- #1
kered rettop
- 259
- 94
- TL;DR Summary
- Happy New Year to anyone asking it, but it's a bad question.
The "worlds" of MWI do not actually appear in the theory behind it. They are, so to speak, an interpretation of the interpretation. But what exactly are worlds?
The picture begins with an interaction. In general this results in an entanglement. If we decompose it into product terms, each of them develops, by further interactions, into a state which reflects one of the "possible" outcomes of the interaction. These separate (now generally accepted to be due to decoherence) into non-interacting worlds.
So the simple view would be that a world is a macroscopic state reflecting one possible outcome. Writers such as Vongehr refer to these as phenomenal worlds.
Which is fine in a controlled environment, but in nature there is no obvious basis for the decomposition, so the number of worlds is undefined.
You could even chose a basis that is the original state itself so that there is no superposition and you just have one phenomenal world.
This issue goes away if there is a preferred basis, or one set by the experimenter, of course.
Next issue: the previous was about worlds as phenomenal states - observable macroscopic states. But the states needn't be macroscopic. Each microstate, representing one particular set of outcomes for all the microscopic interactions, is derived from one or other of the original possibilities, so they can all be referred to as worlds. They are (presumably) all phenomenal to an embedded observer.
So now we can ask "when did the worlds separate?" The simple answer is that it doesn't take long for the worlds to separate "enough". But it's always possible to push back to the moment of interaction where the worlds don't yet exist. Each component of the original superposition is therefore a seed for either one of the relatively few macro-worlds or for a whole bundle of micro-worlds.
The above seems, to me, to render the question "how many worlds" specious.
The picture begins with an interaction. In general this results in an entanglement. If we decompose it into product terms, each of them develops, by further interactions, into a state which reflects one of the "possible" outcomes of the interaction. These separate (now generally accepted to be due to decoherence) into non-interacting worlds.
So the simple view would be that a world is a macroscopic state reflecting one possible outcome. Writers such as Vongehr refer to these as phenomenal worlds.
Which is fine in a controlled environment, but in nature there is no obvious basis for the decomposition, so the number of worlds is undefined.
You could even chose a basis that is the original state itself so that there is no superposition and you just have one phenomenal world.
This issue goes away if there is a preferred basis, or one set by the experimenter, of course.
Next issue: the previous was about worlds as phenomenal states - observable macroscopic states. But the states needn't be macroscopic. Each microstate, representing one particular set of outcomes for all the microscopic interactions, is derived from one or other of the original possibilities, so they can all be referred to as worlds. They are (presumably) all phenomenal to an embedded observer.
So now we can ask "when did the worlds separate?" The simple answer is that it doesn't take long for the worlds to separate "enough". But it's always possible to push back to the moment of interaction where the worlds don't yet exist. Each component of the original superposition is therefore a seed for either one of the relatively few macro-worlds or for a whole bundle of micro-worlds.
The above seems, to me, to render the question "how many worlds" specious.
Last edited: