Understanding Ordered Pairs to Notation and Definitions

  • Thread starter gnome
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Pair
In summary, the ordered pair <x,y> must be defined in such a way that it satisfies the property <x,y> = <u,v> iff x=u and y=v. The standard definition for this is <x,y> = {{x}, {x, y}}. This definition allows for distinguishing between the first and second elements in the pair and ensures that (x,y) is not equal to (y,x). It also accounts for the case when x=y. While this may seem counterintuitive, it satisfies the properties we expect from an ordered pair.
  • #36
Matt: yes that makes me feel happy. Dumb, but happy, thank you very much. Actually, you could have stopped at "we define set of ordered pairs of AxB to be" because that in itself made it all clear. You see, I was not reading it as the definition of a set; I was trying to read the definition of a general concept: "An ordered pair is ..." which of course made no sense, and I needed you to hit me over the head with those words to make me see what you meant.

Hurkyl: thank you too, but I know better than to ask that question. :rolleyes: Seriously, it would take more time than I can afford in order to really understand either of those answers. For the time being, I'll sleep very well with a 1-to-1 correspondence to the points on an infinite line.

mathwonk: you misunderstand my motivation in all this nonsense. This was not a debate. Until three days ago I was very satisfied with "an ordered pair is a pair of things, and one of them is designated as the first one" (and tomorrow I will again be satisfied with that). Unfortunately, I came across that {{a},{a,b}} definition in Enderton's "Mathematical Introduction to Logic" and foolishly thought that if it was important enough for him to put there, it was important enough for me to try to understand. Hurkyl and Matt were kind enough to waste their time helping me.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
Hurkyl: thank you too, but I know better than to ask that question. Seriously, it would take more time than I can afford in order to really understand either of those answers.
I only meant it as an analogy. :frown: I was trying to give a way for you to clarify what kind of answer you want, by analogy with this other case!


Unfortunately, I came across that {{a},{a,b}} definition in Enderton's "Mathematical Introduction to Logic" and foolishly thought that if it was important enough for him to put there, it was important enough for me to try to understand.
It is!

I think you're trying to get the wrong lesson from it, though: I suspect that (aside from completeness's sake) the point of this is that it's an example of the process of modelling a concept in some theory.



What happens in practice is that a budding mathematician is told "This is how we can define an ordered pair in the language of sets. Now let's just use the notation (a, b) and never speak of this again." (I think we've hinted at this, but I don't remember if we've said it explicitly)
 
Last edited:
  • #38
i know that gnome. I was answering your persistent questions about why people were answering your questions with questions, and generally having to be begged to stay on topic. it just isn't a topic that seems important after grasping it.
nonetheless, it was rude of me, and I apologize.

Like you, I encountered this definition in a book, and assumed it must have some importance since it was given there (Kelley's Continental classroom algebra book? in 1960?).

I remember thinking only slightly sceptically at the time, " so this is really the definition of an ordered pair? Do I need to know this?"

The answer is no, and I think the only reason this was included in the book, was that someone decided at the time of the set theory hysteria that's wept the math ed world in 1960, that it could be done, and showed off by doing it.

However I think Kelley may have honestly remarked there that it could be done that way if desired, implying that ti had limited significance.

I did however work the exercise that {{x}, {x,y}} = {{z},{z,w}} if and only if x=z and y = w.

assume for example that x = y. then the first set contains only {x}. thus the second set which equals it, must contain only one set too, so we must have z = w also. then since {{x}} = {{z}}, we must have x = z.

now suppose x is different from y...

interesting huh?...:zzz:
 
Last edited:
  • #39
I can't wait until you come across what a set theorist thinks the natural numbers really are. If you think the ordered pair stuff is unnecessarily fussy wait until you see this.
 
  • #40
yeah, i just reviewed a book on this stuff supposedly written for young math majors learning proofs. the definition of multiplication of integers in there was really off putting.

those guys must have been smoking crack. then the publishers advertised it by saying it was user friendly, and "written in a highly understandable style".

what a joke.
 
  • #41
mathwonk said:
an ordered pair is a pair of things, and one of them is designated as the first one.

The problem with that is that you need to define what "first one" means- in other words, to define "ordered pair" you'd better first define an order!

The definition: "An ordered pair, (a,b), is a set of the form {{a},{a,b}}" avoids that- it doesn't talk about "first" or "second", "left" or "right", "top" or "bottom". It asserts that there are two objects (a and b) and that
(a,b)= {{a},{a,b}} is different from (b,a)= {{b},{a,b}}. You are then free to assume whatever "order" you want. That's all that "ordered pairs" have to say.
 
  • #42
mathwonk said:
yeah, i just reviewed a book on this stuff supposedly written for young math majors learning proofs. the definition of multiplication of integers in there was really off putting.
those guys must have been smoking crack. then the publishers advertised it by saying it was user friendly, and "written in a highly understandable style".
what a joke.
Dont worry, the future is not doomed. Most of us with real interest tend to stay away from such trashy books and even have copies of books from those passed away 100 years gone!
 
  • #43
The problem with that is that you need to define what "first one" means- in other words, to define "ordered pair" you'd better first define an order!
Or, you could take the interpretation that "first" is merely a name for one of the elements, and has nothing to do with any notion of an ordering.
 
  • #44
gnome said:
Unfortunately, I came across that {{a},{a,b}} definition in Enderton's "Mathematical Introduction to Logic" and foolishly thought that if it was important enough for him to put there, it was important enough for me to try to understand. Hurkyl and Matt were kind enough to waste their time helping me.

The concept of translating ordinary mathematical statements into a formal language is relevant to mathematical logic. Enderton could have omitted that brief exercise but if a reader struggles to see how, in principal, the concept of an ordered pair can be expressed set theoretically, then the reader is probably going to struggle with things presented later in the book.

Set theorists & Mathematical Logicians don't study formal theories because they provide a justification or because knowledge of them is required for other branches of mathematics. They study formal theories because they find it interesting. Same reason why number theorists study integers. If you're not interested in formal theories, don't tie yourself up in knots about it -- just stick to subjects that you enjoy.
 
Last edited:
  • #45
I'm glad I was able to keep you all entertained these past few days. :approve:
matt grime said:
I can't wait until you come across what a set theorist thinks the natural numbers really are. If you think the ordered pair stuff is unnecessarily fussy wait until you see this.
You'll be the first to know. :wink:
CrankFan said:
They study formal theories because they find it interesting. Same reason why number theorists study integers. If you're not interested in formal theories, don't tie yourself up in knots about it -- just stick to subjects that you enjoy.
As I said, there's no danger that I'll be crowding the ranks of the set-theorists. On the other hand, I don't consider this to have been a waste of time.

For example, this is the first time I've come across this idea of construction of mathemetical objects. Seems like a surprisingly "empirical" activity for mathematicians to be involved in. Personally, I'd rather tinker around under the hood of my TR-7, but I can see how you could find that interesting. :-p

And, all kidding aside, I think the question of how to express the idea of ordering is fascinating. We all have this concept of order in our minds, but it takes so many forms depending on the particular subject to which it's being applied that it seems like a fairly daunting challenge for AI and one certainly worthy of attention.
 
  • #46
gnome said:
For example, this is the first time I've come across this idea of construction of mathemetical objects. Seems like a surprisingly "empirical" activity for mathematicians to be involved in.


It is not empirical at all. Think of it like this:

We take a theory of some type, written in some formal language, if you want to think of it like that. Then we make some formal statement about the objects that is not written in the original formal language. The question is if we can write this statement in that original formal language.

If you're interested in the Category theoretic viewpoint then it is occasionally useful to know when the construction we define is in 'the same universe' (which has a strict set theoretic meaning) as the things we first start from.


As a concrete example, consider the set of rational numbers, this is closed under finite sums of rational numbers (as in sums x_1+x_2+...+x_n a finite number of rationals added up). We can define a space of potentially infinite sums, whereby the infinite sums converge if and only if the sequence of finite partial sums is cauchy. This space cannot be the rational numbers, and is indeed the reals. Now suppose we ask the same question again whereby we allow for all infinite sums of reals whose partial sums are cauchy, do we get anything new? No, since the reals are complete.

Another example, that is easier to explain: consider the real numbers, and then ask if we can find all roots of all real coefficient polynomials in the reals. We can't but we can add in i and get the complex numbers. Is C then algebraically closed? Yes, it is.


Now, set theoretically, consider the class of all finite sets, is this closed under arbitrary unions? No, it is not, indeed there is a strict hierarchy, indexed by the cardinals, that indicate the sets one can make after taking different kinds of unions.
 
  • #47
Just kidding.

I do get your point, and I intend to read more about category theory but I'm juggling too many balls to get involved in that right now.

Another day. Thanks again.
 
  • #48
The set theoretic definition of a tuple uses the ordered pair as it's starting point. The result is that an n-tuple is an ordered set of n elements (or objects). -- Under this definition.

However, a tuple in database theory is usually defined as a finite function that maps fields in a relation(database table for instance) to data, and is not necessarily an ordered set of n elements. Another name for it is a "row" in a resultset or a row in a relation.
 
  • #49
halls, surely you jest.
 
Last edited:
  • #50
Aha! Halls you are right! Forgive me, but now I see for the first time, there really is no way to decide which element is "first"
.
For example when a = b, we have the proposed definition of the "ordered pair" (a,b) as the set {{a},{a,a}}. Now since {a} = {a,a}, this is just
{{a},{a}}, which of course is just {{a}}.
Thus there is no first copy of the element a.
Now this is clearly nonsense.
I.e. suppose we define an ordered singleton as a set of form {{a}}.
Then there is a non trivial intersection between the colection of ordered singletons and the collection of ordered pairs!
I.e. then when given the object {{a}}, we have no way of knowing whether it is an ordered singleton or an ordered pair.
This is obviously ridiculous and only someone who never planned to use them, would define them this way.
For instance with this definition, one could not tell the difference between the point (a,a) of the diagonal in the euclidean plane, and the point a on the real line.
So in fact the definition proposed for the ordered pair (a,b), namely {{a},{a,b}}, is a bit odd.
So unless I have made another of my many flagrant errors of thought (which is highly likely, given the huge number of intelligent people who have dutifully repeated this definition in their books), this silly definition is not only unimportant, but has odd properties.
e.g. in R^3, how should we define an ordered triple? perhaps we set (a,b,c) = the ordered pair (a,(b,c))? i.e. {{a},{{a},{b,c}}}.
Oho! We get the following: the "right" silly definition in this tradition, for an ordered singleton is of course not {{a}} but {a}.
then the ordered pair (a,a) is just {{a},{a,a}} = {{a}}.
and the ordered triple (a,a,a) is hmmm... {{a}, {{a}}}, so now R is disjoint from R^2, etc...
wheee... this kind of trivial nonsense is fun, until you wake up and realize you have more important things to do. It is kind of addictive though, like watching television. I fear it is equally harmful, as I am losing time I could be spending thinking about something deeper, like differential equations, or skew symmetric line bundles on curves. :-p
 
Last edited:
  • #51
I've always wondered about the existence of strange and unusual statements one might be able to prove through these standard models. For example:

3 = 1 U (0, 1)

Because:
0 = {}
1 = {0}
2 = {0, 1}
(0, 1) = {{0}, {0, 1}} = {1, 2}
3 = {0, 1, 2}
1 U (0, 1) = {0} U {1, 2} = {0, 1, 2} = 3


At one time, I satisfied myself that none of this is a worry, if you rigorously `type' things. (I.E. don't try to ask about the equality of things of different `types')
 
  • #52
mathwonk said:
Aha! Halls you are right! Forgive me, but now I see for the first time, there really is no way to decide which element is "first"
.
For example when a = b, we have the proposed definition of the "ordered pair" (a,b) as the set {{a},{a,a}}. Now since {a} = {a,a}, this is just
{{a},{a}}, which of course is just {{a}}.
Thus there is no first copy of the element a.
Now this is clearly nonsense.
I.e. suppose we define an ordered singleton as a set of form {{a}}.
Then there is a non trivial intersection between the colection of ordered singletons and the collection of ordered pairs!
I.e. then when given the object {{a}}, we have no way of knowing whether it is an ordered singleton or an ordered pair.
This is obviously ridiculous and only someone who never planned to use them, would define them this way.
For instance with this definition, one could not tell the difference between the point (a,a) of the diagonal in the euclidean plane, and the point a on the real line.

I think the definition works, and I do not think it is meaningful to infer backwards. I think <x,y> => {{x}, {x,y}}. That when x = y, we have a singleton means that since all parameters are equal the choice of first is ambigious or trivial. Because {{x},{x,y}} is a defintion and a convention its meaning can only be inferred by context (for example with knowledge of what space you are working on). {x} is drawn out first only to state which element is first in purely set theoretic terms in order to define some concept of order.
 
  • #53
note however the difference between this and the more usual definition of a set of ordered pairs as a map with domain {1,2}. then the ordered pair (a,b) is a function f with f(1) = a and f(2) = b, so there are two "copies" of a, one taken first and one taken second.
to say that when both elements of the pair are equal, one does not need to designate one as first is different from saying there are two elements, one first one second, and both are equal. that is all i ma saying: i n ever noticed thius distinction before, and it violates my sense of...
hey what am I doing! I am going on with this trivial topioc. also if you read the remainder of my previous post you will see i have already pointed out the answer to my own paradox.
notice that in most cases a math talk can never be too elementary, the more elementary it is the mroe people understand and the mroe they respond. similarly a thread can never be too trivial. the moreso, the mroe resposnes it generates,
perhaps if i ask why 1+1 = 2, we will have another deathless thread. :-p
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
3K
Replies
3
Views
1K
Replies
10
Views
10K
Replies
13
Views
2K
Back
Top