Effective Dynamics of Open Quantum Systems: Stochastic vs Unitary Models

In summary: Not quite. But it necessarily has to be described by a different quantum model than unitary dynamics if it is an open system and the rest of the universe is not explicitly modeled.
  • #36
stevendaryl said:
Now, surely there is a difference between using ψcollapsed\psi_{collapsed} for prediction of the probabilities of results of future experiments and using ψuncollapsed\psi_{uncollapsed}. So the collapse hypothesis seems to have testable consequences. So shouldn't we be able to decide, once and for all, whether collapse happens, or not?
Interpretations without collapse have some other assumptions which make them experimentally indistinguishable from interpretations with collapse.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
Demystifier said:
Please, read the general theorem!
The theorem is often stated but I want to read its proof! Please point to a public source where the general theorem is really proved in full generality (rather than outlined only), and I'll read it.
Demystifier said:
One place where the general theorem is presented is my own paper
http://arxiv.org/abs/1112.2034
Secs. 2.1-2.2. The word "theorem" is not explicitly used, nevertheless the proof ends with the proof of the Born rule in Eq. (13).
You already start with assuming that the operator to be measured has a nondegenerate spectrum. This does not cover measuring a spin component of a spinning particle.

Moreover, after (11), you assume without argument that the state of the universe (the only existing state in Bohmian Mechanics) is effectively a tensor product of the state of system+apparatur and the remainder of the universe, which is an assumed collapse!

Thus your proof only works assuming the collapse and then only for observables with nondegenerate spectrum. But your claim is far more general!

I had read the article http://arxiv.org/pdf/1206.1084v2.pdf pointed to by atyy, which had claimed in its introduction
Oriols and Mompart said:
This chapter provides a comprehensive overview of the Bohmian formulation of quantum mechanics.
but failed to explain why this general theorem or even to give a formal reference to a proof. iIt is the introductory article to a book ''Applied Bohmian Mechanics'', so that I'd be allowed to take it as authoritative. But apparently not...
 
  • #38
Demystifier said:
Interpretations without collapse have some other assumptions which make them experimentally indistinguishable from interpretations with collapse.

Yes, I assumed that. But my point, which was addressed to atyy, originally, is that the argument that Bohmian mechanics is equivalent to standard quantum mechanics (with Von Neumann collapse) is not as simple for multiple consecutive measurements as it is for a single measurement. I'm not saying that it's not equivalent, but that the argument that it is equivalent is a lot more complicated than the argument for a single measurement.
 
  • #39
A. Neumaier said:
You already start with assuming that the operator to be measured has a nondegenerate spectrum. This does not cover measuring a spin component of a spinning particle.
Yes, but it's trivial to make an appropriate generalization. Instead of eigenstates ##|k\rangle## with eigenvalues ##k## one can introduce eigenstates ##|k,l\rangle## with eigenvalues ##k##, and in subsequent equations replace label ##k## with label ##k,l## when appropriate.

A. Neumaier said:
Moreover, after (11), you assume without argument that the state of the universe (the only existing state in Bohmian Mechanics) is effectively a tensor product of the state of system+apparatur and the remainder of the universe, which is an assumed collapse!
This is not an assumed collapse. I still have the superposition in (6), so I don't have collapse. The remainder of the universe that appears as a product is that part of the universe that did not play any role in the process of measurement. When you measure spin on Earth, the state of Andromeda galaxy does not have any (significant) influence on it, so the state of Andromeda appears as a product. This, of course, is an approximation, but a very good one.
 
  • #40
A. Neumaier said:
Please point to a public source where the general theorem is really proved in full generality (rather than outlined only), and I'll read it.
Even rigorous mathematicians practice outline of certain generalizations of proofs when the generalization is trivial. (For instance, even Godel only outlined his second incompleteness theorem.) But of course, to see that something is trivial requires understanding. That's why textbooks have exercises, to test your understanding. So I challenge you to do the generalizations and nitpicking details by yourself.
 
  • #41
Demystifier said:
Yes, but it's trivial to make an appropriate generalization. Instead of eigenstates |k⟩|k\rangle with eigenvalues kk one can introduce eigenstates |k,l⟩|k,l\rangle with eigenvalues kk, and in subsequent equations replace label kk with label k,lk,l when appropriate.
No, because the decomposition is no longer unique. Thus your subsequent argument depends on which decomposition you choose.
Demystifier said:
This is not an assumed collapse. I still have the superposition in (6), so I don't have collapse
No. Without collapse you have a similar decomposition as (6) but with the state ##\Phi_k## replaced by a superposition of detector and environment states. Ignoring the environment is collapse - indeed, it changes the dynamics since there is an associated decoherence effect!
Demystifier said:
When you measure spin on Earth, the state of Andromeda galaxy does not have any (significant) influence on it, so the state of Andromeda appears as a product.
I am not worried about Andromeda but about the immediate neighborhood of the detector - the air and the photons that interact with it. They are not far enough a way for your argument to count. (And if you'd prepare Bell states that extend to Andromeda even Andromeda would have to count as being close...)

Your alleged proof (as written) is therefore not more than handwaving.

Demystifier said:
the general theorem that measurement of any observable in non-relativistic Bohmian mechanics leads to probabilities given by the Born rule. The theorem is given in most books and reviews on Bohmian mechanics
Given this multiplicity and the importance of the result, someone should have stated and proved such a fundamental general theorem with impeccable arguments. Please point me to such a treatment.
 
  • #42
Demystifier said:
even Godel only outlined his second incompleteness theorem
But 20 years after Goedel there were plenty of impeccable proofs.

Much more than 20 years have passed since Bell popularized Bohm's theory.
 
Last edited:
  • #43
A. Neumaier said:
No, because the decomposition is no longer unique. Thus your subsequent argument depends on which decomposition you choose.
The final result does not depend on it. It is easy to show it, so I leave it as an exercise for you.

A. Neumaier said:
No. Without collapse you have a similar decomposition as (6) but with the state ##\Phi_k## replaced by a superposition of detector and environment states. Ignoring the environment is collapse - indeed, it changes the dynamics since there is an associated decoherence effect!

I am not worried about Andromeda but about the immediate neighborhood of the detector - the air and the photons that interact with it. They are not far enough a way for your argument to count. (And if you'd prepare Bell states that extend to Andromeda even Andromeda would have to count as being close...)
All the decoherence and neighborhood of the detector can be included into a redefinition of the concept of "apparatus". So its all there, just use the expression "apparatus+neigborhood" instead of "apparatus", if that will make you happy.

A. Neumaier said:
Your alleged proof (as written) is therefore not more than handwaving.
Your objections are trivial nitpicking.

A. Neumaier said:
Someone should have stated and proved such a fundamental general theorem with impeccable arguments. Please point me to such a treatment.
Physics is not mathematics. A mathematically more rigorous proof is presented in
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0308039
but even there such trivial irrelevant omisions can be found by someone who cannot see the forest from the trees.
 
  • #44
A. Neumaier said:
But 20 years after Goedel there were plenty of impeccable proofs.

Much more than 20 years have passed since Bell populaized Bohm's theory.
Fully rigorous proofs on Bohmian mechanics are missing only because there is no many mathematical physicists dealing with Bohmian mechanics. As with other rigorous proofs in physics, theoretical physicists (who are not mathematical physicists) consider it irrelevant nitpicking.
 
  • #45
A. Neumaier said:
Your alleged proof (as written) is therefore not more than handwaving.
In mathematics, that would be a sufficient reason to dismiss the proof. But in physics, the point is whether you understand that handwaving? If you don't, I can't help you. If you do, as a person who likes rigorous proofs you can turn the handwaving into a rigorous proof by yourself.
 
  • #46
Demystifier said:
just use the expression "apparatus+neigborhood" instead of "apparatus", if that will make you happy.
Now the problem is shifted to the missing interaction with the neighborhood of "apparatus+neigborhood". You are entering a Wigner's friend argument, hence you have he same problem as ordinary QM has with the cut in the Copenhagen interpretation.
 
  • #47
A. Neumaier said:
Now the problem is shifted to the missing interaction with the neighborhood of "apparatus+neigborhood". You are entering a Wigner's friend argument, hence you have he same problem as ordinary QM has with the cut in the Copenhagen interpretation.
Again, you are missing the point. If you wish, you may call the whole universe "the apparatus" and say that ##n## is the number of particles in the whole universe. Nothing important in my analysis will be changed and no Wigner's friend problem will remain.

I have also said something more about the Wigner's problem in (the last paragraph of)
http://arxiv.org/abs/1406.3221
 
  • #48
stevendaryl said:
This more sophisticated analysis may reproduce the same predictions as if they used [itex]\psi_{collapsed}[/itex], but it certainly isn't at all obvious, and the equivalence (if they are equivalent) is not particular easy to see.

Yeah, it's not obvious to me either. I have simply worked through enough special cases to believe at the non-rigourous level that BM solves the measurement problem, the same way I believe in the Wilsonian effective field theory picture.
 
  • #49
Demystifier said:
A mathematically more rigorous proof is presented in
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0308039
I found there neither the general theorem (general enough to apply for measuring spin) nor the proof.

But I found unphysical arguments that affect whatever is done: In going from (5.12) to (5.14) it is claimed that if the support of the initial state is a union of two disjoint regions, this remains so in the future ''for a substantial amount of time''. But for laboratory distances, these times are typically extremely short, of the order of the time one of the light particles involved needs to cross the lab. Thus the effective wave functions (which they later simply call wave functions - see bottom of p.29) are not at all guaranteed to exist only for a substantial amount of time, although the authors claim on p.29 that ''the qualifications under which we have established (5.22) are so mild that in practice they exclude almost nothing''.
 
  • #50
atyy said:
I have simply worked through enough special cases to believe at the non-rigourous level
Since Demystifier copped out, could you please point to a paper or bookchapter you worked through, where the case of measuring spin (certainly the most important special case) is treated? Or if this example wasn't needed to make you ''believe at the non-rigourous level that BM solves the measurement problem'', how did you convince yourself of the latter?
 
  • #51
Demystifier said:
it's trivial to make an appropriate generalization. Instead of eigenstates |k⟩ with eigenvalues k one can introduce eigenstates |k,l⟩ with eigenvalues k, and in subsequent equations replace label k with label k,l when appropriate.
A. Neumaier said:
No, because the decomposition is no longer unique. Thus your subsequent argument depends on which decomposition you choose.
Demystifier said:
The final result does not depend on it. It is easy to show it, so I leave it as an exercise for you.
In the case of a spin, ##l## is the position of the measured particle, hence a continuous index. Therefore (3) cannot be valid after your suggested change. Otherwise it would be valid in the limit where the position parts of ##k_1## and ##k_2## tend to each other, which contradicts (4).

Thus the proposed exercise is ill-conceived.
 
  • #52
A. Neumaier said:
Since Demystifier copped out, could you please point to a paper or bookchapter you worked through, where the case of measuring spin (certainly the most important special case) is treated? Or if this example wasn't needed to make you ''believe at the non-rigourous level that BM solves the measurement problem'', how did you convince yourself of the latter?

At the non-rigourous level, I was happy with a non-degenerate case, because I think I can always add a term that breaks the degeneracy by an arbitarily small amount so that it is mathematically non-degenerate, but the difference is physically undetecable.
 
  • #53
atyy said:
At the non-rigourous level, I was happy with a non-degenerate case, because I think I can always add a term that breaks the degeneracy by an arbitarily small amount so that it is mathematically non-degenerate, but the difference is physically undetecable.
But Born's rule in its standard discrete form is robust only under deformations that preserve the discreteness of the spectrum. This cannot resolve the infinite degeneracy of a spin component operator in a single spinning particle.

How would you perturb ##A=\sigma_3## by a tiny amount to get an operator with a nondegenerate spectrum? I don't know of any reasonable perturbation that achieves this. For example, ##A+\epsilon x_3## is still doubly degenerate at each generalized eigenvalue.

Even if you find one, the perturbed version would have to be treated with Born's rule in its continuous form, which doesn't collapse the wave function to a nonexistent normalizable eigenstate.

Thus your perturbation argument is far from convincing!
 
  • #54
A. Neumaier said:
But Born's rule in its standard discrete form is robust only under deformations that preserve the discreteness of the spectrum. This cannot resolve the infinite degeneracy of a spin component operator in a single spinning particle.

How would you perturb ##A=\sigma_3## by a tiny amount to get an operator with a nondegenerate spectrum? I don't know of any reasonable perturbation that achieves this. Even if you find one, the perturbed version would have to be treated with Born's rule in its continuous form, which doesn't collapse the wave function to a nonexistent normalizable eigenstate. Thus your perturbation argument is far from convincing!

You can use the Born rule in continuous form, and collapse it to a normalizable state.

I admit I cannot readily construct a suitable perturbation in all cases.

But just to make sure I understand you - your concern is that eg. with spin, the simplest Coulomb potential hydrogen atom treatment has degeneracy, in the sense that spin up and spin down wave functions can have the same energy?
 
  • #55
atyy said:
You can use the Born rule in continuous form, and collapse it to a normalizable state.
How do you do that? The typical reasoning is that one cannot measure the continuous spectrum exactly but only approximately. Thus one splits the continuum into a discrete union of intervals, each representing an uncertain measurement, and applies the corresponding projectors to get the collapse. But with the finite resolution, each of these projectors has again an infinite degeneracy! Thus one cannot maintain both reduction to a normalizable state and nondegeneracy.
atyy said:
But just to make sure I understand you - your concern is that eg. with spin, the simplest Coulomb potential hydrogen atom treatment has degeneracy, in the sense that spin up and spin down wave functions can have the same energy?
Of course. Most discrete energy eigenstates of the nonrelativistic hydrogen electron are highly degenerate. This is the reason why one gets a fine splitting in the relativistic treatment, and (since some degeneracy still persists) a hyperfine splitting (= Lamb shift) in the QED treatment. The continuous spectrum of the hydrogen electron remains degenerate even in the QED version.

For a multiparticle system that (unlike the hydrogen atom) can dissociate into more than two pieces, part of the continuous spectrum is even infinitely degenerate!
 
  • #56
A. Neumaier said:
How do you do that? The typical reasoning is that one doesn't measure the continuous spectrum exactly but only approximately. Thus one splits the continuum into a discrete union of intervals, each representing an uncertain measurement, and apply the correponding projectors to get the collapse. But with the finite resolution, each of these projectors has again an infinite degeneracy! Thus you cannot maintain both reduction to a normalizable state and nondegeneracy.

That's an issue that is interesting in its own right, apart from discussions about various interpretations of quantum mechanics.

Let's take position as the most familiar example of a continuous observable. Any scheme for measuring position has a limitation in accuracy. So suppose you are using a procedure that only determines position to an accuracy of [itex]\pm \delta x[/itex]. Then in a sense, you're not measuring position, but some related observable [itex]\hat{X}[/itex] that returns a discrete set of possible results: [itex]n \delta x[/itex] where [itex]n[/itex] is an integer. What then, is the complete set of eigenstates of this operator? (Realistically, there is a distinction between returning a fuzzy result with accuracy [itex]\pm \delta x[/itex] and returning the precise result that is [itex]n \delta x[/itex]. But I'm going to use the latter, because it's easier to analyze mathematically.)

Well, the answer is that a complete set of eigenstates would be of the form [itex]\psi_{n,m}[/itex] where:
  • [itex]\psi_{n,m}(x) = 0 [/itex] if [itex]x < n \delta x[/itex]
  • [itex]\psi_{n,m}(x) = sin(\frac{m \pi x}{\delta x}) [/itex] if [itex]n \delta x < x < (n+1) \delta x[/itex]
  • [itex]\psi_{n,m}(x) = 0 [/itex] if [itex]x > (n+1) \delta x[/itex]
So the index [itex]m[/itex] in [itex]\psi_{n,m}[/itex] is this infinite degeneracy that you're talking about. However, when [itex]\delta x[/itex] is very small, then the expectation value for energy increases rapidly with increasing [itex]m[/itex] so for practical purposes, can't we assume that only the [itex]m=1[/itex] eigenstate is relevant?
 
  • #57
stevendaryl said:
Let's take position as the most familiar example of a continuous observable. Any scheme for measuring position has a limitation in accuracy. So suppose you are using a procedure that only determines position to an accuracy of [itex]\pm \delta x[/itex]. Then [...] a complete set of eigenstates would be of the form [itex]\psi_{n,m}[/itex] where:
  • [itex]\psi_{n,m}(x) = 0 [/itex] if [itex]x < n \delta x[/itex]
  • [itex]\psi_{n,m}(x) = sin(\frac{m \pi x}{\delta x}) [/itex] if [itex]n \delta x < x < (n+1) \delta x[/itex]
  • [itex]\psi_{n,m}(x) = 0 [/itex] if [itex]x > (n+1) \delta x[/itex]
So the index [itex]m[/itex] in [itex]\psi_{n,m}[/itex] is this infinite degeneracy that you're talking about. However, when [itex]\delta x[/itex] is very small, then the expectation value for energy increases rapidly with increasing [itex]m[/itex] so for practical purposes, can't we assume that only the [itex]m=1[/itex] eigenstate is relevant?
No, because even the first eigenstate in each interval will already have a very high energy, so should be ignorable by the same argument. But one cannot ignore all basis states! This shows that the energy argument is faulty.

What counts is the energy of the superposition, not of a basis state itself. This energy should be small; an example is the state with ##\psi(x)=x## for ##x\in[0,1]## and zero otherwise. But its projection to any measurable interval inside ##[0,1]## has lots of non-negligible Fourier components with high energy. The very slow convergence of the Fourier series plays havoc with any calculations done subsequent to the approximation.
 
  • #58
A. Neumaier said:
How do you do that? The typical reasoning is that one cannot measure the continuous spectrum exactly but only approximately. Thus one splits the continuum into a discrete union of intervals, each representing an uncertain measurement, and applies the corresponding projectors to get the collapse. But with the finite resolution, each of these projectors has again an infinite degeneracy! Thus one cannot maintain both reduction to a normalizable state and nondegeneracy.

One allows a continuous spectrum to be measured exactly. Then a collapse rule suitable for a continuous variable is given in Eq (3) and (4) of http://arxiv.org/abs/0706.3526.

A. Neumaier said:
Of course. Most discrete energy eigenstates of the nonrelativistic hydrogen electron are highly degenerate. This is the reason why one gets a fine splitting in the relativistic treatment, and (since some degeneracy still persists) a hyperfine splitting (= Lamb shift) in the QED treatment. The continuous spectrum of the hydrogen electron remains degenerate even in the QED version.

For a multiparticle system that (unlike the hydrogen atom) can dissociate into more than two pieces, part of the continuous spectrum is even infinitely degenerate!

I have never worked through this, but googling came up with an attempt in the spirit of my thinking: https://www.ma.utexas.edu/mp_arc/c/12/12-59.pdf

For an attempt to rigourously show that BM reproduces non-relativistic QM (I believe they treat degenerate eigenvalues also), try:
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0308039
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0308038
 
  • #59
A. Neumaier said:
In the case of a spin, l is the position of the measured particle, hence a continuous index.
Someone much more clever than me had a perfect response to that:
"No, no, you're not thinking; you're just being logical."
Niels Bohr


Let me give you a hint (but again not all the details). I did not say that ##|k,l\rangle## are a complete basis. They are just states that in a given experimental setup can be distinguished.

Applying Born rule is like cooking. Either you understand the general principles or you ask for a precise recipe for each possible case.
 
Last edited:
  • #60
Demystifier said:
They are just states that in a given experimental setup can be distinguished.
If it is only finitely many (as in any real experimental setup) it doesn't resolve the infinite degeneracy.
 
  • #61
Demystifier said:
Someone much more clever than me had a perfect response to that:
"No, no, you're not thinking; you're just being logical."
Niels Bohr

I'm not going to venture an opinion about whether this quote is appropriate in the current thread, but I do like the sentiment. There are certain types of counterarguments that sound rational, but can actually be applied endlessly, in every situation, and so in practice often end up being just mud to hurl at your (philosophical) opponents. You can always complain that your opponent is using terms that haven't been given precise enough definitions. You can always complain that your opponent's argument has missing steps, and so is not logically valid. You can always complain that your opponent has insufficient empirical data to justify his conclusions (or that the empirical data has multiple interpretations, only some of which support his conclusions). You can always complain that your opponent's claim that something is impossible only shows a lack of imagination. I could probably put together a toolbox of counterarguments that can be used (with some tweaking) to attack any claim or argument, whatsoever.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #62
atyy said:
For an attempt to rigourously show that BM reproduces non-relativistic QM (I believe they treat degenerate eigenvalues also), try:
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0308039
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0308038
The first one was suggested by Demystifier in post #30, and I commented on it in post #49. The second is indeed about measurement in the POVM version, which I agree is the simplest form for discussing collapse. But I didn't see how the POVM formula is derived from the Bohmian dynamics; p.40 seems to contain only formulas from quantum mechanics that are free of the Bohmian dynamics
 
  • #63
A. Neumaier said:
If it is only finitely many (as in any real experimental setup) it doesn't resolve the infinite degeneracy.
That is true, but I don't see it as a problem. No real experiment can't resolve the infinite degeneracy, and Bohmian mechanics only claims that it can explain the results of real experiments. Bohmian mechanics does not claim that it can explain a more general mathematical Born rule that cannot be directly tested by real experiments.
 
  • #64
Demystifier said:
That is true, but I don't see it as a problem. No real experiment can't resolve the infinite degeneracy
The point is that the recipe to handle degeneracy that you left as a trivial exercise fails if degeneracy is left in the measured operators. To cope with degeneracy (which is necessarily present when you resolve a continuous spectrum only to finite resolution) you need to improve the argument justifying your fundamental theorem!
 
  • #65
A. Neumaier said:
But I found unphysical arguments that affect whatever is done: In going from (5.12) to (5.14) it is claimed that if the support of the initial state is a union of two disjoint regions, this remains so in the future ''for a substantial amount of time''. But for laboratory distances, these times are typically extremely short, of the order of the time one of the light particles involved needs to cross the lab. Thus the effective wave functions (which they later simply call wave functions - see bottom of p.29) are not at all guaranteed to exist only for a substantial amount of time, although the authors claim on p.29 that ''the qualifications under which we have established (5.22) are so mild that in practice they exclude almost nothing''.
You would be right if ##\Psi## was a one-particle wave function. But it is really a wave function describing a very large number of particles, because it includes all the particles of the apparatus. Therefore ##\Psi## does not live in the 3-dimensional space but in a highly dimensional configuration space. In such a big-dimensional space the regions really remain disjoint for a very long time.
 
  • #66
Demystifier said:
In such a big-dimensional space the regions really remain disjoint for a very long time.
Why? Is there somewhere an estimate of the times for a reasonably realistic model system?
 
  • #67
A. Neumaier said:
The point is that the recipe to handle degeneracy that you left as a trivial exercise fails if degeneracy is left in the measured operators. To cope with degeneracy (which is necessarily present when you resolve a continuous spectrum only to finite resolution) you need to improve the argument justifying your fundamental theorem!
All these nitpicking details can relatively easily be done.
 
  • #68
Demystifier said:
All these nitpicking details can relatively easily be done.
How? That something can easily be done is much easier to say than to verify! Your first hint didn't work since it either lead to a continuous index or didn't resolve the degeneracy. Thus I don't trust your intuition without seeing the improved argument.
 
  • #69
A. Neumaier said:
Why? Is there somewhere an estimate of the times for a reasonably realistic model system?
For simplicity, suppose that wave packet of one particle takes 1/10 of the total volume in the laboratory. Then two such wave packets will typically often collide with each other.

But if one-particle wave packet takes 1/10 of the total volume, then ##N##-particle wave packet takes ##(1/10)^N## of the total configuration-space volume. For ##N=10^{23}## this is an incredibly small number. It should be clear that two such small objects will very rarely collide. Try to estimate typical times by yourself.
 
  • #70
A. Neumaier said:
How? That something can easily be done is much easier to say than to verify! Your first hint didn't work since it either lead to a continuous index or didn't resolve the degeneracy. Thus I don't trust your intuition without seeing the improved argument.
You don't motivate me take an effort to explain the details. When I explain some details to you, you never say "Ah, thanks, now I understand that. Could you please explain one more thing to me?". Instead, you merely jump to another question without showing any sign that my previous explanations were at least partially successful. That is not motivating.
 

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
10
Views
3K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
26
Views
8K
Replies
65
Views
8K
Replies
87
Views
6K
Back
Top