Exploring the Fundamental Postulates of QM: Are They Truly Ad-Hoc and Strange?

In summary, the fundamental postulates of quantum mechanics appear ad-hoc and strange compared to the postulates of other physical theories like special relativity and classical mechanics. However, these postulates are motivated by experiments and provide a consistent explanation for observed phenomena. While quantum mechanics may seem different from other theories, it has not been proven wrong and continues to accurately describe the behavior of matter.
  • #1
HomogenousCow
737
213
I find the fundamental postulates of QM very ad-hoc and strange.
Compare them to the fundamental postulates of special relativity, special relativity naturally arises out of classical electromagnetism and the equivalence of all inertial frames, while QM seems to come out of nowhere.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Can you present a list of the postulates you have in mind?
 
  • #3
The reason that the postulates seem to come out of nowhere is because we live in a macroscopic world and do have a built in physical intuition of quantum mechanics.

I'll post the postulates for further conversation referance (for simplicity assume non-degenerate discrete spectrum):

First postulate: At a fixed time t the state of a physical system is defined by specifying a ket |psi(t)> belonging to the state spce E

Second postulate: Every measurable physical quantity A is described by an operator A actin in E; this operator is an observable.

Third postulate: The only possible result of a measurement of a phyical quantity A is one of the eigenvalues of the corresponding observable A.

Fourth postulate: When the physical quantity A is measured on a system in the normalized state |psi>, the probability of obtaining the non-degenerate eivenvalue an of the corresponding observable A is:

p(an) = |<un|psi>|2

where |un> is the normalized eigenvector of A associated with the eigenvalue an,

Fifth postulate: If the measurement of the physical quantity A on the system in the state |psi> gives the result an, the state of the system immediately after the measurement is the normalized projection Pn|psi>/sqrt(<psi|Pn|psi>) of |psi> onto the eigen subspace associated with an.

Sixth postiulate: The time evolution of the state vector |psi(t)> is governed by the Schrodinger equation:

ihbar (d/dt)|ps> = H(t)|psi>

where H(t) is the observabe associated with the total energy of the system.
 
  • #4
HomogenousCow said:
I find the fundamental postulates of QM very ad-hoc and strange.
Compare them to the fundamental postulates of special relativity, special relativity naturally arises out of classical electromagnetism and the equivalence of all inertial frames, while QM seems to come out of nowhere.

It does?

The postulate of SR appears "ad hoc" to me as well. After all, one HAS to make such a thing when saying that c is constant in all reference frame. Only AFTER making a logical/mathematical consequence of such a postulate, and having it match to physics observation, can one consider such a postulate to be correct.

So I don't see this being any different than any other postulate made in physics.

Zz.
 
  • #5
HomogenousCow said:
I find the fundamental postulates of QM very ad-hoc and strange.
Compare them to the fundamental postulates of special relativity, special relativity naturally arises out of classical electromagnetism and the equivalence of all inertial frames, while QM seems to come out of nowhere.
Could it be that you are not bothered by the postulates but by the entities used in the postulates?
 
  • #6
tom.stoer said:
Could it be that you are not bothered by the postulates but by the entities used in the postulates?

More or less, my point is that there is a natural procession from classical mechanics to SR and even GR, the system of things are still comparable to each other, we still have our good old equations of motion and initial value problems.
Whereas for quantum mechanics, it seems the entire formalism has changed. Probability is involved, complex numbers and observables becoming operators, it is completely departed from all other theories.
 
Last edited:
  • #7
ZapperZ said:
It does?

The postulate of SR appears "ad hoc" to me as well. After all, one HAS to make such a thing when saying that c is constant in all reference frame. Only AFTER making a logical/mathematical consequence of such a postulate, and having it match to physics observation, can one consider such a postulate to be correct.

So I don't see this being any different than any other postulate made in physics.

Zz.

I disagree, Einstein's postulates seem much more physical and "tangible" and so do Newtons.
The QM postulates just aren't really motivated by experiment and they don't seem to originate from some simple physical principle.
 
  • #8
HomogenousCow said:
I disagree, Einstein's postulates seem much more physical and "tangible" and so do Newtons.
The QM postulates just aren't really motivated by experiment and they don't seem to originate from some simple physical principle.

I disagree. SR postulate did not originate from "some simple physical principle" either! What physical principle dictates the uniformity and the isotropic nature of c?

What you are describing appears to be a matter of tastes, and that is what we are arguing about now.

Zz.
 
  • #9
@ HomogenousCow: I know what you mean, in that the QM theory seems wildly different to any other physical theory. But I would say that the QM postulates are motivated by experiment. I think they are just the simplest set of postulates that people could think of that matched the new idea of the quantum. (Edit: and this idea of the quantum seemed to consistently agree with experiment).

QM is the same as other physical theories in that it has postulates, makes predictions. But it seems very different to most other of the broad physical theories. You could say this is depends on the person. Some people might think that QM is similar to other theories, and other people might think QM is very dissimilar. Neither person is necessarily wrong. All we can say is that so far QM has not been proven wrong. Therefore, it obeys the correspondence principle, so its result agrees with other theories (like classical mechanics), in the limit which those theories apply to.
 
Last edited:
  • #10
ZapperZ said:
What you are describing appears to be a matter of tastes, and that is what we are arguing about now.
yeah, HomogenousCow is not disputing that QM is a physical theory. he's just saying that it looks pretty ad-hoc and strange. And I would agree with him. Maybe this is too 'philosophical' for PF.
 
  • #11
There is nothing too philosophical with quantum mechanics. It's a clearly stated physical theory about the behavior of matter, it's giving a very precise description about what's observed in nature, and so far there is no empirical evidence for a restriction of its validity. That's why it is the most fundamental theory about matter (its constituents, the elementary particles and the interactions between them). So there is no doubt that quantum theory is a very nice example for a physical theory.

Surely, quantum theory leads to a quite drastic correction of our everyday experience about the behavior of matter, but that's only due to the fact that we are simply not confronted with situations, where the quantum effects (coherence) play a role. Of course, given the microscopical structure of matter the most important conclusion from quantum mechanics is the supposedly "simple fact" that matter in everyday life is pretty stable. Given this "simple fact" in almost all circumstances of everyday life classical mechanics and classical electromagnetism "explain" the behavior of objects around us pretty well.

It's, of course, important for the consistency of these different layers of description of nature that all of them can be understood in terms of the most fundamental theory at hand, which is, in our context quantum theory. That's indeed the case, because the classical behavior of macroscopic objects, including the absence of the unusual properties of coherence, entanglement, "wave-particle complementarity", etc. is understandable from quantum many-body theory, where one derives the classical equations for macroscopic objects as a very good approximation to the full quantum behavior, which we cannot resolve with our senses anyway.

This is not so different from the theory of relativity, where also many aspects appear not to be so easily comprehensible with everyday experience. This starts even with the most simple kinematical effects like the relativity of simultaneity, time dilation, length contraction, etc. Again, the reason is that we are not used to circumstances where relativistic effects play a prominent role since usually bodies around us do not move with a speed close to the speed of light and we are living only in a very weak gravitational field of the Earth (and other bodies around us like the moon and the sun). So again, Newtonian mechanics is well valid in our world of everyday experience, and that's why we are unused to the fact that these phenomena are descibable by the Newtonian approximation of the more comprehensive theory of relativity.

All that is of course not "philosophical" but at the very heart of the natural sciences and the role of model building within them.
 
  • #12
ZapperZ said:
I disagree. SR postulate did not originate from "some simple physical principle" either! What physical principle dictates the uniformity and the isotropic nature of c?

What you are describing appears to be a matter of tastes, and that is what we are arguing about now.

Zz.

Right but I find the postulate that speed of light is the same in all inertial frames much more physical and "tangible" than the QM postulates.
If you look at it, QM is very much just infinite dimensional linear algebra given physical interpretations, it baffles me why they correctly describe our world.

The whole business of quantization gives me a weird feeling, of them all canonical quantization is the most unintuitive to me and path integral quantization is least.
 
  • #13
BruceW said:
But I would say that the QM postulates are motivated by experiment. I think they are just the simplest set of postulates that people could think of that matched the new idea of the quantum.

I agree but it baffles me why this model works, none of the postulates are directly motivated by experimental evidence, only after some deep digging do we find that they agree with interference and other observations.
 
  • #14
HomogenousCow said:
I agree but it baffles me why this model works, none of the postulates are directly motivated by experimental evidence, only after some deep digging do we find that they agree with interference and other observations.
The postulates are a refinement of years of progress based on experimental work. Quantum mechanics wasn't birthed by writing down the postulates.
 
  • #15
It seems like your uneasiness with the postulates of QM is that they are mathematical and not "physical" like the postulates of SR? While I agree that the motivation for the postulates of SR from the need to make Maxwell's equations frame invariant is extremely "physical" and elegant, it is not as if the postulates of QM are completely arbitrary even if they are mathematical. Read the first couple of pages in ch2 of Ballentine and see if the motivation there is satisfactory enough.
 
  • #16
I find the QM axioms rather natural if you take the approach of C*-algebra. In that approach, you can clearly see the link between QM and classical mechanics. And you clearly see that QM and CM are the same thing, except that QM is noncommutative. The usual axioms are than derived through some difficult mathematics.
 
  • #17
Edit: LOL. micromass always finds a way to say something similar to what I'm going to say while I'm typing. :smile: (Although, it's been a while since the last time that happened).

There are at least two other approaches to QM (other than starting with the Hilbert space axioms) that are a bit more intuitive. Unfortunately, they require some very heavy math. I don't have a perfect understanding of either of these approaches, so it's possible that some of these details are a bit off, but I'll try:

One approach argues that if a theory can predict the average value of a sequence of measurements on identically prepared systems, done by identical measuring devices, then we should be able to define equivalence classes of measuring devices, and some mathematical operations on the set of equivalence classes that give it the structure of a C*-algebra. The rest is just an application of the theory of representations of C*-algebras. In particular, there's a theorem that ensures that there's a homomorphism from the C*-algebra (whose members are called "observables" btw) into the set of bounded operators on a Hilbert space. This approach is called algebraic quantum mechanics.

Apparently if the C*-algebra is commutative, there's some other theorem that ensures that what we get is a classical theory.

Another approach argues that there should be a lattice (a partially ordered set that satisfies some additional conditions) associated with each theory, and that this lattice will need to satisfy some technical conditions in order to not be extremely hard to work with. Apparently these technical conditions are sufficient to ensure that the lattice is isomorphic to the lattice of Hilbert subspaces of a Hilbert space. This approach is called quantum logic.

Apparently, if the lattice satisfies some additional conditions that makes it even easier to work with, it will be isomorphic to the (partially ordered) set of subsets of some set X. This set can then be interpreted as the phase space of a classical theory.

Some not so easy references:

Strocchi: Introduction to the mathematical structure of quantum mechanics: a short course for mathematicians.
Araki: Mathematical theory of quantum fields.
Varadarajan: Geometry of quantum theory.

For the algebraic approach, you need to know lots of topology and functional analysis. The book by Varadarjan is so hard to read that it's even hard to tell what sort of things you need to know for the quantum logic approach. The book contains long sections on projective geometry, and measure theory on locally compact simply connected topological groups.
 
Last edited:
  • #18
HomogenousCow said:
I agree but it baffles me why this model works, none of the postulates are directly motivated by experimental evidence, only after some deep digging do we find that they agree with interference and other observations.
yeah, true. But if you look at the postulates of classical mechanics, then it is not immediately obvious that they are related to experimental evidence. As far as I know, these are the most commonly used set of postulates:

1) Transformations between inertial frames of reference are described by continuous, differentiable and bijective functions.
2)If the velocities of two freely moving particles are equal in system S, they will also be equal in system S'.
3)All the inertial reference frames are equivalent.
4)The space in any inertial reference system is isotropic.
5)Simultaneity is not relative. ((This is the one that is different for special relativity))

Maybe you would count these as postulates about the geometry we exist in, and stuff like F=ma as the postulates of mechanics... But the point is that you need these 'geometry postulates' as well as the 'F=ma' postulates, to get classical mechanics. You can't just start with F=ma. In a similar way, you need to have some postulates in QM which do not give off an obvious appearance of being motivated by experimental evidence.

So I'd say that (in my personal opinion), the postulates of QM give as much of an appearance of 'being motivated by experimental evidence' as the postulates of classical mechanics are. (And to be clear, I know it is true a priori that both sets of postulates are motivated by experimental evidence. But the only thing I am discussing is whether it is immediately obvious from looking at the postulates that they are motivated by experimental evidence).
 
  • #19
You might be interested in this document: http://www.math.uchicago.edu/~may/VIGRE/VIGRE2009/REUPapers/Gleason.pdf

Jorriss (and some others at Uchicago to be fair xD) showed it to me ages ago but I guess he forgot to link it himself; esentially it outlines the same issues that you are putting forth but then goes on to give the more "classical mechanics related" C* algebraic approach (note that the results aren't proven in this document but there are references to texts e.g. Rudin where you can see the associated proofs).
 
  • #20
Fredrik, you mention two different theories. Can you tell me which theories are described in the books you recommend?
 
  • #21
micromass said:
Fredrik, you mention two different theories. Can you tell me which theories are described in the books you recommend?
Strocchi and Araki cover the algebraic approach. Varadarajan covers the quantum logic approach. If you are interested in the quantum logic stuff, it might be easier to start with Beltrametti & Cassinelli, or Piron. (Not sure though, I have only read small parts of each).

I should also add that I have only read the first few pages of Araki. They are very readable by the way. There he talks about defining equivalence classes of measuring devices and that kind of stuff. Since the goal of the book apparently has something to do with quantum fields, Strocchi is probably a much better choice for the basics of the algebraic approach.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
I think some of the reasons why quantum theory looks so strange in comparison to other theories are:

- the presentation one encounters in schools/books involves rather contradictory notions (wave - particle). Bohr tried to make this an advantage by his complementarity principle, but after years it still makes a lot of people confused;

- It is very mathematical; Jaynes once remarked that the quantum theory is a mathematical shell without sensible physical content. It is indeed a fusion of new pieces of mathematics due to many different people with different physical/philosophical thinking - Schroedinger, Heisenberg, Dirac, von Neumann ... The mathematics was new and difficult at the time and I think this mystified its physical content very much;

- it still has basic important questions unanswered, like how the actual events that happen are to be described or what is the link to the common macroscopic physics.
 
  • #23
The problem is that people learn classical mechanics using the usual "physical" approach but never learn classical mechanics (CM) in a very mathematical manner (unless they chose to on their own of course) thus giving rise to the issues that the OP puts forth. You can formulate CM in an algebraic manner as well and then go on to QM and the discomfort wouldn't be as big in magnitude. It's like if you first learned about Lagrangian and Hamiltonian mechanics using the language of smooth manifolds and then went on to GR, things would feel very familiar. Anyways, in the spirit of the above link, see here for a brief summary: http://www.math.uchicago.edu/~may/VIGRE/VIGRE2011/REUPapers/Gleason.pdf
 
  • #24
probably a large part of the reason why I find the QM postulates ad-hoc and strange is because they talk about the system, and the state of the system, and how this is related to observables. So straight away, it looks (to me) like the theory of QM is like "well, we've got these strange experimental results, so let's just put together a theory that links the system with the observations, physical meaning be damned"

So really, for me, the QM postulates are strange because when I read them, I think "the people who wrote these really didn't have faith in what they were writing". Of course, this is just a matter of tastes. This doesn't discredit QM in any way as a physical theory. And people have put their faith in QM. For example, Paul Dirac, who predicted the positron, saw that the QM equations might suggest that there is a positively charged electron, and so he predicted the positron, by trusting in the equations of QM.

p.s. when I say 'faith', don't take this as a 'belief in a deity' kind of faith. You know what I mean really.
 
  • #25
BruceW said:
probably a large part of the reason why I find the QM postulates ad-hoc and strange is because they talk about the system, and the state of the system, and how this is related to observables. So straight away, it looks (to me) like the theory of QM is like "well, we've got these strange experimental results, so let's just put together a theory that links the system with the observations, physical meaning be damned"
It looks that way to me too. To be more specific, it looks like a toy theory that was created by a mathematician just to show it's possible to define a theory that assigns non-trivial probabilities (i.e. not always 0 or 1) to possible results of experiments. In fact, it looks like the simplest such theory that has any chance of being even a little bit useful. So I find it pretty remarkable that it has turned out to be the best theory science has ever produced.
 
  • #26
WannabeNewton said:
The problem is that people learn classical mechanics using the usual "physical" approach but never learn classical mechanics (CM) in a very mathematical manner (unless they chose to on their own of course) thus giving rise to the issues that the OP puts forth. You can formulate CM in an algebraic manner as well and then go on to QM and the discomfort wouldn't be as big in magnitude.
that's a good point. people don't usually begin with a mathematical description of CM. And the link you gave talks a lot about the state, for a classical system. So it kind of answers my last post, by saying that actually CM involves a lot of talk about 'the state'.

Although I think that this stuff about 'the state' is not in every mathematical formalism of CM? As in, I would guess it is possible to do a mathematical formalism of CM without defining states as "linear functionals on the set of observables" and without similar statements like these? I am not sure, I really have no experience in this area.

But then on the other hand, if QM and CM are similar in this mathematical formalism (using states and observables), then this means that QM and CM are similar generally. (Since 'similarity' between two physical phenomena should not be dependent on the mathematical formalism). i.e. I am assuming any mathematical formalism of CM that does not involve 'states and observables' should be equivalent to the mathematical formalism of CM that does involve 'states and observables'. (equivalent in the sense that it describes the same physical phenomena).
 
  • #27
BruceW said:
that's a good point. people don't usually begin with a mathematical description of CM. And the link you gave talks a lot about the state, for a classical system. So it kind of answers my last post, by saying that actually CM involves a lot of talk about 'the state'.

Although I think that this stuff about 'the state' is not in every mathematical formalism of CM? As in, I would guess it is possible to do a mathematical formalism of CM without defining states as "linear functionals on the set of observables" and without similar statements like these? I am not sure, I really have no experience in this area.

But then on the other hand, if QM and CM are similar in this mathematical formalism (using states and observables), then this means that QM and CM are similar generally. (Since 'similarity' between two physical phenomena should not be dependent on the mathematical formalism). i.e. I am assuming any mathematical formalism of CM that does not involve 'states and observables' should be equivalent to the mathematical formalism of CM that does involve 'states and observables'. (equivalent in the sense that it describes the same physical phenomena).

States in CM are usually described as actual points in some space. So you have a space ##X## (for example ##\mathbb{R}^{6n}##) and the points in here are states. The observables are continuous functions ##f:X\rightarrow \mathbb{R}##. So the set of all continuous functions ##\mathcal{C}(X)## is the set of observables, in some sense.

In the "algebraic" approach to QM, you are given a set of observables ##A## (which is analgous to ##\mathcal{C}(X)##). But the states now are certain linear functionals on ##A##. So a state is a function ##T:A\rightarrow \mathbb{R}## such that some properties are preserved. If ##a\in A##, then we should see ##T(a)## as some kind of average.

These two approaches seem not very similar, but they actually are. Indeed, given a classical system ##X## with ##\mathcal{C}(X)##, then any ##x\in X## determines a linear functional as ##\mathcal{C}(X)\rightarrow \mathbb{R}: f\rightarrow f(x)##. Furthermore, it can be shown that this correspondance is a bijection. So all linear functionals (with the right properties) correspond to elements of the state space.

This correspondance fails if ##A## is noncommutative. And if ##A## is noncommutative, then there is no right notion of state space (there are notions, but they are very ill behaved). So instead of working with an actual space ##X##, we work with the linear functionals as states. Then QM can be developed by associating a Hilbert space with ##A## and so on.
 
  • #28
WannabeNewton said:
The problem is that people learn classical mechanics using the usual "physical" approach but never learn classical mechanics (CM) in a very mathematical manner (unless they chose to on their own of course) thus giving rise to the issues that the OP puts forth. You can formulate CM in an algebraic manner as well and then go on to QM and the discomfort wouldn't be as big in magnitude. It's like if you first learned about Lagrangian and Hamiltonian mechanics using the language of smooth manifolds and then went on to GR, things would feel very familiar. Anyways, in the spirit of the above link, see here for a brief summary: http://www.math.uchicago.edu/~may/VIGRE/VIGRE2011/REUPapers/Gleason.pdf

I think there would still be some discomfort, I'm guessing the born interpretation doesn't just pop out of this reformulation of QM.
The fact that the theory is ultimately undeterministic, I think, is what ultimately makes me uncomfortable.
To expand, let's say that the hidden variables theory is correct and we one day find a deterministic theory that explains it all, how does one explain the fact that we just happened to have created an indeterminstic one beforehand?? How did we happen to guess that these were the statistical version of the underlying deterministic theory?
 
  • #29
Well, you can think about determinism as something much more incomprehensible than indeterminism. Why should nature behave deterministic?

Then, of course there is always the possibility that one day any physical theory may be found to be incomplete. It's even pretty likely that this happens to a physical theory. Quantum theory is not an exception. Only at the moment, there is no hint, how such a theory might look like. However, if such a theory is deterministic, it must be a pretty complicated non-local scheme since the violation of Bell's inquality (in accordance with quantum theory!) is a well-established empirical fact. So far there is no convincing non-local theory found. As long as we have nothing better we have to live with quantum theory. Due to the great successes of quantum theory it is clear that any more comprehensive theory must contain it as a limiting case of approximate accuracy and with a certain range of applicability. This is the case with Newtonian mechanics vs. the theory of relativity. The former can be derived from the latter as an approximation, valid for velocities small compared to the speed of light and for only small gravitational fields.
 
  • #30
HomogenousCow said:
I think there would still be some discomfort, I'm guessing the born interpretation doesn't just pop out of this reformulation of QM.
It doesn't imply that we should assign probabilities to measurement results, but it turns out that there's only way to do that. That result implies the Born rule.
 
  • #31
HomogenousCow said:
I think there would still be some discomfort, I'm guessing the born interpretation doesn't just pop out of this reformulation of QM.

In Classical mechanics, the observables can be seen as ##\mathcal{C}(X)## and the (pure) states are certain functionals. The Riesz representation theorem suggests that the states are averages with respect to some probability theory.

In the algebraic approach, we have an algebra of observables ##A## and certain functionals, called the (pure) states. If we only accept that there functionals are averages wrt to some probabilities (which is already suggested in the classical sense), then everything else pops out. In particular, the Born rule can be deduced. A good account of this is given in Ballentine. Ballentine sadly does not do the most general case of C*-algebras. But he does show how you can derive the entire probabilistic structure from simply accepting that the states give some kind of averages.
 
  • #32
Apparently, in QM we need both pure states and other states. But in Classical Mechanics, we can get by with just the pure states. The pure states already determine the entire phase space ##X##. The other states induce naturally probability distributions on ##X##, but they don't seem necessary. Is there some interpretation in CM for states that are not pure states? Are they somehow needed in CM?
 
  • #33
So to summarize, in this formulation of CM and QM, we have indeterminism everywhere but observables in CM all commute thus we have simultaneous eigenstates for all observables and the probabilities never come to play at all?
 
  • #34
HomogenousCow said:
So to summarize, in this formulation of CM and QM, we have indeterminism everywhere but observables in CM all commute thus we have simultaneous eigenstates for all observables and the probabilities never come to play at all?
To view CM and QM as two aspects of the same thing, we need to view CM as an assignment of probabilities as well. But the probabilities assigned will all be 0 or 1, when we're dealing with pure states.
 
  • #35
so just as I said then, does the schroedinger equation also arise from this?
 

Similar threads

Replies
130
Views
9K
Replies
29
Views
4K
Replies
69
Views
5K
Replies
23
Views
4K
Replies
14
Views
2K
Replies
15
Views
2K
Replies
28
Views
2K
Replies
27
Views
3K
Back
Top