Insights Blog
-- Browse All Articles --
Physics Articles
Physics Tutorials
Physics Guides
Physics FAQ
Math Articles
Math Tutorials
Math Guides
Math FAQ
Education Articles
Education Guides
Bio/Chem Articles
Technology Guides
Computer Science Tutorials
Forums
Trending
Featured Threads
Log in
Register
What's new
Search
Search
Google search
: add "Physics Forums" to query
Search titles only
By:
Latest activity
Register
Menu
Log in
Register
Navigation
More options
Contact us
Close Menu
JavaScript is disabled. For a better experience, please enable JavaScript in your browser before proceeding.
You are using an out of date browser. It may not display this or other websites correctly.
You should upgrade or use an
alternative browser
.
Forums
inconsistent
Recent contents
View information
Top users
Description
In classical, deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory
T
{\displaystyle T}
is consistent if there is no formula
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi }
such that both
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi }
and its negation
¬
φ
{\displaystyle \lnot \varphi }
are elements of the set of consequences of
T
{\displaystyle T}
. Let
A
{\displaystyle A}
be a set of closed sentences (informally "axioms") and
⟨
A
⟩
{\displaystyle \langle A\rangle }
the set of closed sentences provable from
A
{\displaystyle A}
under some (specified, possibly implicitly) formal deductive system. The set of axioms
A
{\displaystyle A}
is consistent when there is no formula
φ
{\displaystyle \varphi }
such that
φ
∈
⟨
A
⟩
{\displaystyle \varphi \in \langle A\rangle }
and
¬
φ
∈
⟨
A
⟩
{\displaystyle \lnot \varphi \in \langle A\rangle }
. A trivial theory (i.e., one which proves every sentence in the language of the theory) is clearly inconsistent. Conversely, in an explosive formal system (e.g., classical or intuitionistic propositional or first-order logics) every inconsistent theory is trivial.: 7 Consistency of a theory is a syntactic notion, whose semantic counterpart is satisfiability. A theory is satisfiable if it has a model, i.e., there exists an interpretation under which all axioms in the theory are true. This is what consistent meant in traditional Aristotelian logic, although in contemporary mathematical logic the term satisfiable is used instead.
In a sound formal system, every satisfiable theory is consistent, but the converse does not hold. If there exists a deductive system for which these semantic and syntactic definitions are equivalent for any theory formulated in a particular deductive logic, the logic is called complete. The completeness of the propositional calculus was proved by Paul Bernays in 1918 and Emil Post in 1921, while the completeness of (first order) predicate calculus was proved by Kurt Gödel in 1930, and consistency proofs for arithmetics restricted with respect to the induction axiom schema were proved by Ackermann (1924), von Neumann (1927) and Herbrand (1931). Stronger logics, such as second-order logic, are not complete.
A consistency proof is a mathematical proof that a particular theory is consistent. The early development of mathematical proof theory was driven by the desire to provide finitary consistency proofs for all of mathematics as part of Hilbert's program. Hilbert's program was strongly impacted by the incompleteness theorems, which showed that sufficiently strong proof theories cannot prove their consistency (provided that they are consistent).
Although consistency can be proved using model theory, it is often done in a purely syntactical way, without any need to reference some model of the logic. The cut-elimination (or equivalently the normalization of the underlying calculus if there is one) implies the consistency of the calculus: since there is no cut-free proof of falsity, there is no contradiction in general.
View More On Wikipedia.org
Forums
Back
Top