- #36
JeffJo
- 143
- 25
Since I missed out on the previous "debate," I'll point out some things that are appropriate to both that one and this one.
Here is an outline of Cantor's Diagonal Argument (CDA), as published by Cantor. I'll apply it to an undefined set that I will call T (consistent with the notation in Wikipedia). One important property of the elements t of T, is that each is a surjection from the natural numbers N to some set of characters C.
Part B, as I would word it:
Note: What Cantor actually wrote is closer to "If s1, s2, …, sn, … is any simply infinite series of elements of T, then there always exists an element s0 of T, which cannot be connected with any element sn."
+++++
The problem Warp has with CDA, as it is usually taught, is that it is indeed logically invalid. I'm not saying the conclusion is wrong, just that the one-part CDA that is usually taught is invalid.
Here is an outline of Cantor's Diagonal Argument (CDA), as published by Cantor. I'll apply it to an undefined set that I will call T (consistent with the notation in Wikipedia). One important property of the elements t of T, is that each is a surjection from the natural numbers N to some set of characters C.
- Cantor used the set of two characters C={'m','w'}
- Wikipedia used the set of two characters C={'0','1'}
- When taught to teenagers, it is usually the decimal representation of real numbers, so it uses C={'0','1','2','3','4','5','6','7','8','9'}. With some additional steps.
- Let S be any subset of T, proper or improper, that is countable.
- So a bijection b(n): N ->S exists.
- Construct a new function s0:N->C such that that s0(n) is not equal to b(n)(n).
- Prove that s0 is in T, but not in S.
- QED.
From Part A, it follows immediately that T is uncountable. Otherwise we would have the contradiction, that an object s0 would be both an element of T, but also not an element of T.
Part B, as I would word it:
The contrapositive of the proposition is Part A is "For any subset S of T, if S is not a proper subset of T, then S is not countable.
This is applicable here, because the new proposition Warp is trying to prove doesn't fit step A4. The elements of his set T always degenerate to a repeating sequence (i.e., are rational numbers). To apply CDA, he has to prove that his s0 also degenerates like that, so it is in T, and also is not in the set S.Note: What Cantor actually wrote is closer to "If s1, s2, …, sn, … is any simply infinite series of elements of T, then there always exists an element s0 of T, which cannot be connected with any element sn."
+++++
The problem Warp has with CDA, as it is usually taught, is that it is indeed logically invalid. I'm not saying the conclusion is wrong, just that the one-part CDA that is usually taught is invalid.
To apply proof by contradiction, one must use everything in the assumption to establish the contradiction. If I assume that the moon in made of individually wrapped packets of green and bleu cheeses, in a ratio that equals the square root of two, I can derive the contradiction that an even number must be equal to an odd number. But I only use the assumption about the ratio, not the kinds of cheeses that comprise the moon. So all I prove is that the square root of two is irrational.
Similarly, as CDA is usually taught, only the assumption "there is a list" is used to derive the alleged contradiction. Never the assumption that this list is complete. What Part A proves, directly, is negation of the unused part. Which is why proof-by-contraposition is logically more valid than proof-by-contradiction. This is actually an age-old criticism of proof-by-contradition.