The Schwarzschild Geometry: Part 4 - Comments

In summary: The white hole horizon is conceptually really bizarre...Since nothing is allowed to get in, that means that 'test' particles traveling in orbits around the white hole horizon (more precisely the particle horizon) will accumulate there, and there will be a severe blue shift when viewed from infinity. This blue sheet is a sort of classical instability, and it is argued that it leads to gravitational collapse, and thus there is likely a singularity in the future as well! This blue sheet is a sort of classical instability, but I'm not sure what you mean by "classical instability."
  • #1
47,459
23,741
PeterDonis submitted a new PF Insights post

The Schwarzschild Geometry: Part 4

SchwarzschildGeometry4.png


Continue reading the Original PF Insights Post.
 
  • Like
Likes berkeman, m4r35n357 and Greg Bernhardt
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
There are a few other really interesting points about region III and region IV.
1) There is a serious Cauchy problem with having a past singularity that is allowed to communicate information off to infinity.

2) The white hole horizon is conceptually really bizarre...
Since nothing is allowed to get in, that means that 'test' particles traveling in orbits around the white hole horizon (more precisely the particle horizon) will accumulate there, and there will be a severe blue shift when viewed from infinity. This blue sheet is a sort of classical instability, and it is argued that it leads to gravitational collapse, and thus there is likely a singularity in the future as well! See:

Death of White Holes in the Early Universe - Eardley, Douglas M. Phys.Rev.Lett. 33 (1974) 442-444

3) Quantum mechanically, if you believe in Hawking radiation/evaporation, and black hole thermodynamics, in some sense black hole and white hole microstates have to be the same thing! See:
Black Holes and Thermodynamics - Hawking, S.W. Phys.Rev. D13 (1976) 191-197
 
  • #3
Haelfix said:
There is a serious Cauchy problem with having a past singularity that is allowed to communicate information off to infinity.

If "Cauchy problem" is intended to mean that the spacetime has a Cauchy horizon, this is not true. The Schwarzschild spacetime is globally hyperbolic.

It is true that the past singularity seems highly unphysical, but I'm not sure "Cauchy problem" is the best way to describe why.

Haelfix said:
Since nothing is allowed to get in, that means that 'test' particles traveling in orbits around the white hole horizon (more precisely the particle horizon) will accumulate there

Which test particles are these? If they are test particles in stable orbits in region I, they can equally well be viewed as orbiting the black hole; they certainly don't accumulate near the white hole horizon.

If you mean test particles that are close to the white hole horizon, there are no stable orbits there; there are no stable orbits inside ##r = 6M##, and there are no orbits at all, even unstable ones, inside ##r = 3M##. So any freely falling object below ##r = 3M## will fall into the black hole, region II; it won't "accumulate" at the white hole horizon.

Haelfix said:
there will be a severe blue shift when viewed from infinity

Not for objects that are free-falling radially inward. They will see incoming light from infinity to be redshifted.

Objects in free-fall orbits will see incoming light from infinity to be blueshifted, but at the lowest possible orbit, ##r = 3M##, the blueshift is quite modest.

Objects that have nonzero proper acceleration can "hover" close to the horizon and will indeed see a large blueshift in light coming in from infinity. But this is due to their proper acceleration, which increases without bound as the horizon is approached.

All of this is standard Schwarzschild spacetime physics; none of that changes when we include the full maximally extended spacetime in our model.

Haelfix said:
See:

Death of White Holes in the Early Universe - Eardley, Douglas M. Phys.Rev.Lett. 33 (1974) 442-444

Unfortunately this paper is behind a paywall so I can't access it. If you want to email me a copy, I'm at peterdonis@alum.mit.edu. I would be curious to read the paper and see exactly what spacetime geometry it is assuming. Since it is dealing with the early universe, it obviously is not using a vacuum geometry, and the Schwarzschild spacetime I am discussing in this series is a vacuum solution (except for the Oppenheimer-Snyder model, which has a non-vacuum region, but that model also has no region III or IV so it's not relevant here). In short, I'm not sure the term "white hole" in that paper means the same thing as I mean by "white hole" in these articles.
 
  • #4
Haelfix said:
Quantum mechanically, if you believe in Hawking radiation/evaporation, and black hole thermodynamics, in some sense black hole and white hole microstates have to be the same thing!

I'm aware of this hypothesis by Hawking, but I don't know if it has led to anything in the field of quantum gravity.
 
  • #6
PeterDonis said:
If "Cauchy problem" is intended to mean that the spacetime has a Cauchy horizon, this is not true. The Schwarzschild spacetime is globally hyperbolic.

A Cauchy problem ('initial value problem') in GR is a statement about taking surfaces of initial data (in GR-- spacelike surfaces but they could in principle also involve data from other matter fields) and developing them forward in some regular way subject to the relevant partial differential equations such that the process satisfies certain constraints (basically you want reversibility, avoiding many to one mappings, etc). Here, the initial data surface is singular as there is geodesic incompleteness, and physically this manifests itself as a loss of predictability between any 'two' distinct states in the theory, provided the singular surface was is in at least ones past lightcone. Basically you are taking an infinite amount of information (states) and allowing that to propagate throughout spacetime. This language is often used when discussing formulations of cosmic censorship, but for some reason that I don't understand the FRW singularity and the White hole singularity seem to be excluded from theorems about cosmic censorship (probably b/c they are trivial).

PeterDonis said:
Since it is dealing with the early universe, it obviously is not using a vacuum geometry, and the Schwarzschild spacetime I am discussing in this series is a vacuum solution (except for the Oppenheimer-Snyder model, which has a non-vacuum region, but that model also has no region III or IV so it's not relevant here). In short, I'm not sure the term "white hole" in that paper means the same thing as I mean by "white hole" in these articles.

Sorry I'm not being clear here. The geometry I'm referring to is not vacuum, but it is somewhat similar to Oppenheimer Snyder which you were discussing. It is the *perturbed* extended Schwarzschild solution with an infalling sheet of spherically symmetric null dust. Unfortunately I'm now away from my institution for the holidays, and it seems hard to find material discussing this that's not behind a paywall (there is a whole chapter about white hole instabilities in Novikov and Frolov), but for the Eardley instability I found roughly the picture I was looking for in the following paper, as well as some of the discussion of the setup: See figure 1
http://gravityresearchfoundation.org/pdf/awarded/1989/blau_guth.pdf

PeterDonis said:
I'm aware of this hypothesis by Hawking, but I don't know if it has led to anything in the field of quantum gravity.

Hawking's argument is a statement about semiclassical states and thermal equilibrium, and in my opinion is pretty convincing. Of course without knowing the degrees of freedom of quantum gravity, it's hard to speculate whether a similar thing holds true in the full theory or not.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #7
Haelfix said:
A Cauchy problem ('initial value problem') in GR is a statement about taking surfaces of initial data (in GR-- spacelike surfaces but they could in principle also involve data from other matter fields) and developing them forward in some regular way subject to the relevant partial differential equations

Ah, ok. I had seen that language before but got confused thinking of a Cauchy horizon.

Haelfix said:
Here, the initial data surface is singular as there is geodesic incompleteness

I am still confused by this, however. As I said before, the maximally extended Schwarzschild spacetime is globally hyperbolic; that means it automatically has a well-posed initial value problem. As an example of how to formulate it, the spacelike surface ##T = 0## in Kruskal-Szekeres coordinates is a Cauchy surface for the spacetime; appropriate initial data on that surface (basically the geometry of all the 2-spheres that make it up, which is equivalent to specifying the one free parameter ##M## in the line element) determines the entire spacetime. It is true that the entire spacetime thus determined is geodesically complete--more precisely, it is timelike geodesically incomplete. But that is not inconsistent with the spacetime being globally hyperbolic and having a well posed initial value problem.

Haelfix said:
The geometry I'm referring to is not vacuum, but it is somewhat similar to Oppenheimer Snyder which you were discussing. It is the *perturbed* extended Schwarzschild solution with an infalling sheet of spherically symmetric null dust.

I'll look at the paper you linked to and comment further after I've read it.
 
  • #8
Haelfix said:
A Cauchy problem ('initial value problem') in GR is a statement about taking surfaces of initial data (in GR-- spacelike surfaces but they could in principle also involve data from other matter fields) and developing them forward in some regular way subject to the relevant partial differential equations such that the process satisfies certain constraints (basically you want reversibility, avoiding many to one mappings, etc). Here, the initial data surface is singular as there is geodesic incompleteness, and physically this manifests itself as a loss of predictability between any 'two' distinct states in the theory, provided the singular surface was is in at least ones past lightcone. Basically you are taking an infinite amount of information (states) and allowing that to propagate throughout spacetime. This language is often used when discussing formulations of cosmic censorship, but for some reason that I don't understand the FRW singularity and the White hole singularity seem to be excluded from theorems about cosmic censorship (probably b/c they are trivial).

Can you elaborate, because as written it doesn't seem right? The initial hypersurface of the initial value problem is not singular. It is a complete Riemannian manifold. Its future (and past Cauchy) development is incomplete (Lorentzian manifold), but the initial data is as regular as it gets.
 
  • #9
So there are certainly spacelike Cauchy surfaces that one can construct that will have finite values for all physical quantities arbitrarily 'near' the singularity, but I don't believe this is sufficient condition for being a well posed surface (regular is I agree an incorrect word choice). There are other technical restrictions on the form of the initial data and I'd have to consult a textbook (im currently away) for the exact statements. Clearly having arbitrarily large(but finite) tidal forces is not what one would want for well behaved data.
 
  • #10
Haelfix said:
So there are certainly spacelike Cauchy surfaces that one can construct that will have finite values for all physical quantities arbitrarily 'near' the singularity, but I don't believe this is sufficient condition for being a well posed surface (regular is I agree an incorrect word choice). There are other technical restrictions on the form of the initial data and I'd have to consult a textbook (im currently away) for the exact statements. Clearly having arbitrarily large(but finite) tidal forces is not what one would want for well behaved data.

I don't think there is any problem, but I would like to know, so I'd like to see it when you find it.

It seems that you expect the initial hypersurface to be as far back in the past as possible, but that is not needed any surface could be used. For example a horizontal line that goes right in the middle of the diagram is as good as any other.
 
  • #11
Yes but think about it, any such line has access to the singularity region in its causal past. Surfaces that include data with arbitrarily large curvature invariants are thus being evolved forward with Einsteins equations, when they likely don't even obey the equation to begin with. The entire future spacetime is thus built out of that dubious development. When people formulate statements about cosmic censorship they are trying to formalize that notion somehow (and I know there are difficulties with making the statement precise). I'll look into it when I get the chance
 
  • #12
Haelfix said:
2) The white hole horizon is conceptually really bizarre...
Since nothing is allowed to get in, that means that 'test' particles traveling in orbits around the white hole horizon (more precisely the particle horizon) will accumulate there, and there will be a severe blue shift when viewed from infinity. This blue sheet is a sort of classical instability, and it is argued that it leads to gravitational collapse, and thus there is likely a singularity in the future as well!

Exactly what the white hole is is a little mysterious to me. It seems that there is a sense in which there is no difference in the spacetime geometry of a black hole and a white hole; the difference is simply initial conditions of the test particles traveling in that geometry.

Let me explain why I think that.

To simplify, let's talk about purely radial motion, so we can treat the Schwarzschild geometry as if there were only one spatial dimension. Let [itex]Q[/itex] be the Schwarzschild factor defined by: [itex]Q \equiv 1 - \frac{2GM}{c^2 r}[/itex]. Let [itex]\tau[/itex] be proper time. Let [itex]U^\mu \equiv \frac{\partial x^\mu}{\partial \tau}[/itex]. Then for a test particle of mass [itex]m[/itex] moving along a radial timelike geodesic, we have the following conserved quantities:
  1. [itex]K \equiv m c Q U^t[/itex]. This is sort of the "momentum" in the t-direction.
  2. [itex]H \equiv \frac{m c^2}{2} Q (U^t)^2 - \frac{m (U^r)^2}{2Q}[/itex]. This is actually [itex]\frac{mc^2}{2} \frac{ds^2}{d\tau^2}[/itex], so it's just equal to [itex]\frac{mc^2}{2}[/itex].
Putting these together gives an equation for [itex]U^r[/itex]:

[itex]\frac{m}{2} (U^r)^2 - \frac{GMm}{r} = \mathcal{E}[/itex]

where [itex]\mathcal{E} = \frac{K^2}{2 mc^2} - \frac{mc^2}{2}[/itex]

I wrote it in this way so that you can immediately see that it's just the energy equation for a test particle moving under Newtonian gravity. So without any mathematics, we can immediately guess the qualitative behavior:

If [itex]\mathcal{E} < 0[/itex], and initially, [itex]U^r > 0[/itex], then the test particle will rise to some maximum height: [itex]r_{max} = \frac{GMm}{|\mathcal{E}|}[/itex], and then will fall back to annihilation at [itex]r=0[/itex] in a finite amount of (proper) time. The interesting case is [itex]r_{max} > \frac{2GM}{c^2} \equiv r_S[/itex], where [itex]r_S[/itex] is the black hole's Schwarzschild radius. In that case, this scenario represents a particle rising from below the event horizon and then turning around and falling back through the event horizon.

That seems to contradict the fact that nothing can escape from the event horizon, but to see why it doesn't, you have to see what the time coordinate [itex]t[/itex] is doing: In the time period between the particle rising out of the event horizon and falling back into the event horizon, only a finite amount of proper time passes, but an infinite amount of coordinate time passes. In the far past, [itex]t \rightarrow -\infty[/itex], the particle arises from the event horizon, and in the far future, [itex]t \rightarrow +\infty[/itex], the particle sinks below the event horizon. The time period while the particle is rising up to the event horizon, and the time period while the particle is falling below the event horizon is not covered by the coordinate [itex]t[/itex] (well, you can still have a [itex]t[/itex] coordinate there, but its connection to the [itex]t[/itex] coordinate above the horizon is broken by the event horizon). So from the point of view of someone far from the black hole, using the [itex]t[/itex] coordinate for time, nothing ever crosses the event horizon (in either direction) for any finite value of [itex]t[/itex].

Going back to the test particle, we can identify the various parts of the Schwarzschild geometry:
  1. During the time that the particle is rising below the event horizon, the particle is traveling through Region IV, the white hole interior.
  2. During the time that the particle is above the event horizon, the particle is traveling through Region I, the black hole exterior.
  3. During the time that the particle is falling below the event horizon, the particle is traveling through Region II, the black hole interior.
(A fourth region, Region III, is not visited by the test particle, but is a black hole exterior like Region I).

The point is that nothing about the local geometry of spacetime changes in going from Region IV (the white hole interior) to Region II (the black hole interior). The only difference is the sign of [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}[/itex]. So the difference between a black hole and a white hole is simply the initial conditions of the test particle. So it's not that the particle is repelled by the white hole and is attracted by the black hole. It's true by definition that:
  • If the test particle is below the event horizon and [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau} > 0[/itex], then the particle is in the black hole interior.
  • If the test particle is below the event horizon and [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau} < 0[/itex], then the particle is in the white hole interior.
As for the exterior, the same region, Region I, serves as the exterior of the white hole and the black hole. The same event horizon looks like a white hole in the far past [itex]t \rightarrow -\infty[/itex], because the test particle is rising from it, and looks like a black hole in the far future [itex]t \rightarrow +\infty[/itex], because the test particle is falling toward it. (For a realistic black hole formed from the collapsed of a star, there is no event horizon in the limit [itex]t \rightarrow -\infty[/itex], so there is no corresponding white hole.)

Here are some puzzles having to do with the test particles:
  1. In the case of many one test particles instead of just one, do all the particles have the same sign of [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}[/itex]? They are all falling in the black hole interior, and all rising in the white hole interior. Why aren't there some particles that are rising, while other particles are falling? It turns out that there is a simple answer to this question. If you have [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau} > 0[/itex], you can make it [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau} < 0[/itex] by reparametrizing: [itex]\tau \rightarrow -\tau[/itex]. So it's possible to arrange it so that all particles have the same sign of [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}[/itex].
  2. A followup to the first puzzle: If you just arbitrarily flip the sign of [itex]\tau[/itex] for a test particle, it makes no difference, since they have no internal state. But if instead you don't have a test particle, but a physical object, such as a clock or a human being, then flipping the sign of proper time means reversing the usual progression of states. The clock will start running backwards, and the human will start getting younger, instead of older. That's not technically a contradiction, because the laws of physics are reversible, so it's possible for a human to age backwards. But it's a violation of the law of increasing entropy. So if it happens to be the case (and it sure seems to be) that all processes in the universe have the same thermodynamic arrow of time--entropy increases as proper time increases--then puzzle number 1 switches to the question of why is there a universal thermodynamic arrow of time? This boils down to the question: Why was entropy lower in the far past? General Relativity doesn't answer this question. (I'm not sure what does
  3. Another complication is to include test particles that don't move on geodesics, because of non-gravitational forces. How does that affect the picture?
 
  • #13
stevendaryl said:
It's true by definition that:
  • If the test particle is below the event horizon and ##\frac{dr}{d\tau} > 0##, then the particle is in the black hole interior.
  • If the test particle is below the event horizon and ##\frac{dr}{d\tau} < 0##, then the particle is in the white hole interior.

You have these backwards.

stevendaryl said:
Why was entropy lower in the far past? General Relativity doesn't answer this question. (I'm not sure what does

We don't have a final answer to this question, because we don't know what preceded the hot, dense, rapidly expanding "Big Bang" state. We only know that the entropy of that state was much lower than the present entropy of the universe.

stevendaryl said:
Another complication is to include test particles that don't move on geodesics, because of non-gravitational forces. How does that affect the picture?

In regions IV and II (the white hole and black hole), it doesn't really change things at all: all test particles must still leave the white hole, and all test particles that enter the black hole still can't escape.

In region I (and III as well), it allows test particles that would otherwise fall into the black hole to avoid it and stay in region I (or III). It still doesn't allow anything to enter the white hole.
 
  • #14
To me there is a simple inverse symmetry between BH and WH : for a WH, the singularity is in the past light cone of every event in the interior, while for a BH it is the future light cone of every interior event.
 
  • #15
Haelfix said:
Surfaces that include data with arbitrarily large curvature invariants are thus being evolved forward with Einsteins equations

You don't have to evolve them forward. You can evolve the initial data on the hypersurface ##T = 0## in Kruskal-Szekeres coordinates both forwards and backwards. Doing so will give you the complete globally hyperbolic region, all the way back to the past singularity and forward to the future singularity. Since the equations are time symmetric, this is perfectly well-defined and justified.

Haelfix said:
when they likely don't even obey the equation to begin with.

I don't know what you're basing this on. The subject under discussion is a well-defined solution of the classical Einstein Field Equation. Any event with finite spacetime curvature invariants, including arbitrarily large ones, can occur in such a solution. The solution might not end up describing anything physically relevant, but that doesn't mean the points with large spacetime curvature values "don't obey the equation"; it just means physics, unlike this particular mathematical model, chooses some other equation at that point.
 
  • #16
Haelfix said:
Yes but think about it, any such line has access to the singularity region in its causal past. Surfaces that include data with arbitrarily large curvature invariants are thus being evolved forward with Einsteins equations, when they likely don't even obey the equation to begin with. The entire future spacetime is thus built out of that dubious development.

Well, it's not how it works. The initial data doesn't include anything from the past of the Cauchy surface. In fact until you solve the equations, there is no past nor future. The initial data consists of fields defined on the surface. Whatever the values of the past and future evolution may be, say arbitrary large, they are not part of the initial conditions. So there is nothing dubious here and by construction you get solutions to the Einstein equation.

When people formulate statements about cosmic censorship they are trying to formalize that notion somehow (and I know there are difficulties with making the statement precise). I'll look into it when I get the chance

I am not sure if this is relevant but one way the strong cosmic censorship conjecture is formulated is that the maximal Cauchy development is not extendible. Which is the case in Schawrtzschild, but not Kerr. The weak version usually asks for completeness of future null infinity.
 
  • #17
martinbn said:
Well, it's not how it works. The initial data doesn't include anything from the past of the Cauchy surface. In fact until you solve the equations, there is no past nor future. The initial data consists of fields defined on the surface. Whatever the values of the past and future evolution may be, say arbitrary large, they are not part of the initial conditions. So there is nothing dubious here and by construction you get solutions to the Einstein equation.

Sure, you can formally do this. Butt then I can formally take a line in the middle of the diagram, evolve it arbitrarily far backwards to the singularity region, then evolve it forward again back to the start. The two resulting hypersurfaces won't necessarily agree anymore depending upon details of what takes place near the singularity. This is why it's often said that naked singularities yield problems for determinism. So I would say the propriety of those sorts of manipulations are basically equivalent to whether you accept (weak) cosmic censorship or not.
 
  • #18
PeterDonis said:
You have these backwards.

Right. In the black hole interior, [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}< 0[/itex] and in the white hole interior, [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau} > 0[/itex].

So now I'm a little confused: What is it that prevents having two nearby test particles with opposite signs of [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}[/itex]?
 
  • #19
Haelfix said:
Sure, you can formally do this. Butt then I can formally take a line in the middle of the diagram, evolve it arbitrarily far backwards to the singularity region, then evolve it forward again back to the start. The two resulting hypersurfaces won't necessarily agree anymore depending upon details of what takes place near the singularity. This is why it's often said that naked singularities yield problems for determinism. So I would say the propriety of those sorts of manipulations are basically equivalent to whether you accept (weak) cosmic censorship or not.

I think the problem you are trying to highlight is merely that you can't use the white-hole singularity as a Cauchy surface. This doesn't mean that Cauchy surfaces don't exist. Informally, anything can come out of a white hole, much like anything can fall into a black hole.

I agree this leads to problems with causality in the eternal black hole spacetime, because effectively one cannot evolve from the infinite past into the infinite future. So one cannot answer the question, "What happens if I put a white hole in spacetime?" However, the Cauchy problem is not "What happens if I do something undefined?", but rather "Given that the current state is A, what happens next?"

PeterDonis said:
You don't have to evolve them forward. You can evolve the initial data on the hypersurface ##T = 0## in Kruskal-Szekeres coordinates both forwards and backwards. Doing so will give you the complete globally hyperbolic region, all the way back to the past singularity and forward to the future singularity. Since the equations are time symmetric, this is perfectly well-defined and justified.

I disagree with the terminology "globally hyperbolic" here. The equations of motion fail at the singularities, and the singularities are reachable in finite proper time. Thus the hyperbolic region is not "global".

The main issue here is the geodesic incompleteness at the singularities. This means you cannot just excise the singularities, as you could if they were "infinitely far away".

I don't know what you're basing this on. The subject under discussion is a well-defined solution of the classical Einstein Field Equation. Any event with finite spacetime curvature invariants, including arbitrarily large ones, can occur in such a solution. The solution might not end up describing anything physically relevant, but that doesn't mean the points with large spacetime curvature values "don't obey the equation"; it just means physics, unlike this particular mathematical model, chooses some other equation at that point.

The issue is that the singularities don't obey the equation. There is no sense in which they do (in contrast, e.g., to the singularity in the electric field of a point charge, which can be dealt with by using distributions).
 
  • #20
stevendaryl said:
What is it that prevents having two nearby test particles with opposite signs of ##\frac{dr}{d\tau}##?

The convention you just implicitly adopted for the direction along the worldline in which ##\tau## increases. To be fair, I slipped it in there without saying so. :wink:

A more explicit unpacking would be this: first, at every event in the spacetime, we make a choice of which half of the light cone is the "future" half, and which half is the "past" half, in such a way that the choice is continuous throughout the spacetime. There are only two ways of doing this: we can choose the half that points towards region II on the Kruskal diagram as the "future" half, or we can choose the half that points towards region IV. But once we've made that choice at one event, for continuity we have to make the same choice at every event. The usual convention is to choose the "future" half to point towards region II.

Then we just define ##\tau## along every timelike worldline such that it increases from the past to the future, as defined by the halves of the light cones. Once we've done that, then we must have ##dr / d\tau > 0## in region IV and ##dr / d\tau < 0## in region II along every timelike worldline.

If you think about it, you will see that there is no actual loss of generality in doing all this, because the spacetime as a whole is time symmetric.
 
  • #21
stevendaryl said:
Right. In the black hole interior, [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}< 0[/itex] and in the white hole interior, [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau} > 0[/itex].

So now I'm a little confused: What is it that prevents having two nearby test particles with opposite signs of [itex]\frac{dr}{d\tau}[/itex]?
Applying an orientation to an orientable spacetime involves choosing a consistent labeling of past/future of all light cones. Then, for any world line, a tangent directed one way (one sign, in your case) is future directed, while the other sign is past directed.
 
  • #22
Ben Niehoff said:
I disagree with the terminology "globally hyperbolic" here.

Then you disagree with Hawking & Ellis, not to mention every other textbook on GR that I'm aware of that discusses this topic. It's a standard term in the field.

Ben Niehoff said:
The equations of motion fail at the singularities, and the singularities are reachable in finite proper time.

The technical definition of "globally hyperbolic" allows this, because the manifold must be an open set, and the singularities are not part of the manifold. The fact that the globally hyperbolic region is geodesically incomplete does not prevent it from being globally hyperbolic. At least, not according to Hawking & Ellis and all the other textbooks.

Ben Niehoff said:
This means you cannot just excise the singularities

Sure you can; within the open set that constitutes the manifold, all curvature invariants are finite at every event.

Whether the resulting globally hyperbolic region is physically reasonable is a different question; AFAIK nobody thinks the white hole region is physically reasonable. But that doesn't change its mathematical properties. And AFAIK nobody thinks classical GR remains valid to arbitrarily large values of curvature invariants. But that doesn't change the mathematical properties either.

Ben Niehoff said:
The issue is that the singularities don't obey the equation.

That's irrelevant because the equation is never applied at the singularities. They're not part of the manifold.
 
  • #23
What, then, stops me from saying the Reissner-Nordstrom geometry is globally hyperbolic? Can't I just excise the Cauchy horizons (and whatever lies beyond them) and call it a day?

In a similar fashion, it seems I can call anything "globally hyperbolic", if I just cut out the bad parts and redefine what I'm talking about.
 
  • #24
Ben Niehoff said:
What, then, stops me from saying the Reissner-Nordstrom geometry is globally hyperbolic? Can't I just excise the Cauchy horizons (and whatever lies beyond them) and call it a day?

In a similar fashion, it seems I can call anything "globally hyperbolic", if I just cut out the bad parts and redefine what I'm talking about.

You can do that, but then you will have a space-time that is extendible (and it can be extended in more than one way).
 
  • #25
Most (open patches of) manifolds can be extended in more than one way. For example, ##ds^2 = -dt^2 + dx^2## could be Minkowski space, or it could be a torus. Minkowski space is globally hyperbolic, but a torus with a Lorentzian metric has closed timelike curves.

I can agree that if a smooth extension exists, then we shouldn't be referring to properties as "global". However, I am generically uncomfortable calling something "global" when our manifold is geodesically incomplete, even if all possible analytical continuations are singular.

If you can point to a mathematician's definition of "global" which is meant to include such cases, then obviously I'll have to change my mind. But physicists tend to be quite loose with this kind of terminology.

Although I suppose practically speaking in this case, it doesn't make much difference.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #26
Oh, I see, you are objecting about the use of global. I don't know, you might be right. But take a standard Friedman model. Why wouldn't we call it globally hyperbolic?

p.s. Perhaps one has to dig out the history of the terminology. May be this is how the PDE people speak.
 
  • #27
I'm not altogether familiar with cosmological metrics. Is the FLRW metric geodesically complete in the past? (Probably the answer depends on the matter content!)
 
  • #28
Some are incomplete in the past. If it falls under the assumptions of Hawking's theorem.
 
  • #29
Ben Niehoff said:
Most (open patches of) manifolds can be extended in more than one way.

This is true, and the Hawking & Ellis definition of a "manifold" includes the global topology, so Minkowski spacetime and the torus with Lorentzian metric are two different manifolds by this definition, even though they have the same local geometry.

Ben Niehoff said:
If you can point to a mathematician's definition of "global"

I don't know if it does. I was using a physicist's definition of "globally hyperbolic", which, as you say, might not be the term a mathematician would choose. (I'm not even sure about that, though; this aspect of GR relies heavily on differential geometry and topology.)

As far as I can tell, this Wikipedia page is a good summary of the Hawking & Ellis definition of a globally hyperbolic manifold:

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Globally_hyperbolic_manifold
 
  • #30
Ah, I see we are meant to think of this slightly differently than I was expecting. The definition doesn't care about completeness, but only whether causal curves are "inextendible" (i.e., that they do not have endpoints within the manifold). Under such definitions, the "Reissner-Nordstrom geometry minus the bad regions" (as I described above) is "globally hyperbolic". The point is the term is meant to capture the physically-sensible regions of a geometry, by asking what is the maximal globally hyperbolic Cauchy development of some initial data.

So I will agree I had the definition wrong. But I still feel that an incomplete spacetime is physically unhealthy in some way, as it means that there are some observers who can reach a region of "Here be dragons" in finite proper time. Perhaps that is simply the best that GR can say about such spacetimes, and an obvious indication that the theory cannot be fundamental (since it cannot answer physically reasonable questions about what happens to some observers).
 
  • #31
Ben Niehoff said:
I still feel that an incomplete spacetime is physically unhealthy in some way, as it means that there are some observers who can reach a region of "Here be dragons" in finite proper time.

I think that is the way most physicists look at it.

Ben Niehoff said:
Perhaps that is simply the best that GR can say about such spacetimes, and an obvious indication that the theory cannot be fundamental

Yes. The problem is that we don't (yet) have a more fundamental theory that covers the regime that GR does not.
 
  • #32
Ben Niehoff said:
But I still feel that an incomplete spacetime is physically unhealthy in some way, as it means that there are some observers who can reach a region of "Here be dragons" in finite proper time. Perhaps that is simply the best that GR can say about such spacetimes, and an obvious indication that the theory cannot be fundamental (since it cannot answer physically reasonable questions about what happens to some observers).

My personal view is that incompleteness as in the Schwartzschild solution is OK. The observer is torn apart by infinite curvature and ceases to exists, but everyone is accounted for. Incompleteness as in the Kerr solution, where the observer reaches the Cauchy horizon in finite proper time and there is no unique extension beyond it, is not OK. The theory loses its predictability. But this is where the strong cosmic censorship conjecture comes in. If true, these situations are non generic and therefore the theory is still as good as ever.
 
  • #33
martinbn said:
My personal view is that incompleteness as in the Schwartzschild solution is OK. The observer is torn apart by infinite curvature and ceases to exists, but everyone is accounted for. Incompleteness as in the Kerr solution, where the observer reaches the Cauchy horizon in finite proper time and there is no unique extension beyond it, is not OK. The theory loses its predictability. But this is where the strong cosmic censorship conjecture comes in. If true, these situations are non generic and therefore the theory is still as good as ever.
The cosmic censorship I'm familiar with only requires the BH be surrounded by a horizon. It doesn't say anything about the a-causality of the manifold inside the inner horizon. Does the strong version go further and say something like no singularity in the past light cone of any observer? This would require rejection of the inner horizon region due to CTCs. It also would reject the full Kruskal geometry.

[Ok, I looked this up, and I was only familiar with the weak censorship hypothesis. The strong would, indeed, say the interior of the Kerr Couchy horizon is a violation, and must be non-generic, if true. Does anyone know of much evidence or argument about the strong conjecture? Most discussion, e.g. Hawking's bets, revolve around the weak form, which already had to be modified to avoid a disproof of its simpler form.]
 
Last edited:
  • #34
PeterDonis said:
Yes. The problem is that we don't (yet) have a more fundamental theory that covers the regime that GR does not.

The way I understand cosmic censorship is that it is a research program that specifically tries not to appeal to a different theory. So it wouldn't merely be a statement that say quantum mechanics regulates the problems with the singularity, rather something about the mathematics behind the singularity structure in classical GR allows you to do that. So for instance the original definition of strong cosmic censorship was that you could only have spacelike singularities in physically reasonable theories with gravitational collapse (modulo some details that prevented simple counterexamples from being formulated)

I share Ben Niehoffs view that simply excising the singularity in the standard way done in textbooks counts as a rather *hard* regularization scheme, which perhaps misses some of the details that might help prove or disprove the conjecture. Perusing some of the work that's been done on the subject one can see that there have been multiple approaches and redefinitions and that there is no consensus on which direction to even take. So it stands more on simple physical arguments like the one's already given in the thread, and does not appear to have the correct mathematical formulation yet.
 

FAQ: The Schwarzschild Geometry: Part 4 - Comments

How does the Schwarzschild geometry relate to Albert Einstein's theory of general relativity?

The Schwarzschild geometry is a solution to the equations of Einstein's theory of general relativity. It describes the gravitational field around a spherically symmetric mass, such as a star or black hole.

Can you explain the concept of gravitational time dilation in the context of the Schwarzschild geometry?

In the Schwarzschild geometry, time is affected by the presence of a massive object. As an object gets closer to the massive body, time appears to slow down for an outside observer. This is known as gravitational time dilation and is a consequence of the curvature of spacetime caused by the massive object.

How does the Schwarzschild radius relate to the event horizon of a black hole?

The Schwarzschild radius is the distance from the center of a massive object at which the escape velocity is equal to the speed of light. This is also known as the event horizon of a black hole, as anything that crosses this radius cannot escape the gravitational pull of the black hole.

What is the significance of the singularity in the Schwarzschild geometry?

The singularity in the Schwarzschild geometry is a point of infinite density and zero volume. It is where the curvature of spacetime becomes infinite, and the laws of physics as we know them break down. This singularity is thought to exist at the center of a black hole.

How does the Schwarzschild geometry explain the phenomenon of gravitational lensing?

Gravitational lensing occurs when the path of light is bent by the curvature of spacetime caused by a massive object. In the Schwarzschild geometry, the curvature of spacetime is described by the Schwarzschild metric, which can be used to calculate the bending of light around a massive object. This phenomenon has been observed and confirmed by astronomers, providing evidence for the validity of the Schwarzschild geometry and general relativity.

Similar threads

Replies
39
Views
5K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
26
Views
5K
Replies
4
Views
944
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
4
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
17
Views
2K
Back
Top