of supervenience, and in fact, the term has a unique meaning in philosophy. Philosophers widely accept that phenomenal properties supervene on physical properties. Most however, don’t refer to this as the “supervenience thesis” but simply as supervenience.

Another good explanation of supervenience is in the http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/" where the use of A and B things is common terminology:
The core idea of supervenience is captured by the slogan, “there cannot be an A-difference without a B-difference.” It is important to notice the word ‘cannot’. Supervenience claims do not merely say that it just so happens that there is no A-difference without a B-difference; they say that there cannot be one. A-properties supervene on B-properties if and only if a difference in A-properties requires a difference in B-properties—or, equivalently, if and only if exact similarity with respect to B-properties guarantees exact similarity with respect to A-properties.

Ok, so that sounds easy enough. The obvious example would be that A represents mental or phenomenal states and B represents physical states, though the terminology can be used also for other, less controversial concepts. However, there are obvious issues that arise when we apply this concept, such as:
But there is vigorous disagreement about whether the supervenience relation holds with metaphysical or merely nomological necessity. Ask yourself—could there be an individual that has no conscious experience at all, despite being physically indiscernible from an individual that is conscious (Kirk 1994; Chalmers 1996)? That is, could there be what philosophers call a ‘zombie’? Because it is widely agreed that the mental nomologically supervenes on the physical, it is widely agreed that zombies are nomologically impossible—that their existence would violate psychophysical laws.

And also the problems with mental causation:

Some think that supervenience is indeed ontologically innocent in this sense. After all, if the A-properties supervene with metaphysical necessity on the B-properties, then they come along automatically given the B-properties. To borrow Kripke's metaphor (1972, 153-154), once God fixes the B-properties, she is all done; she does not need to do anything further to get the A-properties going. Indeed, she cannot block them. Given the distribution of B-properties, there is no further question about which A-properties are instantiated. So, it is claimed, the latter are nothing over and above the former. However, other people vigorously resist this idea. How can the A-properties not count as a further ontological commitment, if they are numerically distinct from the B-properties?
This dispute is central to various issues in metaphysics and the philosophy of mind. For example, nonreductive physicalists often say that mental properties are distinct from but nonetheless “nothing over and above” physical ones. Their reductivist opponents, however, clearly think that this is illegitimate. This can be seen in the charge that nonreductive physicalists face the exclusion problem—that they are unable to account for the causal efficacy of the mental without claiming that all of its effects are “double-caused.”

So what should it be? Is the supervenience thesis valid or not?

1. Maudlin, T; 1989, ‘Computation and Consciousness’, Journal of Philosophy 86:407-432
 
Last edited by a moderator:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Q_Goest said:
For those interested in cognitive science, the supervenience thesis seems to be one of those fundamental axioms which goes unsaid. If it needs to be said however, I think Tim Maudlin1 summed it up best:

Seems that all other philosophers have the same views of supervenience, and in fact, the term has a unique meaning in philosophy. Philosophers widely accept that phenomenal properties supervene on physical properties. Most however, don’t refer to this as the “supervenience thesis” but simply as supervenience.

Another good explanation of supervenience is in the http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/" where the use of A and B things is common terminology:


Ok, so that sounds easy enough. The obvious example would be that A represents mental or phenomenal states and B represents physical states, though the terminology can be used also for other, less controversial concepts. However, there are obvious issues that arise when we apply this concept, such as:


And also the problems with mental causation:



So what should it be? Is the supervenience thesis valid or not?

1. Maudlin, T; 1989, ‘Computation and Consciousness’, Journal of Philosophy 86:407-432
The fixed B-properties are too open to allow
meaningful fixing of the A-properites, unless
she (God) stipulated conditions such as 'I am
done' etc.

Increased complexity in A-properties (for example
informatic manipulation) would allow indistinguishable
apparently unrelated ontologies to occur.

So, my vote is that supervenience is not a valid theory.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #3
.

I would say that the supervenience thesis is a valid concept, but it is not without its limitations and controversies. It provides a useful framework for understanding the relationship between physical and mental properties and their potential causal interactions. However, the extent to which it holds with metaphysical or nomological necessity is still a subject of debate, and the concept of mental causation raises important questions about the nature of consciousness and its role in the physical world. As with any philosophical concept, it is important to critically examine and evaluate its implications and limitations in order to further our understanding of the mind and its relationship to the brain.
 

FAQ: Supervenience Thesis, Valid or Not?

What is the Supervenience Thesis?

The Supervenience Thesis is a philosophical concept that states that all higher-level properties of a system are determined by the lower-level properties of that system. This means that any changes in the lower-level properties will result in changes in the higher-level properties.

What does it mean for the Supervenience Thesis to be valid?

A valid Supervenience Thesis means that the higher-level properties of a system are indeed determined by the lower-level properties, and any changes in the lower-level properties will necessarily result in changes in the higher-level properties. In other words, there is a strict dependence between the two levels of properties.

Is the Supervenience Thesis a universally accepted concept?

No, the Supervenience Thesis is a highly debated concept in philosophy and has not been universally accepted. There are various arguments against its validity, including the possibility of emergent properties that cannot be explained by lower-level properties.

How is the Supervenience Thesis related to reductionism?

The Supervenience Thesis is often seen as a form of reductionism, as it claims that higher-level properties can be reduced to lower-level properties. However, some argue that reductionism goes beyond the Supervenience Thesis, as it also asserts that higher-level properties are nothing more than the sum of their lower-level parts.

Can the Supervenience Thesis be applied to all systems?

The applicability of the Supervenience Thesis is still a topic of debate. Some argue that it can only be applied to physical systems, while others argue that it can also be applied to mental and social systems. However, there are also criticisms that the Supervenience Thesis may not be applicable to all types of systems, such as those involving emergence or non-linear dynamics.

Back
Top