Why Unitary Evolution? QM Justification Ideas

In summary, the conversation discusses the justifications for postulating fundamental unitary evolution in quantum mechanics, and the challenges in teaching non-relativistic QM. The "symmetry approach" is mentioned as a plausible heuristic for selecting unitary evolution, which involves the theory of Lie groups and Lie algebras. The conversation also touches on the historical approach to teaching QM and the use of the Schrödinger equation and canonical quantization.
  • #36
But "symmetry arguments" are usually considered "first principles reason". Of course, if you have a non-static background spacetime, time-translation symmetry is gone, i.e., at least this argument is no reason for unitarity.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
vanhees71 said:
But "symmetry arguments" are usually considered "first principles reason".
How do you know there isn't a time-translation invariant CPTP evolution?
 
  • #38
This I don't know, but by definition a symmetry is realized in QT as a unitary (or antiunitary) ray representation. Analyzing the Galilei or Poincare groups for Newtonian or special-relativistic dynamics leads to unitary representations for the time translations, and that's why the time evolution of the system is described by a unitary transformation. The assumption of a symmetry is pretty restrictive in this sense.
 
  • #39
vanhees71 said:
This I don't know, but by definition a symmetry is realized in QT as a unitary (or antiunitary) ray representation. Analyzing the Galilei or Poincare groups for Newtonian or special-relativistic dynamics leads to unitary representations for the time translations, and that's why the time evolution of the system is described by a unitary transformation. The assumption of a symmetry is pretty restrictive in this sense.
Let me give some context, because it's not really that I disagree in any way.

Quantum Information is now a common enough topic at universities, either as an upper undergraduate course itself, part of a quantum computing one or aspects of it are built into basic QM courses. As students become more familiar with its techniques they see CPTP maps and even CPTP evolutions more and more, so they could ask:
"Well why can't you represent time evolution with a CPTP evolution? Why does it have to be represented unitarily?"

My thinking is basically the same as yours. There are time-translation invariant CPTP evolutions, but they don't represent a symmetry. They won't preserve things like transition amplitudes. So this symmetry based argument you gave earlier is much better than the usual "probs should sum to one".
 
  • #40
I must admit that I'm pretty ignorant about this very interesting topic of quantum information, but of course CPTPs that are not induced by a unitary time evolution are common for open quantum systems, because the fundamental symmetries must only be realized by "closed systems", i.e., if you have a system composed of two parts (e.g., a particle and a heat bath coupled to each) and you consider the particle alone, i.e., "trace out the heat bath" the time evolution of the reduced density operator of the particle is a CPTP, but not a unitary time evolution in the particle Hilbert space alone. Only the total closed system, particle+heat bath, is described by a unitary time evolution.
 
  • Like
Likes LittleSchwinger
  • #41
vanhees71 said:
Only the total closed system, particle+heat bath, is described by a unitary time evolution.
Agreed, basically students are increasingly asking why can't the total closed system also be described with a CPTP evolution.
 
  • #42
vanhees71 said:
Time reflection symmetry has nothing to do with the unitary time evolution. In the parts of Nature (i.e., neglecting the weak interaction) it's an additional discrete symmetry, which must necessarily be represented as an anti-unitary transformation since the Hamiltonian must stay bounded from below under time-reversal. Although with the weak interaction the time evolution in Q(F)T is unitary.

The symmetry argument for unitarity of the time evolution is that time-translation invariance as a continuous symmetry must be realized as unitary transformation.
@vanhees71: nowhere in my post did I mention time reflection symmetry. A process can be time reversible (i.e. there exists a way to infer the past from the present) without being symmetric under time reversal.

Also, regarding (continuous) symmetry as a basis for unitarity, (i) there exist an abundance of non-unitary representations of non-compact Lie groups such as the Galilean and Poincaré groups, (ii) how do you know that those symmetries aren't an emergent property at macroscopic (i.e. N of order Avogadro's number) scales, (iii) there are plenty of systems that exhibit unitarity (or "near" unitarity, to within one part in a million say) where those symmetries are absent (e.g. small molecules.) Are you arguing that unitarity applies at a 'global' level (i.e. for a wave function describing the universe) on the basis of those symmetries, and that the unitarity of systems for which those symmetries are spontaneously broken is "induced" in a way from the unitarity of the universe?
 
Last edited:
  • #43
What is it they said in Blazing Saddles - I like to keep my audience riveted. Lovely thread.

For a textbook reference, see Ballentine, page 64 in my edition, but is likely in the first couple of pages of Chapter 3 in any edition. Here he evokes Wigner's Theorem, which has already been mentioned.

My contribution is for those that may not have heard of it before; here is the statement and proof (as mentioned originally due to Weinberg):
https://arxiv.org/abs/1810.10111

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Couchyam, vanhees71, gentzen and 1 other person
  • #44
bhobba said:
What is it they said in Blazing Saddles - I like to keep my audience riveted. Lovely thread.

For a textbook reference, see Ballentine, page 64 in my edition, but is likely in the first couple of pages of Chapter 3 in any edition. Here he evokes Wigner's Theorem, which has already been mentioned.

My contribution is for those that may not have heard of it before; here is the statement and proof (as mentioned originally due to Weinberg):
https://arxiv.org/pdf/1603.00353

Thanks
Bill
I don't know, where in this paper (no math!) is this important proof. The proof is of course due to Wigner and Bargmann. A very nice treatment is in the old edition in the QT textbook by Gottfried.
 
  • Informative
  • Like
Likes bhobba and LittleSchwinger
  • #45
bhobba said:
My contribution is for those that may not have heard of it before; here is the statement and proof (as mentioned originally due to Weinberg):
https://arxiv.org/pdf/1603.00353
I guess you wanted to post a different reference. This is the same reference you also posted at the same time in another thread, and is unrelated to unitary evolution.
 
  • Like
  • Haha
Likes bhobba, physika and vanhees71
  • #46
bhobba said:
For a textbook reference, see Ballentine, page 64 in my edition, but is likely in the first couple of pages of Chapter 3 in any edition. Here he evokes Wigner's Theorem, which has already been mentioned.
I only read Ballentine recently thanks to this forum. A really good text, wished I'd had it as an undergraduate. I loved the section on state tomography.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier, bhobba, gentzen and 1 other person
  • #47
gentzen said:
I guess you wanted to post a different reference. This is the same reference you also posted at the same time in another thread, and is unrelated to unitary evolution.
Whoops. Sorry guys - fixed now.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and LittleSchwinger
  • #48
LittleSchwinger said:
I only read Ballentine recently thanks to this forum. A really good text, wished I'd had it as an undergraduate. I loved the section on state tomography.
This book had a strong effect on me.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes LittleSchwinger
  • #49
bhobba said:
Whoops. Sorry guys - fixed now.

Thanks
Bill
Thanks for that. What a lovely paper. Given the above and your like of Ballentine, I think you might enjoy Talagrand's new book on QFT where he really digs deep into representations of the Poincaré group. He treats even massive Weyl Spinors.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and bhobba
  • #50
LittleSchwinger said:
Thanks for that. What a lovely paper. Given the above and your like of Ballentine, I think you might enjoy Talagrand's new book on QFT where he really digs deep into representations of the Poincaré group. He treats even massive Weyl Spinors.

Thanks for that. Just now got the book. Always on the lookout for QFT books for mathematicians because that is my background.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
  • Love
Likes vanhees71 and LittleSchwinger
  • #51
Got the e-book. Just skimming now. I love the remark: 'To top it all, I was buried by the worst advice I ever received, to learn the topic from Dirac’s book itself!'

It was the second serious book on QM I read and know the issue only too well. The first was Von Neumann's book which is excellent for mathematicians since it is just an extension of Hilbert-Space theory. I was confident when I went on to Dirac but became unstuck with that damnable Dirac Delta function. It led me on a sojourn in Rigged Hilbert Spaces that had nothing to do with physics. I came out the other end with the issues resolved - but at that stage of my QM journey, it was not a good move.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and LittleSchwinger
  • #52
But Dirac's book is excellent. What's the problem with it? Von Neumann is of course mathematically rigorous and Dirac is not.
 
  • Like
Likes physicsworks, LittleSchwinger and bhobba
  • #53
vanhees71 said:
But Dirac's book is excellent. What's the problem with it? Von Neumann is of course mathematically rigorous and Dirac is not.

It is excellent, physically better Von-Neumann. The only issue, which has been 'fixed' and is no longer of any relevance, is the diatribe Von Neumann writes about it at the beginning of his book. It is easy for a math graduate to read Von Neumann after studying Hilbert Spaces, but Dirac is more problematic. I personally believe every math degree should include distribution theory because of its wide use in applied math. As part of that, a few paragraphs like that found in Ballentine is all that is needed. I am going through Talagrand's book and it has a more complete explanation. If that was done first, then Dirac is fine. Perhaps include it in a modern preface to both books - just an idea.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and LittleSchwinger
  • #54
vanhees71 said:
Note that, despite for claims often to be read in textbooks, there's no need for parity or time-reversal symmetry for the detailed-balance relations to be valid.
Interesting, can you give a reference with more details?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #57
vanhees71 said:
But Dirac's book is excellent. What's the problem with it?
It has an explicit collapse postulate!
 
  • Haha
Likes Demystifier and vanhees71
  • #58
If that were a problem, you couldn't recommend very many otherwise excellent QT textbooks. Indeed, physics students also have to learn to "not listen to their words but looking at their deeds" (as Einstein adviced concerning all writings of theoretical physicists). That the collapse postulate is at best superfluous and at worst simply a contradiction to causality in the relativistic context should be obvious (though obviously it isn't for many philosophy-inclined physicists who still think that it's needed), but all this is off-topic here in the scientific part of the QT forum!
 
  • #59
vanhees71 said:
physics students also have to learn to "not listen to their words but looking at their deeds" (as Einstein adviced concerning all writings of theoretical physicists).
This also applies to reading your lecture notes and your contributions to PF.. The collapse - not necessarily the von Neumann form but in the general POVM related version - is used informally almost everywhere, namely whenever one argues how a state is prepared.
 
  • #60
For sure, it's not an instantaneous collapse affecting the physics at all points in space simultaneously. All our experiments are local, and nothing can violate the relativistic speed limit of signal propagation.
 
  • Like
Likes physicsworks
  • #61
A. Neumaier said:
It has an explicit collapse postulate!
It does not. And not because Dirac uses the word "principle" instead of "postulate", or the word "jump" instead of "collapse". But this is indeed off-topic.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #63
A. Neumaier said:
Again, this is off-topic, but: thank you, I actually have read Dirac, both the original and the first Russian edition edited by Fock. Nowhere in the book did he elevate the notion of throwing out a part of the probability distribution describing a physical system to a grand status of a physical principle (using Dirac's language when writing the book). Therefore, not even esteemed Peres could find (not that he would or should have) even a small section in Dirac's book with the words "jump" and "principle" in its title (Dirac never uses the word "collapse" in his book). However, you will find an entire chapter on "The Principle of the Superposition" and separate sections on "Heisenberg's Principle of Uncertainty" and "The Action Principle".
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #64
physicsworks said:
Again, this is off-topic, but: thank you, I actually have read Dirac, both the original and the first Russian edition edited by Fock. Nowhere in the book did he elevate the notion of throwing out a part of the probability distribution describing a physical system to a grand status of a physical principle (using Dirac's language when writing the book).
I have just now re-read the relevant section of Dirac's book (The Principles of Quantum Mechanics, 1982 ed). On p35 he writes:

Dirac said:
We now make some assumptions for the physical interpretation of the theory. If the dynamical system is in an eigenstate of a real dynamical variable ##\xi##, belonging to the eigenvalue ##\xi'##, then a measurement of ##\xi## will certainly give as result the number ##\xi'##. [...]
This is not exactly the usual collapse-like assumption, but Dirac goes on with: "some of the immediate consequences of the assumptions will be noted ..." (my emboldening). Among these "consequences of the assumptions" is the passage referenced by Peres and Terno, i.e., (p36):
Dirac said:
When we measure a real dynamical variable ##\xi##, the disturbance involved in the act of measurement causes a jump in the state of the dynamical system. 'From physical continuity, if we make a second measurement of the same dynamical variable ##\xi## immediately after the first, the result of the second measurement must be the same as
that of the first. Thus after the first measurement has been made, there is no indeterminacy in the result of the second. Hence, after the first measurement has been made, the system is in an eigenstate of the dynamical variable ##\xi##) the eigenvalue it belongs to being equal to the result of the first measurement. This conclusion must still hold if the second measurement is not actually made. In this way we see that a measurement always causes the system to jump into an eigenstate of the dynamical variable that is being measured, the eigenvalue this eigenstate belongs to being equal to the result of the measurement.
It's pretty clear that Dirac infers a jump in the state of system (what in modern times would normally be called "collapse") as an "immediate consequence" of his assumption. Sure, it's not in a section title, afaict, but so what?
 
  • Like
Likes A. Neumaier, vanhees71, Demystifier and 2 others
Back
Top