How do entanglement experiments benefit from QFT (over QM)?

In summary, the conversation discusses two important points: the first being the difference between QFT and quantum mechanics (QM) and the second being the role of QFT in analyzing entanglement experiments. QFT is a more comprehensive theory than QM, and while it is commonly used in quantum optics papers, it is not often referenced in experimental papers on entanglement. The main reason for this is that QFT is primarily used when dealing with particle-number changing processes, which are not relevant in most entanglement experiments. In addition, while QFT helps to understand how entanglement should not be explained, it does not provide a significant advantage in explaining entanglement itself, and discussions of entanglement often focus on photons due to
  • #316
Elias1960 said:
So, the abstract already contains appropriate (non-misleading) terms for this, "noncommutative measure theory" and "von Neumann algebras". What I criticize is not that mathematical structures which do not fulfill all axioms of probability theory are studied by those interested in such abstract mathematics, but that it is claimed that quantum theory somehow requires such a generalization of probability theory
Well it does. The title of the paper is "Quantum Probability Theory", the field is called quantum probability theory. The fact that this field uses noncommutative measure theory and von Neumann algebras is exactly the reflection of the fact that it is a generalization of probability theory which uses commutative measure theory and commutative von Neumann algebras.
i.e. the structures in quantum theory are generalizations of those in probability theory. It contains generalizations of results from probability theory (e.g. de Finetti's theorem) and so on. It is a generalization of probability theory.

Elias1960 said:
The reference, again,
Kochen, S., Specker, E.P. (1967). The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics, J. Math. Mech. 17(1), 59-87. They do it on page 63, as already mentioned.
This is just the construction generalized in the more modern ontological models framework which we know must be infinite dimensional as I mentioned above.

Again QM does not possesses a single sample space despite the fact that it can be embedded in an infinite dimensional sample space. Just as general solutions in General Relativity are not flat despite the fact that they can be embedded in a 231 dimensional Minkowski space.

Nobody would object to "Schwarszchild spacetime is curved" with "but it can be embedded in a 231 dimensional Minkowski spacetime!"
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, dextercioby and Auto-Didact
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #317
vanhees71 said:
I don't see, why a preparation procedure doesn't define an ensemble, because an ensemble does not depend on the assumption that all observables take determined value
Correct, but that's not the issue. The variables could all have indeterminate values, such as in a classical stochastic theory, but yet a preparation would still be an ensemble since there is one sample space.

QM doesn't have a single sample space, thus the preparations are not ensembles. It's that simple.
 
  • #318
Then, please, define what you mean by "sample space". A preparation procedure of a Ag-atom beam in the orignal SG experiment defines Ag atoms with properties specific enough to be interpretable within modern QT, and you can understand the outcome of measurements with independently chosen spin components to be measured. So why these Ag atoms, in your opinion, do not define an "ensemble", before also the to-be-measured observable is chosen? If this is the case, how can then quantum states have a well-defined operational meaning in the lab? Specifically, how then is it possible to describe all kinds of "delayed-choice experiments" successfully with QT?
 
  • #319
vanhees71 said:
Then, please, define what you mean by "sample space"
The standard definition from probability theory.

vanhees71 said:
If this is the case, how can then quantum states have a well-defined operational meaning in the lab? Specifically, how then is it possible to describe all kinds of "delayed-choice experiments" successfully with QT?
There's no real contradiction. The state doesn't define an ensemble doesn't mean the state has no meaning or that delayed-choice experiments cannot be described.
 
  • #320
Ok, here's the definition of Wikipedia:

In probability theory, the sample space (also called sample description space[1] or possibility space[2]) of an experiment or random trial is the set of all possible outcomes or results of that experiment.[3] A sample space is usually denoted using set notation, and the possible ordered outcomes are listed as elements in the set. It is common to refer to a sample space by the labels S, Ω, or U (for "universal set").

That's how I understood it too. But as I said, the quantum state refers to preparation procedures not the a "sample space" in this sense. The random experiment "measurement of some set of compatible observables" is of course only specified when this set of observables is chosen, but this choice is independent of the preparation procedure, and this is very important for the description of real-world experiments.
 
  • #321
vanhees71 said:
But as I said, the quantum state refers to preparation procedures not the a "sample space" in this sense
Precisely, but a preparation procedure in classical mechanics is identical with it.

Streater says the following:
The only difference is that, in quantum probability, there is more than one complete commuting set, and each gives a different sample space and probability: the statistical model is contextual
Also when discussing the EPR paper, the error is:
That is, they were arguing as if there were a sample space for the system

Perhaps you just mean ensemble in a looser sense like "a pile of stuff" rather than the formal sense used in statistics and probability theory?
 
  • Like
Likes kith and vanhees71
  • #322
The simplest way of phrasing it perhaps is that in a classical stochastic theory the outcomes, even though they are random, occur independently of the device. That is each observable attains a value (even if randomly driven) regardless of whether one measures or not. In quantum theory only the observable you actually measure has a value or outcome.

Thus the preparation does not prepare a bunch of systems which sample the outcome space in a manner that approximately replicates the relevant probability distribution since there are no outcomes without a device. To make the state into an ensemble we must specify the device which will define the outcomes and then the preparation can be considered to constitute an ensemble.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, Jimster41, kith and 1 other person
  • #323
Yes, sure. That's what's proven by all the Bell tests. I can live with the refinement to not call a state as defining an ensemble.
 
  • Like
Likes Auto-Didact and DarMM
  • #324
DarMM said:
Well it does. The title of the paper is "Quantum Probability Theory", the field is called quantum probability theory. The fact that this field uses noncommutative measure theory and von Neumann algebras is exactly the reflection of the fact that it is a generalization of probability theory which uses commutative measure theory and commutative von Neumann algebras.
It contains generalizations of results from probability theory (e.g. de Finetti's theorem) and so on. It is a generalization of probability theory.
This is as reasonable as to name, say, complex numbers "generalized probabilities". It does not generalize them at all except in a purely mathematical sense but describes very different things.

That some mathematical ideas for proofs may be taken over is an irrelevant mathematical accident, similar to that one can also add complex numbers.

No doubt that from a mathematical point of view it is a generalization of probability theory. This generalization is, nonetheless, uninteresting for anything related to probabilities in the real world.
DarMM said:
This is just the construction generalized in the more modern ontological models framework which we know must be infinite dimensional as I mentioned above.
Whatever, it exists and is constructed in a quite trivial way. I have not claimed it has to be finite-dimensional.
DarMM said:
Again QM does not possesses a single sample space despite the fact that it can be embedded in an infinite dimensional sample space.
There is nothing in Kolmogorovian probability theory which requires that all probability distributions should be part of a given theory. So, once there exist an embedding of the QM probability distributions into the Kolmogorovian probability distribution defined on some single sample space, it is standard probability theory.
DarMM said:
Just as general solutions in General Relativity are not flat despite the fact that they can be embedded in a 231 dimensional Minkowski space.
Nice try but not appropriate. There is no essential property of probability distributions which is lost or gained by an embedding. If the states we can prepare are only those of a subset of quantum equilibrium states, this is not fine but changes nothing in the rules of Kolmogorovian probability theory.
 
  • #325
Elias1960 said:
Nice try but not appropriate. There is no essential property of probability distributions which is lost or gained by an embedding. If the states we can prepare are only those of a subset of quantum equilibrium states, this is not fine but changes nothing in the rules of Kolmogorovian probability theory.
Elias1960 said:
Whatever, it exists and is constructed in a quite trivial way. I have not claimed it has to be finite-dimensional.
There's no essential properties of Schwarzschild space gained or lost by its embedding either.
Quantum Theory itself does not have a single sample space. That is a fact.

That it can be embedded in an infinite dimensional sample space containing variables nobody has ever witnessed negates this as much as the fact that Schwarzschild spacetime can be embedded in a 231 dimensional Minkowski spacetime that nobody has evidence of.

And just like to replicate Schwarzschild spacetime you'd have to posit we're confined to a hypersurface of this massive Minkowski space, to replicate QM you have to assume we're confined epistimically in this infinite-dimensional sample space.

I don't really know what is the purpose in pointing this out.

Elias1960 said:
This is as reasonable as to name, say, complex numbers "generalized probabilities". It does not generalize them at all except in a purely mathematical sense but describes very different things.

That some mathematical ideas for proofs may be taken over is an irrelevant mathematical accident, similar to that one can also add complex numbers.

No doubt that from a mathematical point of view it is a generalization of probability theory. This generalization is, nonetheless, uninteresting for anything related to probabilities in the real world.
Well we have every expert on the topic calling it quantum probability. With quotes like:
Streater Lost Causes p.38 said:
it is natural to interpret quantum mechanics as a generalization of classical probability
Stephen Summers in Quantum Probability Theory said:
This should help the reader in Section 4 to recognize more readily the probability theory inherent in the theory of normal states on von Neumann algebras, which is the setting of noncommutative probability theory. Classical probability theory finds its place there in as the special case where the von Neumann algebra is abelian. Nonrelativistic quantum mechanics is then understood in Section 5 as the special case where the von Neumann algebra is a nonabelian type I algebra.
Scott Aaronson in Quantum Computing since Democritus said:
Quantum mechanics is a beautiful generalization of the laws of probability
Somehow they are all wrong though and you are right for reasons you cannot articulate. In the spirit of probability theory I will let others assign their own priors to this belief as I don't have the energy to debate a field being correctly named and classified by its own experts.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes mattt, weirdoguy and Auto-Didact
  • #326
Elias1960 said:
No doubt that from a mathematical point of view it is a generalization of probability theory. This generalization is, nonetheless, uninteresting for anything related to probabilities in the real world.
Surely, you must be joking? There are tonnes of generalizations of the concept of chance which have mathematical formulations and/or applications and yet cannot be treated, not even in principle, as a form of Kolmogorovian probability theory (KPT).

In fact, it is both an unjustified reductionism to treat chance as probability as well as a frequently made category error to treat the concept of probability as if it were de facto described by KPT. For example, QT itself is a theory which has concerned itself with negative probabilities: this already directly violates Kolmogorov's axioms.

The fact that PT has been axiomatized, while impressive, is a grossly exaggerated achievement. In actuality, KPT is only a theory of probability which is generally prematurely seen as the theory of probability, in much the same way that Newtonian mechanics is a theory of mechanics which was erroneously seen as the theory of mechanics.

In other words, the assumed uniqueness of KPT to be capable of describing the concept of chance is not merely unjustified, but unjustifiable because it has actually been disproven mathematically by the discovery or invention of alternate mathematical frameworks which specifically subsume KPT as a certain idealized limiting case.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, vanhees71 and weirdoguy
  • #327
Auto-Didact said:
Surely, you must be joking? There are tonnes of generalizations of the concept of chance which have mathematical formulations and/or applications and yet cannot be treated, not even in principle, as a form of Kolmogorovian probability theory (KPT).
That there are tons of "generalizations" in the mathematical sense is a triviality. Remove whatever axiom you do not like most, and you have a generalization in the mathematical sense.
Auto-Didact said:
In fact, it is both an unjustified reductionism to treat chance as probability as well as a frequently made category error to treat the concept of probability as if it were de facto described by KPT. For example, QT itself is a theory which has concerned itself with negative probabilities: this already directly violates Kolmogorov's axioms.
Nice example - but it only shows that the interpretations which treat those negative things as probabilities are nonsense.
Auto-Didact said:
The fact that PT has been axiomatized, while impressive, is a grossly exaggerated achievement. In actuality, KPT is only a theory of probability which is generally prematurely seen as the theory of probability, in much the same way that Newtonian mechanics is a theory of mechanics which was erroneously seen as the theory of mechanics.
The point is not that it has been axiomatized. The point is the particular axiomatization given by Cox and Jaynes of the logic of plausible reasoning. To generalize it means, essentially, to accept forms of plausible reasoning so that using different ways to argue would lead to different results, in other words, it would allow inconsistent reasoning.
Auto-Didact said:
In other words, the assumed uniqueness of KPT to be capable of describing the concept of chance is not merely unjustified, but unjustifiable because it has actually been disproven mathematically by the discovery or invention of alternate mathematical frameworks which specifically subsume KPT as a certain idealized limiting case.
I do not care about a "concept of chance", but about the rules of consistent plausible reasoning.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes weirdoguy
  • #328
DarMM said:
There's no essential properties of Schwarzschild space gained or lost by its embedding either.
There are. Everything which mentions curvature is, because curvature is different, is even a completely different mathematical object, on the Schwarzschild space and on the higher dimensional space where you have embedded it.
DarMM said:
Quantum Theory itself does not have a single sample space. That is a fact.
Ok, if you repeat falsehoods even after you have been confronted with an explicit (and simple) construction of a counterexample, I cannot do anything about it. Feel free to continue to believe this. I give up.
DarMM said:
And just like to replicate Schwarzschild spacetime you'd have to posit we're confined to a hypersurface of this massive Minkowski space, to replicate QM you have to assume we're confined epistimically in this infinite-dimensional sample space.
A subset of probability distributions over a given sample space remains to be a set of probability distributions over this sample space.
DarMM said:
Well we have every expert on the topic calling it quantum probability. ...
Somehow they are all wrong though and you are right for reasons you cannot articulate.
One can interpret those quotes as referring to the purely mathematical "generalizations", which one can simply obtain by taking away some axioms.

But these mathematical generalizations do not define a reasonable set of rules of plausible reasoning, in the same way as lattice theory, which has been named "quantum logic", does not define a reasonable replacement of the rules of logic.

As long as you simply take away some axioms, you simply reduce your ability to derive something. If you add, instead, some modification of the axiom, you will end in inconsistent nonsense. Not because the new set of axioms has internal contradictions (the abstract set of axioms may have some nontrivial models) but because these new axioms are not laws of reasoning.

I have articulated the reasons, in particular by the reference to the explicit construction of that sample space which you claim does not exist.

But, aside, Streater is indeed a lost cause. To show this, it is sufficient to quote the begin of his section about Bohmian mechanics:
This subject was assessed by the NSF of the USA as follows [Cushing, J. T.,
review of [28]] “. . . The causal interpretation [of Bohm] is inconsistent with
experiments which test Bell’s inequalities. Consequently . . . funding . . . a re-
search programme in this area would be unwise”. I agree with this recommen-
dation.
So, feel free to support any argument he gives yourself, but as some sort of reference to scientific authority, he is completely worthless.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes weirdoguy
  • #329
Elias1960 said:
Ok, if you repeat falsehoods even after you have been confronted with an explicit (and simple) construction of a counterexample, I cannot do anything about it. Feel free to continue to believe this. I give up.
This will be my last post on this.

That's not a counter-example. You've shown that the objects in quantum theory can be embedded in an infinite dimensional object not in quantum theory.

A Gelfand homomorphism is a map that takes C*-algebra elements and maps them to functions over a manifold. This manifold is then the sample space.
Quantum theory's observable algebra lacks a Gelfand homomorphism that covers all of the algebra. Thus it does not have one sample space. The end.

What you are doing is finding an algebra with infinite degrees of freedom with the quantum algebra embedded as a subset. Note though it's not a subalgebra, the embedding destroys some algebraic properties. Then the fact that this much larger algebra, with observables never seen in a lab, has one sample space you are taking as implying QM has one sample space.

This simply doesn't make any sense. As I said it's like embedding every spacetime from General Relativity in 231-D Minkowski and declaring GR deals with flat spaces.

In fact it is worse, since the generalized Nash's embedding theorem tells us all properties of those manifolds are preserved, e.g. the curvature is retained as extrinsic curvature in the surrounding space. Where as the embedding destroys the algebraic relations in the quantum algebra.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, Auto-Didact and Tendex
  • #330
I'd not say QT is a generalization of probability theory but it's an extension to provide a scheme to predict concrete probability measures for the outcome of measurements on physical systems. As I understand it from the many discussions in this forum, the most general mathematical scheme to do this is standard QT (with Born's rule as definition of the meaning of states, i.e., the statistical operator of the system) together with a POVM. A special case are the "complete measurements" a la von Neumann projector-valued measures (PVM). These schemes are applicable in practice for "small systems" like collisions of two particles producing a plethora of new particles at the LHC, quantum-optics experiments with a few photons and charged particles, few-body systems like atomic nuclei, atoms, molecules etc.

I don't think that this is sufficient though. Another very important ingredient in the realm many-body theory is the application of information theory, i.e., the maximum-entropy principle to QT, which provides another technique to postulate the (initial) statistical operators for a given situation in a sufficiently coarse-grained sense. Only with this quantum-statistical approaches you are able to close the gap between the microscopic description, which in practice is possible only for few-body systems, and the macroscopic matter, with which we deal in everyday life, including the measurement devices in the lab and which we describe by (semi-)classical physics.
 
  • #331
vanhees71 said:
I'd not say QT is a generalization of probability theory but it's an extension
Perhaps you mean something subtle by "extension" vs "generalization", but standard terminology is that it is. See Streater's book or the paper by Summers I gave above.

vanhees71 said:
I don't think that this is sufficient though. Another very important ingredient in the realm many-body theory is the application of information theory, i.e., the maximum-entropy principle to QT
MaxEnt is a technique in probability theory. As you said for finding the right distribution (classical case) or the right statistical operator (quantum case).
So the formalism is "just" POVMS, states on them and a choice of unitary operators. However you might need techniques for choosing the right state, evolution operator, POVM, etc. That doesn't negate that they constitute the formalism however.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #332
My lay-man's view of probability theory is that it provides a mathematical axiomatic system, like e.g., Kolmogorov's. That system of axioms, however just gives a framework and does not define the concrete probabilities. That's of course a feature, since it should have this flexibility.

The art of the application of this framework to real-world problems is to find successful probabilistic descriptions of the real-world situations, and QT provides one framework for it.

I think the axiomatic foundation of probability theory is particularly important to get a complete understanding of QT, precisely for the reason of our current discussion: It gives a clear and "non-esoteric" meaning of the "contextuality issue", i.e., indeed to define probabilities making sense as described by the (Kolmogorov) axioms you have to define both the state (operationally defined as a preparation procedure) and the measured observables (operationally defined as some measurement procedure).

E.g., at the LHC or RHIC one meaures "dileptons" in heavy-ion collisions. The preparation procedure is to provide two beams of lead or gold nuclei with quite well-defined momentum (and thus also energy) and let them collide at specific places. I've never seen this being described as a POVM, and the accelerator physicists do very well with considering classical descriptions of the bunches (either as poin particles or in the case of larger "space-charge densities" hydrodynamics). There are many measurements done to get the dilepton spectra (i.e., the invariant-mass, transverse-momentum and rapidity spectra of electron-positron and muon-antimuon pairs). Among them are ring-imaging Cerenkov detectors: The electrons enter some material, and with appropriate photon detectors one reconstructs the rings from the "Cerenkov cones". Of course, only these two elements together, i.e., the preparation procedure and the measurment device define the complete "random experiment" in the sense of the Kolmogorov axioms.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114 and DarMM
  • #333
DarMM said:
This will be my last post on this.

That's not a counter-example. You've shown that the objects in quantum theory can be embedded in an infinite dimensional object not in quantum theory.

A Gelfand homomorphism is a map that takes C*-algebra elements and maps them to functions over a manifold. This manifold is then the sample space.
Quantum theory's observable algebra lacks a Gelfand homomorphism that covers all of the algebra. Thus it does not have one sample space. The end.

What you are doing is finding an algebra with infinite degrees of freedom with the quantum algebra embedded as a subset. Note though it's not a subalgebra, the embedding destroys some algebraic properties. Then the fact that this much larger algebra, with observables never seen in a lab, has one sample space you are taking as implying QM has one sample space.
In a sense I think you and Elias1960 are actually agreeing, don't let his argumentative style drag you. Certainly quantum probability is formally inserted in a generalization-or extension as vanhees put it, it doesn't make much difference without a clear definition- from classic probability(and that much was admitted "mathematically" by Elias1960) but it is also true that the generalization is (quite loosely in a way but that is the standard in physical theories, especially in quantum field theory where a rigorous mathematization is pendent) at the moment set in an infinite dimensional space that allows to allude to "one sample space" formally, even if it sounds morally wrong in physical terms.

The alternative, to claim that quantum theory has a formalism with its own probability to the exclusion of the classical one(rather than a formalism flexible enough to incorporate both without fatal contradictions which is the role of infinite dimensions here-the whole purpose of functional analysis in quantum theory I'd say ) amounts to saying that quantum theory has a logic of its own, with failing distributive laws for its propositions, and this would make impossible the necessary contact the theory has to make with classical physics, banning all semiclassical approaches or even the use of measurements results like physical constants values.

So IMO even if it is tempting and even morally acceptable in a way to claim that there is no longer a single sample space, at the moment , formally at least, it seems like there is.
 
  • #334
vanhees71 said:
My lay-man's view of probability theory is that it provides a mathematical axiomatic system, like e.g., Kolmogorov's. That system of axioms, however just gives a framework and does not define the concrete probabilities
Let me say it this way. Absolutely the general framework doesn't give you the specific probabilities. However the general framework does specify how probabilities can possibly "mesh" together, i.e. it gives rules for how to relate sets of probabilties that hold regardless of what specific values they have. Kolmogorov's theory (i.e. classical probability) leads to a very specific set of meshing rules, one example being the Total Law of Probability.

It then turns out experimentally that some real world probabilities, such as those found in atomic or sub-atomic scale experiments, do not obey those meshing rules. Thus we need a more general theory of how probabilities interrelate than those found in Kolmogorov/classical probability. That generalization is quantum probability theory.

vanhees71 said:
The preparation procedure is to provide two beams of lead or gold nuclei with quite well-defined momentum (and thus also energy) and let them collide at specific places. I've never seen this being described as a POVM
One doesn't always need a POVM. In many cases a PVM will do. POVMs are simply the most general notion.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt
  • #335
Tendex said:
but it is also true that the generalization is at the moment set in an infinite dimensional space
From Hardy's infinite ontological baggage theorem it must always be infinite dimensional, not just that at the moment that's the only way we can do it.

Tendex said:
this would make impossible the necessary contact the theory has to make with classical physics
No because macroscopic observables end up commuting (for various reasons such as decoherence, Pitwosky's lack of entanglement witnesses, etc), which means they have classical statistics and thus one recovers classical physics. Since quantum probability is more general than classical probability it can contain classical probability.

Observables in general don't live in a single sample space, but macroscopic observables do. That's all there is to it.

Tendex said:
So IMO even if it is tempting and even morally acceptable in a way to claim that there is no longer a single sample space, at the moment , formally at least, it seems like there is
No. QM does not have a single sample space. That is a fact of the formalism due to it not having a Gelfand homomorphism that covers the entire algebra.
"Formally" there is an infinite dimensional sample space of an alternate theory that is not QM where the QM algebra appears as a subset (not subalgebra crucially).
If we were to use your language we would have to say:
"So IMO even if it is tempting and even morally acceptable in a way to claim that in General Relativity spacetime is not flat, at the moment , formally at least, it seems like it is flat"

As I said this entire line of discussion is like saying we should acknowledge that all spacetimes in General Relativity can be embedded in a 231-D Minkowski spacetime and for that reason "strictly speaking" spacetime is not curved. Nobody would do this as:
  1. In order to explain our observations you have to come up with a restriction, i.e. for some reason we are confined to a 4D hypersurface. Just as in such an infinite dimensional sample space replacing QM we are confined epistemically
  2. It's not what General Relativity says, but what an alternate unevidenced Special Relativity says. Exactly so a single space is mathematically not what QM says provably, but what an alternate unevidenced classical probabilistic theory says.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt, Auto-Didact, weirdoguy and 1 other person
  • #336
DarMM said:
From Hardy's infinite ontological baggage theorem it must always be infinite dimensional, not just that at the moment that's the only way we can do it.No because macroscopic observables end up commuting (for various reasons such as decoherence, Pitwosky's lack of entanglement witnesses, etc), which means they have classical statistics and thus one recovers classical physics. Since quantum probability is more general than classical probability it can contain classical probability.

Observables in general don't live in a single sample space, but macroscopic observables do. That's all there is to it.No. QM does not have a single sample space. That is a fact of the formalism due to it not having a Gelfand homomorphism that covers the entire algebra.
"Formally" there is an infinite dimensional sample space of an alternate theory that is not QM where the QM algebra appears as a subset (not subalgebra crucially).
If we were to use your language we would have to say:
"So IMO even if it is tempting and even morally acceptable in a way to claim that in General Relativity spacetime is not flat, at the moment , formally at least, it seems like it is flat"

As I said this entire line of discussion is like saying we should acknowledge that all spacetimes in General Relativity can be embedded in a 231-D Minkowski spacetime and for that reason "strictly speaking" spacetime is not curved. Nobody would do this as:
  1. In order to explain our observations you have to come up with a restriction, i.e. for some reason we are confined to a 4D hypersurface. Just as in such an infinite dimensional sample space replacing QM we are confined epistemically
  2. It's not what General Relativity says, but what an alternate unevidenced Special Relativity says. Exactly so a single space is mathematically not what QM says provably, but what an alternate unevidenced classical probabilistic theory says.
What is that alternate theory that is not quantum theory you refer to?
 
  • #337
Tendex said:
What is that alternate theory that is not quantum theory you refer to?
What ever retrocausal or nonlocal hidden variable theory is giving the infinitely large sample space.
 
  • #338
DarMM said:
What ever retrocausal or nonlocal hidden variable theory is giving the infinitely large sample space.
Ok, that's regular QM, only you are stressing an specific interpretation to describe it.
 
  • #339
Tendex said:
Ok, that's regular QM, only you are stressing an specific interpretation to describe it.
No, they have a completely different mathematical structure and are in fact different theories. Regular QM mathematically does not have a single infinite dimensional sample space.

I don't know how you can claim this is regular QM. Show me mathematically the infinite dimensional contextual single sample in QM. You will not be able to because it doesn't have one. The observable algebra is of such a form that there isn't a single Gelfand homomorphism for it, thus it is impossible. Mathematically impossible. This has nothing to do with interpretations. The algebra in QM does not have a single sample space.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes mattt and weirdoguy
  • #340
DarMM said:
No, they have a completely different mathematical structure and are in fact different theories. Regular QM mathematically does not have a single infinite dimensional sample space.

I don't now how you can claim this is regular QM. Show me mathematically the infinite dimensional contextual single sample in QM. You will not be able to because it doesn't have one. The observable algebra is of such a form that there isn't a single Gelfand homomorphism for it, thus it is impossible. Mathematically impossible. This has nothing to do with interpretations. The algebra in QM does not have a single sample space.
So you are then restricting quantum theory to the algebra of observables?Ok, but hadn't you said that the theory includes the macroscpic observables(measurements) and the classical probability?
 
  • #341
Tendex said:
So you are then restricting quantum theory to the algebra of observables?
I'm not restricting. The algebra of observables and states upon it constitutes the kinematics of quantum theory. What am I leaving out? There is no restriction.

Tendex said:
Ok, but hadn't you said that the theory includes the macroscpic observables(measurements) and the classical probability?
Yes I have. Macroscopic observables are a subset of the observable algebra which all commute and thus this subalgebra has classical probability.

This shows up in many places in Quantum Theory where the observable for electric charge for example has only classical probability. Subsets of the observable algebra can have classical probability. Electric charge observables are one example, macroscopic observables are another.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and Jimster41
  • #342
DarMM said:
I'm not restricting. The algebra of observables and states upon it constitutes the kinematics of quantum theory. What am I leaving out? There is no restriction.Yes I have. Macroscopic observables are a subset of the observable algebra which all commute and thus this subalgebra has classical probability.

This shows up in many places in Quantum Theory where the observable for electric charge for example has only classical probability. Subsets of the observable algebra can have classical probability. Electric charge observables are one example, macroscopic observables are another.
So including such measurements plus the reasonable assumption that they don't influence each other in a faster than light way seems to me that always should allow to a formalism that tries to meet these premises(acknowledging that this formalism hasn't been rigorously found yet as I commented previously) to abstract to a simple sample space the macroscopic measurements.
This notwithstanding that one is of course (given all that you have also explained) always free to use more than one sample space in the description of a certain quantum experiment or lab setting.

I think your examples using GR are not useful here as everybody knows GR is a classical theory, perhaps if we had a quantum gravity theory they could apply but it's not the case.
 
  • #343
Tendex said:
So including such measurements plus the reasonable assumption that they don't influence each other in a faster than light way
What measurements are we including here?

Tendex said:
I think your examples using GR are not useful here as everybody knows GR is a classical theory
You're missing the point of the analogy. It's not about whether GR is classical or not or whether people know that. The classicality of GR is beside the point.

The point is that all of GR's manifolds can be embedded in the Minkowski space of a much higher dimensional Special Relativity. Thus we can recast GR as a subset of a different theory with far more degrees of freedom with a highly unnatural restriction. Thus it is for QM and these single sample space theories. Both can be recast as a subset of a larger theory with a highly unnatural restriction. In both cases the larger theory, in addition to the subset that replicates QM/GR, has elements that have never experimentally been confirmed.

Thus in both cases there is no reason to cast doubt on the statements in the actual theory such as "there is more than one sample space" or "spacetime is curved".
 
  • #344
DarMM said:
What measurements are we including here?You're missing the point of the analogy. It's not about whether GR is classical or not or whether people know that. The classicality of GR is beside the point.

The point is that all of GR's manifolds can be embedded in the Minkowski space of a much higher dimensional Special Relativity. Thus we can recast GR as a subset of a different theory with far more degrees of freedom with a highly unnatural restriction. Thus it is for QM and these single sample space theories. Both can be recast as a subset of a larger theory with a highly unnatural restriction. In both cases the larger theory, in addition to the subset that replicates QM/GR, has elements that have never experimentally been confirmed.

Thus in both cases there is no reason to cast doubt on the statements in the actual theory such as "there is more than one sample space" or "spacetime is curved".
Oh, but I'm not casting doubt on those statements, I'm saying that functional analysis allows us to make them compatible with the statement of allowing one sample space, unless one is rejecting classical mathematical logic as the basis of quantum theory which I don't think you are doing.
As for GR, you have actually people like Kip Thorne and actually all particle physicists I know making compatible the idea of curvature and " flatness" of the infinite dimensional space one needs (to have general covariance anyway) and it is of course never to exclusion of curvature or multiple sample spaces in this case, but it also allows the abstraction to define one sample space to the extent that macroscopic local measurements is all that we have access to in physics and assuming no ftl and local gauge they are at some level random in the classical sense of approximately equal likeliness.
 
  • #345
Tendex said:
I'm saying that functional analysis allows us to make them compatible with the statement of allowing one sample space
Only with an artificial restriction and also it's a contextual sample space containing an infinite number of degrees of freedom nobody has ever observed. Why is this even being discussed?

Quantum Theory does not have a single sample, that is a mathematical fact. I have given Streater and Summers as two experts in the area who state this. If you disagree show me a construction of a single sample space that does not postulate an infinite number of observables unconfirmed by actual observations.

Tendex said:
As for GR, you have actually people like Kip Thorne and actually all particle physicists I know making compatible the idea of curvature and " flatness" of the infinite dimensional space one needs (to have general covariance anyway) and it is of course never to exclusion of curvature or multiple sample spaces in this case, but it also allows the abstraction to define one sample space to the extent that macroscopic local measurements is all that we have access to in physics and assuming no ftl and local gauge they are at some level random in the classical sense of approximately equal likeliness.
Show me this construction by Kip Thorne. I've never seen it.
 
  • #346
DarMM said:
Only with an artificial restriction and also it's a contextual sample space containing an infinite number of degrees of freedom nobody has ever observed. Why is this even being discussed?

Quantum Theory does not have a single sample, that is a mathematical fact. I have given Streater and Summers as two experts in the area who state this. If you disagree show me a construction of a single sample space that does not postulate an infinite number of observables unconfirmed by actual observations.


Show me this construction by Kip Thorne. I've never seen it.
Noone has ever observed infinite dimensions for that matter. Only an infinity of observations outside physics can confirm an infinite number of dof but if we are talking about the mathematics that support the physics you would have ask me also for evidence of the elements of infinite sets that are used in quantum theory for your demand to make sense.

But you have not explained how all equiprobable macroscopic local measurements(the only ones possible) in the sense of not influencing each other ftl at spacelike separation can't use infinite dimensional space(at the very base of the theory) to form a sample space.
 
  • #347
If I understand it right, what @DarMM refers to is the fact that, in contradistinction of classical (statistical) physics, in QT the sample space "all possible observables on the system" does not make sense, i.e., there are no states (pure or mixed) for which all observables take predetermined, yet maybe unknown, values. That's not only a mathematical fact about QT but seems to be pretty sure to be an empirical fact too, as the many Bell tests, all of which confirming QT rather than any possible local deterministic hidden-variable model, show!
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114 and DarMM
  • #348
Tendex said:
Noone has ever observed infinite dimensions for that matter. Only an infinity of observations outside physics can confirm an infinite number of dof but if we are talking about the mathematics that support the physics you would have ask me also for evidence of the elements of infinite sets that are used in quantum theory for your demand to make sense.
I'm not talking about infinite spatial dimensions. You don't even need to make an infinity of observations. I'm talking about a mathematical fact of the theory. Show me a single sample space that doesn't need to postulate an infinite number of additional degrees of freedom.

The resulting sample space has observables far more general than those in quantum theory. Not even a finite subset of these have been seen. Not even one of them has been seen.

I'll be frank, I don't think you really understand the single sample hidden variable theories construct and you are confusing several concepts. Have you gone through Hardy's infinite ontological baggage theorem? If not I'd read up about and go through the prove.

Tendex said:
But you have not explained how all equiprobable macroscopic local measurements(the only ones possible) in the sense of not influencing each other ftl at spacelike separation can't use infinite dimensional space(at the very base of the theory) to form a sample space.
"At the very base of the theory"? What does this mean?
You do realize that such an infinite dimensional sample space contains several observables that don't correspond to anything we've ever seen right?
 
  • #349
vanhees71 said:
If I understand it right, what @DarMM refers to is the fact that, in contradistinction of classical (statistical) physics, in QT the sample space "all possible observables on the system" does not make sense, i.e., there are no states (pure or mixed) for which all observables take predetermined, yet maybe unknown, values. That's not only a mathematical fact about QT but seems to be pretty sure to be an empirical fact too, as the many Bell tests, all of which confirming QT rather than any possible local deterministic hidden-variable model, show!
Precisely the part you have in bold.

To restore the idea of a sample space for all possible observables of the system we have to postulate an infinite number of degrees of freedom nobody has ever seen in a lab, that's basically what Hardy's theorem says. So sure you can make such an infinite dimensional sample space, but who cares that you can do this, none of those things have been seen in a lab.

It's exactly like the fact that "mathematically" any spacetime in GR can be embedded in a 231-D Minkowski background. Who cares? We have no evidence of those additional 227 dimensions.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and vanhees71
  • #350
Indeed, isn't this the most general surprising, for many physicists of the first "quantum generation" even disturbing, discovery of QT to begin with: No matter how accurately you may be able to prepare a system in (and the most "accurate" states possible are just the pure states, i.e., ##\hat{\rho}## is a projection operator) almost all observables do not take determined values but only a set of compatible observables (and functions thereof)?

That's the "danger" of getting involved with the natural sciences: It may happen that your learn something completely new about the natural world, as far as objective facts about it are concerned, that contradict worldviews that seemed very much confirmed by "common sense"! I think, nowadays most physicists are not disturbed anymore by this big surprised, simply because they are used to it by just learning the most recent physical worldview. I think it's save to say that any standard curriculum in physics on any level aims at to provide an understanding to some degree of modern quantum theory as the most comprehensive scientific world view we have today, and only philosophers still have some quibbles with it.

It's even getting further: These very foundational issues, some decades only present in gedanken experiments, become the standard not only in the (quantum optician's) lab but become part of engineering today. It's even dubbed the "2nd quantum revolution" in the popular press, i.e., the development of technology based on the "very disturbing quantum weirdness" of the founding father, using entanglement in practical applications, which may become soon everyday tools as today are computers, mobile phones and all that (realizing also fundamental physics of the 19th and 20th century like electromagnetism (electrics in each household) and quantum mechanics (semiconductor electronics in our beloved cell phones, tablets, and PCs of all kinds). One example that's already realized (though not yet in common use) is "quantum cryptography" (recently used for save communication between Austria and China via satellite communication). I also guess that "quantum computers" become also realized pretty soon though it may take still some time until I can buy my first quantum-personal computer to put on my desk ;-))).
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and DarMM

Similar threads

Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
69
Views
5K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
4
Views
2K
Replies
115
Views
8K
Back
Top