Assumptions of the Bell theorem

In summary: In fact, the whole point of doing so is to get rid of the probabilistic aspects.The aim of this thread is to make a list of all these additional assumptions that are necessary to prove the Bell theorem. An additional aim is to make the list of assumptions that are used in some but not all versions of the theorem, so are not really necessary.The list of necessary and unnecessary assumptions is preliminary, so I invite others to supplement and correct the list.
  • #421
PeterDonis said:
This claim is also interpretation dependent. See my previous post.
I thought we have decided on the scientific part of the theory, according to which the Born rule is one of the postulates.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #422
vanhees71 said:
I thought we have decided on the scientific part of the theory, according to which there is no collapse.
The 7 Basic Rules do not say "there is no collapse". They make no claim either way about whether collapse is a real physical process or not. They just tell how to use the projection postulate under the appropriate circumstances to calculate predictions.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #423
vanhees71 said:
the Born rule is one of the postulates.
The Born Rule is one of the 7 Basic Rules, but, as in my previous post, those rules make no claim about what is "fundamental". They just tell you how to calculate predictions. The Born Rule is one of the rules to be applied when doing that.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #424
Indeed, I'm uneasy about the projection postulate too, but that's the only point of the agreement, I'm a bit worried about since in my opinion the state of the system after a measurement cannot be postulated but depends on the specific measurement done on the system. Von Neumann filter measurements are pretty rare and feasible only for very simple systems. The Born postulate says less, and it's part of our "7 Basic Rules". It just tells you the probabilities when accurately measuring an observable when the (pure or mixed) state the system is prepared in is known.
 
  • #425
PeterDonis said:
The Born Rule is one of the 7 Basic Rules, but, as in my previous post, those rules make no claim about what is "fundamental". They just tell you how to calculate predictions. The Born Rule is one of the rules to be applied when doing that.
I don't know, what's fundamental, if not the "basic rules".
 
  • #426
vanhees71 said:
Von Neumann filter measurements are pretty rare and feasible only for very simple systems. The Born postulate says less, and it's part of our "7 Basic Rules". It just tells you the probabilities when accurately measuring an observable when the (pure or mixed) state the system is prepared in is known.
Yes, that's intentional. There is not general agreement about how to handle more general or more complicated cases, so they aren't included in the 7 Basic Rules, which are only intended to capture the minimal set of things on which there is general agreement.

vanhees71 said:
don't know, what's fundamental, if not the "basic rules".
"Fundamental" implies a claim about "how things really are". Our 7 Basic Rules make no such claim.
 
  • #427
vanhees71 said:
the state of the system after a measurement cannot be postulated but depends on the specific measurement done on the system
Do you mean in general you'd need to update using Kraus operators:
##\rho \rightarrow \rho^{'} = \frac{K_{i}\rho K^{\dagger}_{i}}{Tr(K_{i}\rho K^{\dagger}_{i})}## with ##\sum_{i}K_{i} K^{\dagger}_{i} = \mathbb{I}##
or did you mean something else?
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #428
No, we are just in the next debate about, what I am allowed to say though we are in the interpretations subsection of the quantum physics forum. Now we are again fighting about semantics, i.e., what I am allowed to call fundamental and what not.

My point of view is that one cannot generally say, in which state the system is after a measurement, because it depends on the specific apparatus used to measure, and of course the theory of measurement has evolved much further in the recent years, including the use of projection operator valued measurement formalisms etc. In your language, the Kraus operators are determined not by some postulate but by the apparatus used to do the measurement.
 
  • Like
Likes Kolmo
  • #429
vanhees71 said:
In your language, the Kraus operators are determined not by some postulate but by the apparatus used to do the measurement.
Indeed fully agree, it often requires a form of tomography to find the Kraus operators of the device and they cannot just be postulated. Indeed it is now a subfield of quantum information to find optimal operational algorithms to determine the Kraus operators in various settings.
Just checking I understood your meaning, thanks.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #430
vanhees71 said:
Now we are again fighting about semantics, i.e., what I am allowed to call fundamental and what not.
You are allowed to say it is your opinion that something is fundamental, or that collapse is not a real physical process. You are not allowed to state those things as facts. They are your opinions. The guidelines for this forum (the interpretations forum) make that clear.

vanhees71 said:
My point of view is...
All of this is fine from the standpoint of the guidelines for this forum.
 
  • #431
I'm glad to hear that. I've the impression for discussing in the Quantum Forum you need to have more and more the abilities of a lawyer rather than a physicist :eek:.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and WernerQH
  • #432
vanhees71 said:
I don't know, what's fundamental, if not the "basic rules".
Fundamental are those basic rules that cannot be violated even in principle. For instance, energy conservation and entropy increase are both basic rules, but, as far as we know, only the former is fundamental.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #433
From my perspective I think of "fundamental" elements of a theory, are those that we exclude from requiring further motivation. Ie. the have axiomatic status and taken as unquestionable and not subject to beeing inferrable or "observable".

Things that can be verified by inferences within the theory, or from experiment as true or false, using the methods of the theory, are IMO then not "fundamental", they are inferences to which we assign degrees of belief.

But in the context of evolving theories, and lossy compression, it seems a plausible idea still that an evolving agent, can at some point, as part of lossy compression, "approximate" a confident historical inference, with an axiom.

This is why I think what is fundamental is also interpretation or theory dependent. I personally thing, it's not necessarily critial to assess what is fundamental and what is not, just as its' not important to assess what is true or false, if you have a framework where one can make evolutionary transformations between fundamental and non-fundamental things, as a form of recoding. So if we can observe someting, that ALWAYS holds, it is an inference, but instead of that and agent is to waste resources to maintain a confident opinion, it can instead may an internal remapping, to make a lossy compression it to an axiom, and this resource planning may be economical for the agent, and possibly be well motivated in such a model. We know from biology that evolution has a lot to do not only only with survival, but also about "economy" such as "regulatory economy" and other things. Because using resourcs at hand optimally, is a survival trait indirectly - this is what they information theoretic perspective to QM is IMO highly relevant! But it has many components.

It's how I think, but I am sure others with a more ontological theory on mind, finds this obscure. But even so, I do think they they need to contradict each other.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #434
I think it's a bit misleading to talk about "axioms". I'd rather call them "postulates". Physics is not a mathematical theory but an empirical science. I'd say the "fundamental laws" or "postulates" are those parts of a physical theory which we consider to be right by experience, i.e., all observations as far as we know are in accordance with them, and which cannot be derived within the theory from other laws.
Demystifier said:
Fundamental are those basic rules that cannot be violated even in principle. For instance, energy conservation and entropy increase are both basic rules, but, as far as we know, only the former is fundamental.
Well, in this strict sense neither is fundamental. Entropy increase is a statistical law, i.e., it holds true up to statistical fluctuations. Energy conservation holds only locally (within General relativity).

I think, what's considered as "fundamental" is (a) dependent on the theoretical context and (b) also sometimes a matter of opinion. Concerning (a): E.g., energy conservation is a fundamental law in Newtonian and special relativistic physics and follows from time-translation invariance of the underlying spacetime model(s). Whether you consider energy conservation or the symmetry as the fundamental law is a matter of taste. I'd say it's energy conservation, because it is the physics content and can (at least in principle) be confirmed or falsified by observation.

Concerning QT I'd say our "7 rules" are the fundamental laws except the projection postulate (as you see that's again an example, where it's also a matter of opinion, what you call fundamental), because the projection postulate is true in very rare special cases of ideal filter measurements, which are rather an exception than standard in our labs. That's not in contradiction with my opinion that the Born rule is a fundamental law within QT. Without it the entire formalism wouldn't have physical meaning, because the Born rule connects the abstract description of the quantum state to observable facts in terms of a probability for the outcome of (accurate) measurements. You can do a measurement, and almost always does, without preparing the measured system in an corresponding eigenstate dependent on the state the system was prepared in before the measurement: E.g., if a photon detector makes "click" it says that at its position there was a photon at the time it made "click". Afterwards the photon is not in a corresponding eigenstate of its position, because (a) it's simply absorbed by the apparatus and not there anymore as an "object" separated from the measurement apparatus and (b) a photon doesn't have a position observable to begin with, so that there cannot be position eigenstates either.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, gentzen and Kolmo
  • #435
vanhees71 said:
I think it's a bit misleading to talk about "axioms". I'd rather call them "postulates". Physics is not a mathematical theory but an empirical science. I'd say the "fundamental laws" or "postulates" are those parts of a physical theory which we consider to be right by experience, i.e., all observations as far as we know are in accordance with them, and which cannot be derived within the theory from other laws.
I am fine with either term and I agree with this paragraph for the purpose here.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #436
vanhees71 said:
Without it the entire formalism wouldn't have physical meaning, because the Born rule connects the abstract description of the quantum state to observable facts in terms of a probability for the outcome of (accurate) measurements.
I understand that. But I don't see how to reconcile it with your other claims, namely:
(i) Measurement can only be understood in open systems.
(ii) Born rule is valid also in closed systems.
If Born rule makes sense only for measurements (the quote above) and if measurement requires an open system, then Born rule makes sense only for open systems, which contradicts (ii). Don't you see a logical contradiction and a need to revise at least one of the claims above?
 
  • #437
There is no contradiction. You just haven't read my statement carefully enough.

I said the apparent "measurement problem" can be solved only considering open systems, making use of the fact that a measurement device must be macroscopic to produce an irreversibly stored measurement result. You don't need to solve this apparent problem to use quantum theory with its probabilistic meaning of the state to calculate the probabilities. As a theorist you don't need to bother about the measurement device constructed by the experimentalists, except you want to solve that apparent problem some philosophers still have with quantum theory. The probabilities you calculate with Born's rule are simply measured with devices constructed by experimentalists to measure the observables they want to measure on an ensemble of equally prepared systems and then do the statistics to compare the frequencies of the different outcomes with the predictted probabilities and estimate the statistical significance etc etc.

Also in classical physics I do not need to understand, e.g., the very complicated details of a digital volt meter measuring some voltage across a resistor in some circuit in order to compare it to the value predicted by standard circuit theory. I just have to trust the manufacturer that he had built a device that measures the voltage.
 
  • #438
Demystifier said:
Fundamental are those basic rules that cannot be violated even in principle.
This is how I think of this. For me it helps to think of two forms of probabilities, these two versions are also what I take to illustrated the difference between correlation and causation in agent view. The first type is just correlation, the second type is what is "causes" actions. The feedback loop between the two would be more complex though.

1) Correlations - or distributional patterns in the agents or physicists raw observations.

For example the final results from many many trials in particle experiments, where you get an observed "probability" corresponding to the whole ensemble (never individual events). Without an explicit history of measurment records, this "probability" can not be established. This is what one measures in a real experiments. Inferring observed distributions, does not require born rule. In an abstract agent one could envision and event counter, and automatically builds up a frequentist distribution. It requires not "inferences", just observation and counting distinguishable events.

2) Expectations of the agent - that influences the agents instant action.

This is not based on measurements, and this is where the QM inferemnce comes in. It's based on the agents internal inference (expectation) of the future trial, based on it's own encoded (possibly lossy) information. (Or the "initial state" or "preparation") This kind of "probability" would ideally influence the choices made by the agent, in case it was interacting more than a normal "measurement device does". This is that requires the use of the born rule. As it the prescribed rule for constructing the p-value from the abstract reprensentation of the information (quantum state). Thus I imagine this born rule to be value also for closed systems (ie given that we take quantum theory for what it is), because it describes how the agents "aligns" even in between measurements.

Other than this, we expect that if the theory is GOOD, then the two probabilities (ie it's numbers) will agree!
Ie. the theories "expectated" probabiltiy, should match the observed one.

=> For this we need real measurements (and thus "open" up the system), yet the born rule does make sense for closed systems as it prescribes the inference on the agent side - not on the quantum side.

But I think it's helpful, to understand this, if one sees that they are really different, and don't HAVE to agree. Because the physical process of inference from current state, and the observational recordes are two different ones). It's when they do not agree, that we have the input for a learning loop? So I don't think one should think that a theory whose expectations fails to be equal to the actual future, is useless or wrong. I think there is a value to see how it is instead part of the game, and the theory is alive.

What makes the above indeed possible seems like hopeless soup, is that we do not yet know how, observational history "forges" the agents internal states, that implies the expectations. Ie how the "internal state" revision works. It's clearly not a simlpy bayesian update, as several non-commuting observables must be combinied into ONE state, and ontop of this makes this with the capacity the agent has at hand. But this is exactly what i personally take to be one of the key quests for the foundations. Smolin talked about "principle of precedence" which is just indicative of the idea, but I find this to be a largely crazy and immature field, but still extremely interesting and impossible to get off your mind.

/Fredrik
 
  • #439
vanhees71 said:
I said the apparent "measurement problem" can be solved only considering open systems, making use of the fact that a measurement device must be macroscopic to produce an irreversibly stored measurement result.
Perhaps a part of our mutual misunderstanding is that we don't mean the same by the "measurement problem". How would you say concisely what the apparent "measurement problem" is? I'm not asking for the solution, just briefly state the problem!

vanhees71 said:
Also in classical physics I do not need to understand, e.g., the very complicated details of a digital volt meter measuring some voltage across a resistor in some circuit in order to compare it to the value predicted by standard circuit theory. I just have to trust the manufacturer that he had built a device that measures the voltage.
In comparison of classical and quantum measurements, my problem is this. The general principles of classical theoretical physics can be formulated without even mentioning measurement, while those of quantum physics cannot. The culprit is the Born rule. For instance, if I say that the probability is ##p={\rm Tr}\rho\pi##, the projector ##\pi## is defined by the measurement. I don't see how to specify ##\pi## without specifying measurement (except in the consistent histories interpretation).

So I will ask you again, in your opinion, is the Born rule valid in the absence of measurement? More specifically, if we have one spin-1/2 particle isolated from the environment, does it make sense to speak of probability of its spin in the z-direction?
 
  • Like
Likes romsofia and dextercioby
  • #440
Demystifier said:
In comparison of classical and quantum measurements, my problem is this. The general principles of classical theoretical physics can be formulated without even mentioning measurement
This doesn't change too much of what you are saying but I'd say more it's can't be formulated without effectively Boolean systems.

If we have a state ##\rho## then the most general time evolution is a quantum operation or CPTP map and all such maps are sums of Kraus operators:
##\rho \rightarrow \mathcal{T}(\rho) = \sum_{k} E_{k}\rho E^{\dagger}_{k}##
which was funnily first proven for unknown reasons by Stinespring while working in the navy1.

However when interacting with DOFs described by a Boolean algebra (sometimes called "classical" but this terminology is a bit ambiguous) then it is proven that all interactions with a Boolean system induce an evolution of the Kraus sum type above. This was most fully proven in papers by VP Belavkin, but a readable version is in Greg Kuperberg's old notes (https://www.math.ucdavis.edu/~greg/intro-2005.pdf).

The only question then is can one derive these effectively Boolean systems from within quantum theory itself.

This is closely related to conditionalization. For if a sequence of measurements ##E_{i}## is done for defining the conditional:

$$P(E_{i}|E_{1}\ldots E_{i-1}E_{i+1}\ldots E_{n}) = \frac{Tr(E_{1}\ldots E_{n}\rho)}{\sum_{k}Tr(E_{1}\ldots E^{k}_{i}\ldots E_{n}\rho)}$$

Where the ##k## sum is over some POVM containing ##E_i##. The ambiguity of which POVM prevents a definition of conditional probability, thus only with a Boolean system which has no basis ambiguity can such conditional probabilities be defined (more explanation here: https://arxiv.org/abs/1310.1484).

1 W. Forrest Stinespring, Positive functions on C ∗ - algebras, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 6 (1955), 211–216
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #441
Demystifier said:
Perhaps a part of our mutual misunderstanding is that we don't mean the same by the "measurement problem". How would you say concisely what the apparent "measurement problem" is? I'm not asking for the solution, just briefly state the problem!
The measurement problem is the question, how it comes that an ideal measurement device leads to well-defined single outcomes while the quantum state only provides probabilities for this outcome.

For me the answer is obvious: Because the measurement device is constructed to do so.

Together with the projection postulate, which I don't consider a fundamental postulate but the description of a very special case of preparation procedures, which I'd always call "von Neumann filter measurement" to be clear, it's often considered a problem that there should be a dynamical description of the transition from the state ##|\psi \rangle \langle \psi|## with ##|\psi \rangle=\sum_n \psi_n |u_n \rangle## to ##|u_{n_0} \rangle \langle u_{n_0}## when a (here for simplicity considered non-degenerate) observable is measured and the outcome is the eigenvalue of the ##n_0##-th eigenstate.

The answer to this, in my opinion, is that a projection can of course not be described by a unitary time evolution, and indeed a filter meausurement (or rather a filter preparation) needs a "filter" and thus you have to use the description in terms of an open quantum system to understand the said transition.
 
  • Like
Likes Kolmo
  • #442
Demystifier said:
In comparison of classical and quantum measurements, my problem is this. The general principles of classical theoretical physics can be formulated without even mentioning measurement, while those of quantum physics cannot. The culprit is the Born rule. For instance, if I say that the probability is ##p={\rm Tr}\rho\pi##, the projector ##\pi## is defined by the measurement. I don't see how to specify ##\pi## without specifying measurement (except in the consistent histories interpretation).

So I will ask you again, in your opinion, is the Born rule valid in the absence of measurement? More specifically, if we have one spin-1/2 particle isolated from the environment, does it make sense to speak of probability of its spin in the z-direction?
All of theoretical physics makes only sense with operationally defined observables, i.e., implicitly we always use "measurement protocols" do define even classical observables like position, momentum, etc. In other words theoretical physics is a mathematical description of observables, defined by "measurement protocols". Otherwise you would merely have some axiomatic system in the sense of math without any relation to what's observed in nature. It seems only much more familiar given our everyday experience to deal with classical physics than with quantum physics.

I don't know, what you mean by the validity of Born's rule "in absence of measurement". Born's rule is about the probabilities for the outcome of (precise) measurements of an observable. So I can't make sense of Born's rule "in absence of measurement".

So if an electron is prepared in a spin state ##|\psi \rangle \langle \psi## with ##\psi=|\hat{z},+1/2 \rangle## the probabilities given by Born's rule to measure the spin component in some direction ##\hat{n}##, ##P(\hat{n},\sigma)=|\langle \hat{n},\sigma|\psi \rangle|^2## are the probabilities to find the value ##\sigma \in \{-1/2,1/2\}## when accurately measuring the spin component in ##\hat{n}## direction.

For me, there's no other meaning in the quantum formalism than providing such probabilities for the outcome of measurements.
 
  • Like
Likes Kolmo
  • #443
vanhees71 said:
For me the answer is obvious: Because the measurement device is constructed to do so.
This is why I think it is worth reading the 1962 Daneri et al paper"Quantum theory of measurement and ergodicity conditions" where it is shown that a macroscopic body of the right constituency gives rise to irreversible storage. The most detailed modern treatment by Allahverdyan et al. is just further detail upon this, but various thermodynamic processes give rise to superselection1 for the measurement result.

1 This isn't to say a macroscopic body cannot display quantum effects when probed in enough detail. Also note "superselection" in modern measurement theory has a broader definition than found in older texts.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and vanhees71
  • #444
vanhees71 said:
For me, there's no other meaning in the quantum formalism than providing such probabilities for the outcome of measurements.
For me, Q(F)T is a machinery for calculating correlation functions. This is most easily done for "closed" systems, but of course only for open systems is there a point of contact with the real world.

The "measurement problem" is not about measurements, but what it is that is "correlated". It is certainly a rather misleading idea that an electron always has a definite direction of spin.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #445
WernerQH said:
The "measurement problem" is not about measurements, but what it is that is "correlated"
Measurement results is the usual answer, at least in areas I work in.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #446
Kolmo said:
Measurement results is the usual answer, at least in areas I work in.
But physicists can't agree on what constitutes a "measurement".
 
  • Like
  • Haha
Likes Lord Jestocost and vanhees71
  • #447
Physicists know very well what constitutes a measurement. It's only too philosophy inclined theoreticians that don't agree ;-). SCNR.
 
  • #448
WernerQH said:
But physicists can't agree on what constitutes a "measurement".
I've never really seen this in actual research honestly. A measurement is usually defined as a thermodynamically irreversible process leading to a stored result, normally due to the aggregate properties of a macroscopic body.
I know people have problems with this definition, but I don't see it very often in practice. Probably because the arguments are formally equivalent to arguing about does water really boil in Stat Mech because you only get sharp phase transitions in the infinite volume limit. Most wouldn't be interested in the "boiling water problem" either.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and dextercioby
  • #449
vanhees71 said:
I don't know, what you mean by the validity of Born's rule "in absence of measurement". Born's rule is about the probabilities for the outcome of (precise) measurements of an observable. So I can't make sense of Born's rule "in absence of measurement".
...
For me, there's no other meaning in the quantum formalism than providing such probabilities for the outcome of measurements.
This is where I know we have different views. And I also find your position somehow incomplete, but perhaps(?) for a different reason than Demystifier, I can not tell for sure.

As I see it, the born rule defines the agents expectations of a "potential" future measurement. And if you (like me) are into the agent picture, this reflects the actual state of the agent, even WITHOUT measurments.

I am sure this would have observable consequences in terms of causality, as the agents actions are tuned as per the born rule, BEFORE the measurement takes place, and BEFORE the information update.

But I see our perspective too, as the agent view is a specific interpretation, mixed up with idea of howto modiy QM, so i agree it does not belong to the minimal QM. But this is why the minimal itnerpretation seems to be as "fine" in a FAPP sense, yet conceptually incomplete. This is why i find the minimal theory deeply insatisfactory.

Mvh
/Fredrik
 
  • #450
vanhees71 said:
Physicists know very well what constitutes a measurement. It's only too philosophy inclined theoreticians that don't agree ;-). SCNR.
Of course we have intuitive and stereotyped ideas about measurement ("Stern Gerlach apparatus"). But as the discussions here amply demonstrate, different people's ideas on this topic do not harmonize. Axiomatization of QM was fueled by the hope of making a vague term like "measurement" precise by embedding it in a rigid set of axioms. But is it really useful to introduce such a term as an irreducible primitive concept of a microscopic theory? John Bell railed against this.

A neutral hydrogen atom in interstellar space is the best example of a closed quantum system. Do we really need to introduce a radio astronomer and his dish to discuss the 21 cm radiation?
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #451
WernerQH said:
A neutral hydrogen atom in interstellar space is the best example of a closed quantum system. Do we really need to introduce a radio astronomer and his dish to discuss the 21 cm radiation?
I think this is more to do with the debate revolving around frozen terminology that has never been updated.

Really we have "events", that is thermodynamically irreversible processes resulting in some stored imprint/record/etc. A hydrogen atom can leave such an thermodynamically irreversible imprint in a rock on the Earth's surface for example or some bubble track in the upper atmosphere.

Quantum Theory assigns probabilities to such events, it doesn't necessarily have to be a human's equipment.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #452
Kolmo said:
Quantum Theory assigns probabilities to such events, it doesn't necessarily have to be a human's equipment.
I agree. But the discussion should not be restricted to "thermodynamically irreversible" events. Also the emission of a 21 cm photon is an event that QM should be able to describe without introducing "frozen terminology".
 
  • #453
WernerQH said:
But the discussion should not be restricted to "thermodynamically irreversible" events
I'm not sure what discussion is being restricted, but it just seems that's what QM predictions concern, the probability of the occurrence of these thermodynamically irreversible events.

WernerQH said:
Also the emission of a 21 cm photon is an event that QM should be able to describe without introducing "frozen terminology"
But my point was that it can, rather than measurements it's about the types of events discussed above. You don't need to introduce measurement as a primitive, it's just that the most typical events we deal with scientifically are measurements involving our equipment.

Or if you want a simpler way of putting it rocks can do a measurement as well.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Fra
  • #454
WernerQH said:
I agree. But the discussion should not be restricted to "thermodynamically irreversible" events.
I think the irreversible concept with "classical imprints" is equivalent to constraining things to classical macroscopic agents making the inference. IMO this is a limtation in quantum theory itself. So interpretations will not help.

I agree we should move further (in order to get an intrinsic theory of inference), but it would imlpy a modification, where the objectivity that is manifest in the irreversible macroscopic imprints, must be replaced by an evolving reference without exact agent equivalence. This is what I think is difficult.

/Fredrik
 
  • #455
The sense which Bohr and Heisenberg views are consistent is that while Heisenberg insists on the cut, making the measurement subjective to the observer. The independence Bohr insisted on is recovered thanks to the fact that one is considering only "classical agents", thus the equivlence class of agents is constructed manifested via classical communication, we only need to care about relativity of course.

That possibility goes away if we consider a class of non-classical agents (meaning the measurements are NOT objective publicaly avaiable imprints for any observer to read). Instead measurments results seem to haveto be "hidden variables" of the agent?

/Fredrik
 

Similar threads

Replies
333
Views
14K
Replies
6
Views
2K
Replies
226
Views
20K
Replies
228
Views
13K
Replies
153
Views
7K
Replies
19
Views
2K
Back
Top