How do entanglement experiments benefit from QFT (over QM)?

In summary, the conversation discusses two important points: the first being the difference between QFT and quantum mechanics (QM) and the second being the role of QFT in analyzing entanglement experiments. QFT is a more comprehensive theory than QM, and while it is commonly used in quantum optics papers, it is not often referenced in experimental papers on entanglement. The main reason for this is that QFT is primarily used when dealing with particle-number changing processes, which are not relevant in most entanglement experiments. In addition, while QFT helps to understand how entanglement should not be explained, it does not provide a significant advantage in explaining entanglement itself, and discussions of entanglement often focus on photons due to
  • #421
Does that mathematically consistent single sample space have to contain a cat that is both dead and alive.

Trying to understand if the argument here is about what is mathematically consistent vs. what is both mathematically consistent and observable... or something like that.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #422
DarMM said:
A non-commutative C*-algebra with normed states on it? That is utterly standard. That is QM. A non-commutative C*-algebra has multiple sample spaces. The proof being there is no Gelfand homomorphism that covers the whole algebra. The End.I've been saying Bohmian Mechanics has a single sample space from the beginning, before you got involved. I've never denied this.

Look just look at post #376, I think it is clear you are not actually understanding the papers and material being referenced here.If the C*-algebraic structure and the associated dual state space of QM is "my interpretation" I hope I get my Nobel Prize soon.

Then the BM interpretation of QM is QM itself according to you and it also has a single sample space as constructed by Kochen and Specher not restricted to the noncommutative algebra(do you understand that in this generalization of the probability the noncommutative algebra is a special case?) besides multiple sample spaces for predictions involving just the noncommutative algebra.

I won't continue this exchange, as it seems you only keep repeating the same mantra to save face.
 
  • Sad
Likes weirdoguy
  • #423
Tendex said:
Then the BM interpretation of QM is QM itself according to you
No, Bohmian Mechanics has a completely different mathematical structure. A structure which as of yet has not been shown to give results compatible with QFT, and possibly (there isn't complete proof in this regard) replicates non-relativistic QM when in equilibrium if one ignores iterated Wigner's friend scenarios. It is a different theory that isn't fully developed as of 2019.

QM itself, the fully developed framework of non-commutative C* algebras and states and unitaries upon them is the theory which matches all experimental predictions and it constitutes a multi-sample space probability theory.

Tendex said:
it also has a single sample space
Yes, as I have said from the beginning Bohmian Mechanics has a single sample space.

Tendex said:
do you understand that in this generalization of the probability the noncommutative algebra is a special case?
It isn't. I would study how QM's algebra is embedded in Bohmian observable algebra, it's quite subtle.

Tendex said:
I won't continue this exchange, as it seems you only keep repeating the same mantra to save face.
I'm just glad the whole field uses my terminology and classifications, at least we all get to save face together. :rolleyes:
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and weirdoguy
  • #424
DarMM said:
If locality and no retrocausality are retained then yes.

DarMM said:
BM rejects locality and thus retains a common sample space. The quantum formalism retains locality and rejects a common sample space.

I don't understand how the quantum formalism can retain locality by rejecting a single sample space. If the quantum state is not real, then the quantum formalism is not nonlocal, thus saving locality in a sense. However, saying that the quantum state is not real does not mean that the quantum formalism is local, because realism is a precondition for locality. If the quantum state is real, then the quantum formalism is nonlocal.

So I link the nonreality of the quantum state to saving locality in some sense, whereas you link not having a single sample space to saving locality. Is the nonreality of the quantum state related to not having a single sample space (I don't see how it is)?
 
Last edited:
  • #425
atyy said:
because realism is a precondition for locality
I'll answer this tomorrow, but what exactly do you mean here?
 
  • #426
This is based on Wiseman's well known complete exposition of Bell's theorem:
https://arxiv.org/abs/1503.06413
Which is itself an outcome of work explicating the theorem such as those by Fine and Jarrett.

So Bell's theory assumes:
  1. A measurement has a single objective outcome
  2. Light Cones, space-like separation and hypersurfaces, i.e. the machinery of Minkowski spacetime, make sense for laboratory experiments. Rejecting this is essentially the EPR = ER idea.
  3. For an event ##A## there is a hypersurface that separates events in the PAST of ##A## from those which have ##A## as their past.
  4. A cause of an event is in its PAST. Note axioms (3) and (4) don't yet say the PAST is the past lightcone. They just amount to no retrocausality.

    That concludes the most basic assumption that both classical-like hidden variable theories and QM agree on
  5. Free Choice. It is possible to choose settings in a Bell experiment in a way that is not correlated with the particles, i.e. no superdeterminism
  6. Relativistic Causality. The PAST is the contained in the past light cone
  7. Common causes. If ##A## and ##B## are correlated and they are not the cause of each other, then they have a set of common causes responsible for the correlation ##\mathcal{C}##. This is just the preparation in a Bell experiment, i.e. an event without which there would be no correlation
  8. Decorrelating Explanation. There is an event, some subset of the common causes, that decorrelates the experiments, i.e. the probabilities for ##A## and ##B## factor

The problem with many expositions of Bell's theorem is that they collapse these assumptions into a smaller list. For example Relativistic Causality and Decorrelating Explanation together are equivalent to Bell's assumption in his second (stronger) theorem of 1976 called Local Causality. Which is where I think your statement of "Realism is a precondition for locality" comes from.

So Hidden Variable theories like Bohm's reject Relativistic Causality , where as in QM itself it is Decorrelating Explanations that are violated which is equivalent to rejecting a single space.

This is because for all variables to be conditionable upon a single set of events ##\lambda## they need to be Random Variables on a single common sample space. If they're in different sample spaces this is impossible.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes mattt, weirdoguy, Jimster41 and 2 others
  • #427
DarMM said:
  • Common causes. If ##A## and ##B## are correlated and they are not the cause of each other, then they have a set of common causes responsible for the correlation ##\mathcal{C}##. This is just the preparation in a Bell experiment, i.e. an event without which there would be no correlation
  • Decorrelating Explanation. There is an event, some subset of the common causes, that decorrelates the experiments, i.e. the probabilities for ##A## and ##B## factor
So Hidden Variable theorems like Bohm's reject Relativistic Causality , where as in QM itself it is Decorrelating Explanations that are violated which is equivalent to a single space.

This is because for all variables to be conditionable upon a single set of events ##\lambda## they need to be Random Variables on a single common sample space. If they're in different sample spaces this is impossible.
And this is already close to the key point. Namely, beyond the basic laws of plausible reasoning, which are Kolmogorovian probability with a single sample space (which can be constructed for QT following Kochen Specker) there is also another important law which has to be rejected by non-realistic interpretations: Namely, causality in general. Because of causality without the requirement of common causes, which have to decorrelate observed correlations is not worth much. The tobacco industry would be happy if they could handle some correlations between smoking and lung cancer in a similar way as the violations of the Bell inequalities, namely by rejecting the necessity to find such common causes sufficient to decorrelate those correlations. All they probably have to do is to refer to quantum strangeness, more explanation is no longer required.

But who would accept this? And why this would be rejected? Because of not only the laws of plausible reasoning but also the basic concepts of causality like the common cause principle, are metatheoretical laws of reasoning, part of the scientific method itself, and therefore not open to experimental falsification.
 
  • Sad
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy and Tendex
  • #428
DarMM said:
For an event ##A## there is a hypersurface that separates events in the PAST of ##A## from those which have ##A## as their past.

This is inconsistent with #2. There is no "past" in Minkowski spacetime; there are only the past and future light cones and the spacelike separated region. (Note that this as you state it is also inconsistent with #6, since the boundary of the past light cone does not separate the past of ##A## with events that have ##A## in their past; the latter events are the future light cone, not the complement of the past light cone.)

If you're going to assume #2, I don't see the point of #3 and #4 at all.
 
  • #429
PeterDonis said:
If you're going to assume #2, I don't see the point of #3 and #4 at all.
It's the assumption of topological triviality. Wiseman has more detail. It's saying that you can even get the notion of a flat spacetime of the ground and operationally validate if there is spacelike communication. It's not as such an assumption that the event strucutre of Minkowski space is valid, but that it can be operationally checked.

#3 and #4 are then further specifications that aspects of that structure are valid, so there is a point to them.

PeterDonis said:
This is inconsistent with #2.
It isn't. It isn't rejecting what you mention.
 
  • #430
PeterDonis said:
Note that this as you state it is also inconsistent with #6, since the boundary of the past light cone does not separate the past of AAA with events that have AAA in their past; the latter events are the future light cone, not the complement of the past light cone.
Why do you think it refers to the boundary of the past light cone?
 
  • #431
DarMM said:
It's the assumption of topological triviality. Wiseman has more detail.

I'll take a look at the paper then. It might be that I'm simply not familiar with this way of describing things. But I still see a contradiction; see below.

DarMM said:
Why do you think it refers to the boundary of the past light cone?

Axiom #3 says that there is some hypersurface that bounds the PAST of ##A## from events that have ##A## in their past. That axiom says that the entire spacetime is divided into only two regions: the PAST of ##A## and events that have ##A## in their past. In other words: the region containing events that have ##A## in their past must be the complement of the PAST of ##A##.

Then axiom #6 says the PAST of ##A## is its past light cone; that means the boundary of the past light cone must be the hypersurface referred to by axiom #3 and the region containing events that have ##A## in their past must be the complement of the past light cone. But this is obviously false for Minkowski spacetime.
 
  • #432
PeterDonis said:
Axiom #3 says that there is some hypersurface that bounds the PAST of ##A## from events that have ##A## in their past. That axiom says that the entire spacetime is divided into only two regions: the PAST of ##A## and events that have ##A## in their past. In other words: the region containing events that have ##A## in their past must be the complement of the PAST of ##A##.
No. By definition, a separating hyperplane of two sets A and B is any hyperplane such that A and B are on different sides of the hyperplane. A and B can be small sets!
 
  • #433
PeterDonis said:
That axiom says that the entire spacetime is divided into only two regions
Perhaps this is how I phrased it, but it is saying that there is a hypersurface with those two sets of events on either side. Not that those two sets constitute all events.
 
  • #434
DarMM said:
it is saying that there is a hypersurface with those two sets of events on either side. Not that those two sets constitute all events.

Ah, ok. So in Minkowski spacetime any spacelike hypersurface that contains event ##A## would satisfy #3.
 
  • #435
PeterDonis said:
Ah, ok. So in Minkowski spacetime any spacelike hypersurface that contains event ##A## would satisfy #3.
Precisely.
 
  • #436
DarMM said:
I'll answer this tomorrow, but what exactly do you mean here?

There are (at least) two types of locality
(1) no faster than light transmission of information
(2) classical relativistic causality

Classical relativistic causality requires realism as a precondition, since it does not make sense for a cause not to be real. Hence if the quantum state is assumed not to be real, it cannot be claimed that the quantum formalism has classical relativistic causality. If the quantum state is not real, then it evades Bell's theorem, so Bell's theorem cannot be used to say that QM is nonlocal; at the same time, the lack of reality also means that it cannot be said that QM is local. If the quantum state is real, then Bell's theorem applies, and the quantum formalism has manifest nonlocality (collapse of the wave function).

You can find these sentiments in these papers:

https://arxiv.org/abs/0706.2661 by Harrigan and Spekkens: (footnote 16)
"Note that no notion of ‘realism’ appears in our implication.This is because there is no sense in which there is an assumption of realism that could be abandoned while salvaging locality. There is a notion of realism at play when we grant that experimental procedures prepare and measure properties of systems, but it is a prerequisite to making sense of the notion of locality. Norsen has emphasized this point [41, 42]."

https://arxiv.org/abs/1208.4119 by Wood and Spekkens (p2)
"Nonetheless,this is an improvement over the standard characterization of Bell’s theorem as forcing a dilemma between abandoninglocality and abandoningrealism. It has always been rather unclear what precisely is meant by “realism”. Norsen hasconsidered various philosophical notions of realism and concluded that none seem to have the feature that one couldhope to save locality by abandoning them [8]. For instance, if realism is taken to be a commitment to the existenceof an external world, then the notion of locality – that every causal influence between physical systems propagatessub luminally – already presupposes realism "
 
  • Like
Likes Elias1960
  • #437
atyy said:
requires realism as a precondition
First I'd ask what you mean by "realism" in precise mathematical terms.

atyy said:
There are (at least) two types of locality
(1) no faster than light transmission of information
(2) classical relativistic causality
What you are calling Classic Relativistic Causality is I think a combination of Decorrelating Explanations and Relativistic Causality, i.e. what Bell in his 1976 paper called Local Causality. Indeed QM does not have Local Causality. However as I mentioned in #426 you have to split the assumption up to see what is really being rejected, namely Decorrelating Explanations.

If you include hidden variables in the definition of Locality, then certainly one cannot have locality in the Quantum formalism. However all one is really saying is that it has no hidden variables, as that is what is really being rejected.

Wiseman wrote his paper in order to separate out the assumptions fully due to confusion like this.

atyy said:
Classical relativistic causality requires realism as a precondition, since it does not make sense for a cause not to be real. Hence if the quantum state is assumed not to be real, it cannot be claimed that the quantum formalism has classical relativistic causality
This seems to be identifying ##\Psi##-ontic views with realism. I would have said that psi-onticism is a separate notion from "realism". ##\Psi##-epistemic retrocausal theories are "realist" in the sense of having a hidden variable account, but the wavefunction is not "real" in them.

atyy said:
If the quantum state is not real, then it evades Bell's theorem
That's not directly true. Bell's theorem doesn't really assume anything to do with ##\Psi## in its formulation. Again a ##\Psi##-epistemic retrocausal theory avoids Bell's theorem via the retrocausal elements, not so much the status of the wavefunction.

How QM itself avoids Bell's theorem is via dropping Decorrelating Explanations (which means multiple sample spaces). Bohmian Mechanics does it via dropping Relativistic Causality.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes mattt
  • #438
Elias1960 said:
And this is already close to the key point. Namely, beyond the basic laws of plausible reasoning, which are Kolmogorovian probability with a single sample space (which can be constructed for QT following Kochen Specker)
I've already described how that sample space is not something predicted by QM. That's a fact, a non-commutative C*-algebra cannot have a single sample space.

Elias1960 said:
But who would accept this? And why this would be rejected? Because of not only the laws of plausible reasoning but also the basic concepts of causality like the common cause principle, are metatheoretical laws of reasoning, part of the scientific method itself, and therefore not open to experimental falsification.
Well it's what QM rejects, I am only reporting that. It's not "my view" or something, it's what the machinery of QM itself does.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and weirdoguy
  • #439
DarMM said:
How QM itself avoids Bell's theorem is via dropping Decorrelating Explanations (which means multiple sample spaces). Bohmian Mechanics does it via dropping Relativistic Causality.
QM itself avoids nothing because this is not part of the minimal interpretation. It is your preferred interpretation of QM which avoids it in this way.

DarMM said:
I've already described how that sample space is not something predicted by QM. That's a fact, a non-commutative C*-algebra cannot have a single sample space.
There is no need for such a prediction because the construction of such a space is a straightforward and trivial thing. Take all the propositions in your field of discourse. They define a Boolean algebra. Then use Stone's theorem and get a sample space. Applied to QM, this gives the Kochen Specker construction.

The notion of "single sample space of a non-commutative C*-algebra" is obviously something completely different and irrelevant. It is your personal metaphysical choice that this structure is of some fundamental importance.
DarMM said:
Well it's what QM rejects, I am only reporting that. It's not "my view" or something, it's what the machinery of QM itself does.
No, these are the metaphysical choices you have made by choosing your preferred interpretation of QM. You are aware that there exist other interpretations of QM which have a different view. A piece of mathematical machinery does nothing without your interpretational choices. Here, in particular, you make the assumption that that ##C^*## structure is something fundamentally important, and not a nice accidental consequence of the fact that the stochastic equations for ##\rho(q)## and ##S(q)## become linear equations for ##\psi## for the particular choice of ##\hbar## in ##\psi=\sqrt{\rho}\exp(\frac{i}{\hbar}S)##.

I do not question the idea that this linearity is something really fundamental, and not an otherwise meaningless accident. But it is a metaphysical choice you have to make, and without this choice, QM tells you nothing.

So, it is your own metaphysical decision to reject the necessity of decorrelating explanations. I have explained the consequences of this decision if one would apply this not as a special excuse to handle the violations of the Bell inequalities, but would be applied consistently everywhere: It would destroy the scientific method completely. It may be nonetheless a reasonable decision for you, the tobacco industry possibly needs better public relation specialists, and for a scientist which could explain that because of quantum strangeness there is no necessity at all to decorrelate smoking from lung cancer they could pay a lot. But it remains your choice. You have the freedom to accept, as well, realist interpretations of QM which preserve the scientific method.
 
  • Like
  • Sad
Likes zonde, weirdoguy and Tendex
  • #440
Elias1960 said:
QM itself avoids nothing because this is not part of the minimal interpretation. It is your preferred interpretation of QM which avoids it in this way
The mathematical formalism of QM does not have decorrelating explanations because the observables are not defined on a common sample space to condition the events on.

That's just part of the QM formalism, not "my interpretation".

This thread has become bizarre where basic mathematical facts of QM are being called "my interpretation".

Elias1960 said:
The notion of "single sample space of a non-commutative C*-algebra" is obviously something completely different and irrelevant. It is your personal metaphysical choice that this structure is of some fundamental importance.
What?! QM has non-commutative C*-algebras, how is that my metaphysical choice?

Utter crankish garbage I have to say. Another thread where basic aspects of QM have to be defended and explained for page upon page to people at least four decades out of date.

Elias1960 said:
It would destroy the scientific method completely. It may be nonetheless a reasonable decision for you, the tobacco industry possibly needs better public relation specialists, and for a scientist which could explain that because of quantum strangeness there is no necessity at all to decorrelate smoking from lung cancer they could pay a lot
:rolleyes:
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #441
Elias1960 said:
No, these are the metaphysical choices you have made by choosing your preferred interpretation of QM. You are aware that there exist other interpretations of QM which have a different view. A piece of mathematical machinery does nothing without your interpretational choices. Here, in particular, you make the assumption that that ##C^*## structure is something fundamentally important, and not a nice accidental consequence of the fact that the stochastic equations for ##\rho(q)## and ##S(q)## become linear equations for ##\psi## for the particular choice of ##\hbar## in ##\psi=\sqrt{\rho}\exp(\frac{i}{\hbar}S)##.
Show me such a construction for QFT.

Even so it is an alternate construction. The mathematics of QM does not involve such things, an alternate formalism incapable of replicating QFT and not known to replicate all of QM (as of 2019) does, but that's not QM.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and weirdoguy
  • #442
Elias1960 said:
Take all the propositions in your field of discourse. They define a Boolean algebra.

Not for QM they don't. For example, consider the two propositions relating to an electron that has just passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction and has come out the "up" output:

(1) This electron has ##z## spin up.

(2) This electron has ##x## spin up.

#1 has a well-defined truth value, namely "true". #2 does not have a well-defined truth value at all. Therefore no set of propositions that contains both #1 and #2 can define a Boolean algebra. But both propositions are part of the "field of discourse" of QM. (I believe this is the kind of thing @DarMM is referring to when he says QM requires multiple sample spaces.)
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, DennisN, weirdoguy and 1 other person
  • #443
PeterDonis said:
Not for QM they don't. For example, consider the two propositions relating to an electron that has just passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction and has come out the "up" output:

(1) This electron has ##z## spin up.

(2) This electron has ##x## spin up.

#1 has a well-defined truth value, namely "true". #2 does not have a well-defined truth value at all. Therefore no set of propositions that contains both #1 and #2 can define a Boolean algebra. But both propositions are part of the "field of discourse" of QM. (I believe this is the kind of thing @DarMM is referring to when he says QM requires multiple sample spaces.)
Yes that is equivalent to what I am saying.

Labelling your two events as ##A## and ##B##, a Boolean algebra requires both ##A \lor B## and ##A \land B## to exist which isn't true for such events. These are basic requirements of both Boolean algebras and ##\sigma##-algebras (the latter are basically just a special type of Boolean algebra) and are required to define a measure. Since we don't have this we can't define a measure and thus we don't have a sample space containing both events.
 
Last edited:
  • #444
DarMM said:
First I'd ask what you mean by "realism" in precise mathematical terms.

In the context of the Wiseman paper, my term "realism" is used in the sense that if something is designated as contributing to a cause, then it is real.

Thus if the wave function is real, then QM manifestly violates relativistic causality. If it is not real, then relativistic causality need not be violated. However, relativistic "causality" in the sense of having "causes" is then empty, unless one uses a different definition of cause than as conventionally used in science - for example, one could try using notions discussed in https://arxiv.org/abs/1602.07404.

That is my interpretation of Wiseman's comment (p22):
"That is, even the process whereby, when Alice and Bob share a singlet state, a measurement by Alice in a certain basis causes the quantum state of Bob’s system to collapse instantaneously into one of the basis states, does not violate LOCALITY. Yet the very wording of the preceding sentence implies that the described process does violate RELATIVISTIC CAUSALITY. By contrast, operational quantum mechanics does not violate RELATIVISTIC CAUSALITY, because it does not entail any causal narrative involving quantum states, but simply uses them as computational tools. A more precise formulation of this idea will be given elsewhere [10]."

DarMM said:
How QM itself avoids Bell's theorem is via dropping Decorrelating Explanations (which means multiple sample spaces). Bohmian Mechanics does it via dropping Relativistic Causality.

So Wiseman agrees with me that if the wave function is real, QM violates relativistic causality. However, it would seem that there is no single sample space whether or not the wave function is real. So I don't see how not having a single sample space allows relativistic causality to be saved, unless it has something to do with the wave function contributing or not contributing to a causal narrative.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Jimster41
  • #445
atyy said:
In the context of the Wiseman paper, my term "realism" is used in the sense that if something is designated as contributing to a cause, then it is real.
Is this a common cause or a decorrelating explanation though?

atyy said:
However, relativistic "causality" in the sense of having "causes" is then empty
This is tied into the question above.

atyy said:
So Wiseman agrees with me that if the wave function is real, QM violates relativistic causality.
Yes, if you have a wavefunction as a propogating wave you violate relativistic causality. Such a case is Bohmian Mechanics which as I said violates Relativistic causality and has a single sample space.

atyy said:
However, it would seem that there is no single sample space whether or not the wave function is real.
This is the point of error.

If the wavefunction is real then it defines an outcome and thus your sample space is:
$$\mathcal{H} \times \Sigma$$
with ##\Sigma## being possible additional variables. This is basically what is going on in Bohmian Mechanics.

If the wavefunction is not real, then outcomes are given by POVM elements and probabilities are given by contraction against elements of the dual to the algebra of which wavefunctions are a special case. This is the standard Quantum Formalism. Due to the algebra being noncommutative it cannot be given a common sample space and thus one loses decorrelating explanations and then avoids Bell's theorem.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and Jimster41
  • #446
A toy example from classical probability might help.

Imagine our sample space is some finite set ##\Omega## and probability distributions on it ##\rho(\omega)##.
We know ##\rho(\omega) \in \mathcal{L}^{1}\left(\Omega\right)##.

If I claim the outcomes/set of events are given by elements or subsets of ##\Omega## my state space is finite, but if I say the probability distributions are the actual outcomes/events then my events are subsets of ##\mathcal{L}^{1}\left(\Omega\right)## which is an infinite-dimensional space. So changing the physical status of ##\rho(\omega)## results in an infinitely larger outcome space with very different properties.

This is essentially an aspect of the relation between standard QM and Bohmian Mechanics. Bohmian Mechanics gains a single sample space which is infinitely larger than any of the multiple ones in QM by promoting ##\psi## from being a (generalized) probability distribution to being an actual outcome.

Nobody has managed to prove such a promotion actually replicates QM completely. And there are no indications such a promotion works at all for QFT.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt
  • #447
Sorry, What is L^1 there?
 
  • #448
DarMM said:
Is this a common cause or a decorrelating explanation though?
DarMM said:
This is tied into the question above.

I'm not sure. Instinctively, I would say both a common cause and a decorrelating explanation. Can one have decorrelating explanation without common cause?

DarMM said:
This is the point of error.

If the wavefunction is real then it defines an outcome and thus your sample space is:
$$\mathcal{H} \times \Sigma$$
with ##\Sigma## being possible additional variables. This is basically what is going on in Bohmian Mechanics.

If the wavefunction is not real, then outcomes are given by POVM elements and probabilities are given by contraction against elements of the dual to the algebra of which wavefunctions are a special case. This is the standard Quantum Formalism. Due to the algebra being noncommutative it cannot be given a common sample space and thus one loses decorrelating explanations and then avoids Bell's theorem.

Well, perhaps a point of error or maybe just not understanding your terminology. I have not understood till now why you say BM has a single sample space, but QM does not - to me neither have a single sample space in only the variables defined in Fine's theorem. It wasn't clear to me that you were referring to different sample spaces in each theory.

Anyway, if you mean QM rejects decorrelating explanation, then I understand what you mean (and yes, I do agree with Wiseman). I would, however, disagree on terminology. I would say QM is neutral on the rejection of decorrelating explanation, and it is neutral on the general issue of having no single sample space in arbitrary variables. I would say rejecting decorrelating explanation is an ultra-Copenhagenist interpretation, whereas the orthodox-style Copenhagen interpretation is neutral.
 
  • Like
Likes Tendex
  • #449
DarMM said:
Show me such a construction for QFT.
Even so it is an alternate construction. The mathematics of QM does not involve such things, an alternate formalism incapable of replicating QFT and not known to replicate all of QM (as of 2019) does, but that's not QM.
The construction itself is Nelsonian stochastics. All it needs is to work mathematically is that the energy depends quadratically on the momentum variables. So, the mathematics of Nelsonian stochastics can be taken over to bosonic field theories in the same way as this can be done for Bohmian bosonic field theories, with the formulas given in

Bohm.D., Hiley, B.J., Kaloyerou, P.N. (1987). An ontological basis for the quantum theory, Phys. Reports 144(6), 321-375.

PeterDonis said:
Not for QM they don't. For example, consider the two propositions relating to an electron that has just passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction and has come out the "up" output:
(1) This electron has ##z## spin up.
(2) This electron has ##x## spin up.
#1 has a well-defined truth value, namely "true". #2 does not have a well-defined truth value at all.
Means, it is not an adequately defined proposition of QM.

Because the field of discourse consists of propositions, what you have to do is to find out the propositions of your theories of interest (the field may contain many, all those discussed in a particular discourse). If among these theories is some theory THV where the electron has a well-defined spin in every direction, when the discourse can contain the proposition "THV holds and this electron has ##x## spin up", and this has a well-defined truth value (namely in this case "false" because such a THV has to be false given the violation of the Bell inequalities.) Once in QM itself there are no such propositions about values not measured, the statement "This electron has ##x## spin up." is simply not part of the discourse of QM. The statements would have to refer to results of measurements. So, a more adequate formulation would be "if passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##x## direction the "up" output would come out".

If you use statements A = "if passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##x## direction the "up" output would come out", B = "if passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##y## direction the "up" output would come out", you already have well-defined truth values and can use standard Boolean algebra operations with them. You cannot test them both, thus, you cannot establish their truth-value by observation, but this is not required. You can gain incomplete knowledge about them and apply the rules of classical probability theory without any problem, you can derive internal contradictions of various sets of propositions and so on.
PeterDonis said:
Therefore no set of propositions that contains both #1 and #2 can define a Boolean algebra. But both propositions are part of the "field of discourse" of QM.
No. This is simply the error of "quantum logic": Inaccurate choices of propositions, using statements which, sloppily, could count as propositions in some interpretations making additional hypotheses but are not propositions in QM, with "and" and "or" operations sloppily defining other such non-propositions, so no wonder that the rules of classical logic are inapplicable.
 
  • #450
Elias1960 said:
Means, it is not an adequately defined proposition of QM.

Sure it is. I can measure the spin in the ##x## direction.

Elias1960 said:
a more adequate formulation would be "if passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##x## direction the "up" output would come out".

Which doesn't change the fact that this proposition does not have a well-defined truth value for an electron that has just come out of the "up" output of a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction.

Elias1960 said:
If you use statements A = "if passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##x## direction the "up" output would come out", B = "if passed through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##y## direction the "up" output would come out", you already have well-defined truth values and can use standard Boolean algebra operations with them.

Not for an electron that has just come out of the "up" output of a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction. See above.

Elias1960 said:
You cannot test them both, thus, you cannot establish their truth-value by observation, but this is not required.

Not required for what? Not required for QM, sure; but QM does not claim that there is a single Boolean algebra that captures all of these propositions. You are claiming that, so you can't wave your hands and say it's "not required" to test them both. Not being able to test them both is precisely what prevents there from being a single sample space.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, DarMM, RUTA and 2 others
  • #451
Elias1960 said:
The construction itself is Nelsonian stochastics. All it needs is to work mathematically is that the energy depends quadratically on the momentum variables. So, the mathematics of Nelsonian stochastics can be taken over to bosonic field theories in the same way as this can be done for Bohmian bosonic field theories, with the formulas given in

Bohm.D., Hiley, B.J., Kaloyerou, P.N. (1987). An ontological basis for the quantum theory
The cat is finally out of the bag: I'm a Nelsonian sympathiser, but stochastic mechanics, for all it does - and admittedly it does enormously much, including the full restoration of classical logic in physics - is de facto not standard quantum mechanics, i.e. not part of the canonical mathematical structure of QM as described within the literature and all textbooks: this description is interpretation-free in the sense of how this terminology is used in the foundations literature.

Now the question of whether the canonical description of QM is itself correct, while obviously important, is a completely separate issue to whether a faithfull description is being given of canonical QM: it seems obvious to me that you are arguing for the former and not the latter, while @DarMM is explicitly arguing for the latter.

In other words, it is you and not @DarMM who is involving their personal philosophy for the right reasons - i.e. a deeper constructive mathematical understanding and a restoration of logic - but at the wrong moment within this discussion. More directly, Smolin also explicitly points out in his latest book how the Nelsonian point of view while almost irresistible does not seem to be capable of being correct.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, weirdoguy and DarMM
  • #452
PeterDonis said:
Which doesn't change the fact that this proposition does not have a well-defined truth value for an electron that has just come out of the "up" output of a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction.
Yes. The information you have is insufficient to identify the truth value. So what? It does not mean that it does not have a truth value.
PeterDonis said:
Not required for what?
For the applicability of the classical propositional calculus, in particular, the applicability of Boolean logic, so that the set of propositions defines a Boolean algebra, the application of Stone's theorem to construct a unique sample space, and the logic of plausible reasoning - classical probability theory - on this space of elementary events.
PeterDonis said:
Not required for QM, sure; but QM does not claim that there is a single Boolean algebra that captures all of these propositions.
It is sufficient that any scientific discourse is based on applying classical logic on propositions about QM as well as about other theories. If you cannot talk about a theory you propose using the language of logical propositions with meaningful truth values, you simply don't have a well-defined theory.

This is my point all the time: The rules of logic (inclusive the logic of plausible reasoning) are part of the scientific method, they are theory-independent and beyond particular theories, and in particular not subject to empirical falsification.
PeterDonis said:
You are claiming that, so you can't wave your hands and say it's "not required" to test them both. Not being able to test them both is precisely what prevents there from being a single sample space.
No. There is no such requirement neither in classical logic nor in the logic of plausible reasoning.

A standard proceeding in a criminal investigation would be the evaluation of different possibilities. Some of them appear in conflict with the available data, all others give the conclusion that the accusation is correct. Is this sufficient, even if we cannot identify, given the available information, which of the many scenarios for the crime is the correct one, for a conviction? Yes, it is.

But the advocate of the accused would be happy to be able to apply quantum strangeness in the defense of his client. Once we cannot find out if his T-shirt was yellow or green, there is no single sample space for the colors of his T-shirt, so one cannot apply classical plausible reasoning, thus, one cannot prove that the accused has done it.

(Aside: The rules of scientific reasoning are open to criticism too. But if one proposes to reject the rules of scientific reasoning and to modify them, then one has to do this consistently, theory-independent, and reject the invalid rules of reasoning in everyday reasoning too. This is behind my examples regarding tobacco industry and that criminal case.)
 
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #453
Auto-Didact said:
The cat is finally out of the bag: I'm a Nelsonian sympathiser, but stochastic mechanics, for all it does - and admittedly it does enormously much, including the full restoration of classical logic in physics - is de facto not standard quantum mechanics, i.e. not part of the canonical mathematical structure of QM as described within the literature and all textbooks: this description is interpretation-free in the sense of how this terminology is used in the foundations literature.
I agree. The point being? Note the context where I have introduced it:
No, these are the metaphysical choices you have made by choosing your preferred interpretation of QM. You are aware that there exist other interpretations of QM which have a different view. A piece of mathematical machinery does nothing without your interpretational choices. Here, in particular, you make the assumption that that ##C^∗## structure is something fundamentally important, and not a nice accidental consequence of [the way it is interpreted in Nelsonian stochastics]
Auto-Didact said:
Now the question of whether the canonical description of QM is itself correct, while obviously important, is a completely separate issue to whether a faithfull description is being given of canonical QM: it seems obvious to me that you are arguing for the former and not the latter, while @DarMM is explicitly arguing for the latter.
What is the "canonical description of QM"? There is the minimal interpretation, which remains silent over such questions as if the ##C^∗## structure is something fundamentally important. Those who claim that the ##C^∗## structure is something fundamentally important support an interpretation beyond the minimal one and involve their personal QM philosophy. And naming this "canonical description of QM" (instead of giving it the appropriate name, like "Copenhagen interpretation" or whatever) could be even suspected to be an attempt to hide this. A description as "canonical" and "of QM" I can accept only for the minimal interpretation, and the claims I have questioned are obviously not part of the minimal interpretation.
Auto-Didact said:
More directly, Smolin also explicitly points out in his latest book how the Nelsonian point of view while almost irresistible does not seem to be capable of being correct.
Any open link to it? If it contains more than the standard arguments (necessity of preferred frame, the Pauli argument in favor of p-q symmetry, and Wallstrom), what is his point?
 
  • #454
atyy said:
It wasn't clear to me that you were referring to different sample spaces in each theory
I'm referring to the sample spaces each theory actually has.

atyy said:
Well, perhaps a point of error or maybe just not understanding your terminology. I have not understood till now why you say BM has a single sample space, but QM does not - to me neither have a single sample space in only the variables defined in Fine's theorem.
Bohmian Mechanics does have a single sample space for the variables for Fine's theorem. The variables can be modeled as random variables ##\Gamma_{E,M}(\lambda)##, often called Response functions in the Foundation literature. The difference is that they are contextual, i.e. arbitrary identity partitions ##M## appear.

atyy said:
Anyway, if you mean QM rejects decorrelating explanation, then I understand what you mean (and yes, I do agree with Wiseman). I would, however, disagree on terminology. I would say QM is neutral on the rejection of decorrelating explanation, and it is neutral on the general issue of having no single sample space in arbitrary variables.
I don't agree with this. The formalism itself does not have a single sample since it has a non-commutative C*-algebra. This isn't interpretational. The number of sample spaces is a mathematical fact.

Bohmian Mechanics is an alternate formalism and ultimately a different theory. As a different formalism different mathematical statements are true about it. It has a single sample space of the form:
$$\mathcal{H}\times Q^{\otimes n}$$
where ##Q## is some manifold (generally orbifold) of particle positions.

This simply is mathematically a very different set up. QM itself has no such Hilbert-Orbifold state space.

One can be neutral on which formalism is physically correct, but not on the mathematical facts of each formalism. And it is a mathematical fact that QM has multiple sample spaces. Nobody in the actual literature phrases this as or considers it as interpretational.
 
Last edited:
  • #455
BM interpretation making the same predictions (otherwise it wouldn't be a QM interpretation) also has multiple sample spaces for its predictions and that doesn't prevent it from having one sample space for the much bigger set of all possible outcomes. Having multiple sample spaces for predictive subsets is not equivalent to discard having a single sample space for a bigger set of elementary outcomes that can be used to conform the subsets that correspond to predictions.
Also clearly as one can check reading descriptions of different QM interpretations with the same predictions whether to reject locality, or counterfactuals or not is purely interpretational, not part of the formalism as falsely claimed by DarMM.
 

Similar threads

Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
69
Views
5K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
4
Views
2K
Replies
115
Views
8K
Back
Top