- #71
- 8,943
- 2,949
bluecap said:in terms of Many-Worlds, we only share the same world because we are entangled.
how about in Bohmian, Copenhagen, Objective Collapse, Cramers, Ensemble, how do you describe it in terms of the description "we only share the same world because we are entangled", can we say for example "In terms of Bohmian, we only share the same pilot wave because we are entangled"? how about others? thank you.
So let me illustrate with Schrodinger's cat.
You have a radioactive atom that is in a superposition of a decayed atom and an undecayed atom. The decayed atom triggers the release of poison, killing a cat. The undecayed atom leaves the cat alive.
So in the Many-Worlds interpretation, the state of the universe is a superposition of two possibilities:
- [itex]\psi_{dead}[/itex]: The atom is decayed, the poison is released, the cat is dead, Schrodinger sees a dead cat, etc.
- [itex]\psi_{alive}[/itex]: The atom is not decayed, the poison is not released, the cat is alive, Schrodinger sees a live cat, etc.
In the Bohmian interpretation, you have exactly the same state of the universe as in Many-Worlds, so there is still the same entanglement. The difference is that in the Bohmian interpretation, there is more to the state of the universe than the wave function; the world has an ACTUAL state, where all particles have definite positions at all times. So the cat is either actually dead, or actually alive, although the wave function alone doesn't tell you which is the case.
In collapse interpretations, once Schrodinger checks on his cat, the wave function collapses to one of the possibilities [itex]\psi_{alive}[/itex] or [itex]\psi_{dead}[/itex]. Since neither of those states is entangled, then after the collapse, nothing is entangled.
So it's really only in collapse interpretations does entanglement ever disappear.