Incompleteness of Griffiths' consistent histories interpretation

In summary: Everett interpretation" was not considered due to the fact that it would have required "erasing the history of the interpretation" (to paraphrase Saunders).This is the principle of Liberty: the physicist can use whatever framework he chooses when describing a system.This is a nice principle, but it raises the question whether it would not be more straightforward to require only ##\operatorname{Re}D(\alpha,\beta)=0## for all ##\alpha\neq \beta##, which would be enough to ensure that applicability of classical logic and probability theory within a single framework.This is not done, because of the observation by Lajos Diós that the (canonical)
  • #1
gentzen
Science Advisor
Gold Member
940
747
Robert Griffiths version of consistent histories can be presented as a quantum logic, which is "intentionally" incomplete as an interpretation of QM. The advantage is that one can just require the exact decoherence condition ##D(\alpha,\beta)=0## for all ##\alpha\neq \beta## (with the decoherence functional ##D(\alpha,\beta)=Tr[K^\dagger(Y^\alpha)K(Y^\beta)]##). Then one doesn't need to worry about appropriate approximate forms of it. And of course, one doesn't need to invoke decoherence for the existence of approximately consistent quasi-classical frameworks, and instead just invokes the principle of Liberty:
This is the principle of Liberty: the physicist can use whatever framework he chooses when describing a system

However, this raises the question whether it would not be more straightforward to require only ##\operatorname{Re}D(\alpha,\beta)=0## for all ##\alpha\neq \beta##, which would be enough to ensure that applicability of classical logic and probability theory within a single framework. This is not done, because of the observation by Lajos Diós that the (canonical) composition of two statistically independent quantum systems ##A## and ##B## would not necessarily satisfy that condition (for given frameworks for ##A## and ##B## satisfying that condition). But the composition of such statistically independent quantum systems is not otherwise discussed in any substantial way in typical presentations of consistent histories.

Doesn't this make consistent histories even more incomplete? If composition of statistically independent quantum systems is important enough to justify using the stronger consistency condition, then it should also be important enough to warrant some substantial discussions of their role in that quantum logic.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
gentzen said:
Robert Griffiths version of consistent histories can be presented as a quantum logic, which is "intentionally" incomplete as an interpretation of QM.
In what sense is it "intentionally" incomplete?
 
  • #3
Demystifier said:
In what sense is it "intentionally" incomplete?
With respect to Robert Griffiths, the incompleteness is "intentional" in the way that he responds to criticism and misunderstandings:
As is often the case with new ideas, the histories approach was subject to serious criticisms by (among others) d’Espagnat [20, 21], Dowker and Kent [22], Kent [23–25], and Bassi and Ghirardi [26, 27], during the decade and a half that followed the original publications. Responses were published in [28–31]; in some cases a further reply to the response will be found immediately after the response. While these criticisms were (in the author’s opinion) largely based upon misunderstandings of the histories program, they had the good effect of leading to a better and clearer formulation of its basic concepts. Vigorous scientific debate is often beneficial in this way, though it becomes ineffective if criticisms are cited while responses thereto are ignored.

Those misunderstandings start much earlier than stuff where he himself admits: "the task is still incomplete". Therefore it makes sense for him to focus on the basics (and give up on wishful thinking of how one day the histories program might get completed):
A lack of clarity on the part of the advocates of the histories approach during its first ten or fifteen years contributed to the misunderstanding, but by now these earlier problems have been cleared up. It is hoped that the present paper, supplementing the detailed exposition found in CQT, may serve to further understanding of an approach to quantum foundations that deserves careful attention.
 
  • #4
Is your answer to my question "intentionally" incomplete? :oldbiggrin:
 
  • #5
Demystifier said:
Is your answer to my question "intentionally" incomplete? :oldbiggrin:
Of course, you are joking a bit. I don't want to put too many words into Griffiths mouth. Not sure what I should write. The misunderstandings and "misuses" to which Griffiths had to react are "breathtaking" in a certain sense. As a typical example, Simon Saunders writes
The goal was once again a one-world interpretation of quantum mechanics. But for that, fairly obviously, the history space had to be fixed once and for all. It was clear from the beginning that there were many consistent history spaces for a fixed initial state and Hamiltonian—which one should we choose? But it was thought that ...
But this difficulty does not apply to the marriage of decoherence theory in the more general sense with the consistent histories formalism, as carried through by Gell-Mann and Hartle and J.J. Halliwell ... histories in the latter sense are robustly defined. But decoherence (and the consistency condition) obtained in this way is never exact. ...
It is otherwise if decoherent histories theory is in service of the Everett interpretation - defining, among other things, the preferred basis. In that case it hardly matters if, for some states and regimes, decohering histories are simply absent altogether: ...
It is a complete misunderstanding that the "histories space would have to be fixed once and for all", or that anybody ever "though that ..." this could be achieved in some ridiculously misguided way. The trouble how to handle the tension between "not exactly satisfied consistency conditions" and becoming a fully fledged interpretation was certainly well known to the proponents. But the solution to simply put the histories program "in service of the Everett interpretation" is as far from any goals Griffiths had than you possibly could imagine.

Maybe this is another sense in which consistent histories is "intentionally" incomplete. The Everett interpretation claims to be able to derive the Born rule, and claims to derive some ontology of many quasi-classical worlds. The status of both claims is controversial, to say the least. If one of them fails, then the Everett interpretation becomes "unintentionally" incomplete. So "intentionally" being incomplete might also be a way to avoid being "misused" too badly "in the service of some competing interpretation".
 
  • #6
Why is everybody so obsessed to "derive Born's rule" and not simply take it as one of the postulates? As any system of postulates quantum theory is justified by its success to describe the phenomena. Also what is gained assuming "many worlds", of which only one is observed or "consistent histories" which seemingly is not even a clearly defined interpretation?
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn and Lord Jestocost
  • #7
vanhees71 said:
Why is everybody so obsessed to "derive Born's rule"
Because the Born rule is unsatisfactory as a postulate since it involves the concept of "measurement", which is only informally defined. A postulate in a scientific theory should have a clear formal definition.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier and vanhees71
  • #8
In which sense are the other postulates, as written in our Insight article by @A. Neumaier ,

https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/the-7-basic-rules-of-quantum-mechanics/

more formally defined than Born's rule?

Of course, it's the rule (and in my opinion the only rule really needed) which links the purely mathematical axioms to observations and as such makes it a physical rather than a purely mathematical theory, but what's "not formal enough" for being a postulate of a physical theory?

It's also clear that the postulates have to be somewhat modified to make them really accurate (e.g., it's not ##|\psi \rangle## which represents a pure state but the corresponding statistical operator ##|\psi \rangle \langle \psi|## (or, equivalently the corresponding unit ray) and the operators representing observables must be self-adjoint and not only hermitean. Also for a complete description of quantum mechanics you need more general, i.e., "mixed" states, but all these are subtle mathematical details. I don't see, why all the other postulates are "more formally defined" than Born's rule. I'm talking about "physical postulates" not a mathematically strict axiomatic formulation of QT (which we have for non-relativistic QM only, anyway).
 
  • #9
vanhees71 said:
In which sense are the other postulates, as written in our Insight article by @A. Neumaier ,

https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/the-7-basic-rules-of-quantum-mechanics/

more formally defined than Born's rule?
Of the 7 basic rules as we gave them in that Insights article, the last three, 5, 6, and 7, all use the term "measurement" and are therefore only informally defined. So 5 and 7 as we gave them are open to the same objection as Born's rule (6).
 
  • #10
PeterDonis said:
Because the Born rule is unsatisfactory as a postulate since it involves the concept of "measurement", which is only informally defined. A postulate in a scientific theory should have a clear formal definition.
Of course, there is nothing wrong with taking the Born rule in a measurement context as a practical rule. But in this case it should be clear that the Born rule is the "map", not the "territory". The problem arises when some practical users of the map become so successful in the use of the map that they start to believe that the map is the territory. Furthermore, the problem turns into an irony and self-contradiction when those practical users, who insist that only practical use matters and all philosophy is meaningless, promote this dictum into philosophy.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #11
PeterDonis said:
Of the 7 basic rules as we gave them in that Insights article, the last three, 5, 6, and 7, all use the term "measurement" and are therefore only informally defined. So 5 and 7 as we gave them are open to the same objection as Born's rule (6).
Hm, but what makes this "only informally defined". It's a physical theory not a set of meaningless mathematical axioms. Of course math is always more rigorous, because it's just a "game of rules" without any observational meaning. That's the difference between a structural and a natural science.
 
  • #12
Demystifier said:
Of course, there is nothing wrong with taking the Born rule in a measurement context as a practical rule. But in this case it should be clear that the Born rule is the "map", not the "territory". The problem arises when some practical users of the map become so successful in the use of the map that they start to believe that the map is the territory. Furthermore, the problem turns into an irony and self-contradiction when those practical users, who insist that only practical use matters and all philosophy is meaningless, promote this dictum into philosophy.
Of course it's a map, as all the mathematical items in any physical theory. You are right, physics is an empirical science and the theories/models are just describing ("mapping" if you wish) what's observed.

The philosophy is beyond the natural sciences. It's not founded in observations, i.e., different interpretations of the same theory cannot be empirically tested. Whether you consider philosophy as "meaningless" is also just a personal matter of taste.
 
  • #13
vanhees71 said:
what makes this "only informally defined"
Because it doesn't tell you what a "measurement" is or how to determine when a "measurement" has happened. That is left up to the informal judgment of each individual person making use of the formalism. Whereas other terms, such as "quantum system" and "observable", are given exact formal definitions; it's not left up to the individual judgment of each person to say what those things are.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #14
vanhees71 said:
but what's "not formal enough" for being a postulate of a physical theory?
To support @PeterDonis, it's not formal enough because the formal definition of measurement is missing.
 
  • #15
It's ironic that one of the keys for upholding the rationality of natural sciences, the empirical component - "observation or measurement" (corroboration involves measurments) - is seen as a deep "problem" by so many? They want to get rid of measurements and get rid of observers because its fuzzy. What would be left? metaphysics?

Sure the interface between theory making and reality is fuzzy, but what else to expect from a learning process? Physics (not even theoretical physics) is not unique axiomatic constructions, and I don't see that it's a sound goal?

I must that admit that I have a hard time to fine a better and natural junction than "observation" and "measurement" for theory and practice to meet, so why do some insist in trying to recast this to hide the junctions? This is why for me the observer and it's measurements are a natural starting point, even if it's a bit fuzzy, but the fuzziness is right where it belongs IMO.

/Fredrik
 
  • #16
Fra said:
They want to get rid of measurements and get rid of observers
No, they don't. They want to have complicated things like "measurements" and "observers" be built from the fundamental entities of the theory, instead of being unanalyzed postulates. Just as we expect complicated things like "macroscopic objects" to be built from the fundamental entities of the theory.
 
  • #17
vanhees71 said:
Why is everybody so obsessed to "derive Born's rule" and not simply take it as one of the postulates?
I might have been a bit unfair by implicitly hinting that all MWI proponents would claim that Born's rule can be derived. As an example of a proponent who doesn't, Lev Vaidman wrote:
Negative publicity for the MWI comes from the controversial claims about advantages of the MWI relative to other interpretations, e.g., that the Born Rule can be derived instead of postulated [30]. The claim is natural, because it is not simple to postulate the Born Rule in the MWI, but I believe it is false. In any case, the difficulties of this program reflect negatively on the MWI.

vanhees71 said:
Also what is gained ... "consistent histories" which seemingly is not even a clearly defined interpretation?
It is clearly defined, it is just not complete. In fact, what is gained by caring less about whether it is complete is that its definition can be made simpler and clearer. You can use it to investigate certain controversial questions, like for example locality. Or analyze certain paradoxes.
 
  • #18
But you cannot formally define, what a measurement is. It's what's done in the lab and changes with the advance of technology. It's physics, not pure math!

Also I think it's pretty plausible that Born's rule cannot be derived from the other postulates (see, e.g., Weinberg's textbook on quantum mechanics), though it seems not to be proven not to be deriable either.
 
  • Like
Likes Fra
  • #19
PeterDonis said:
No, they don't. They want to have complicated things like "measurements" and "observers" be built from the fundamental entities of the theory, instead of being unanalyzed postulates. Just as we expect complicated things like "macroscopic objects" to be built from the fundamental entities of the theory.
Ok, I get your point, but I still see that is problematic as from my perspective the "observer" is technically at the center of the inference (and the organism learning and evolving), and probably can't be captured as a "state" in a fixed statespace. The problems are similar to reductionist approach to biology... it usually gets extremely unnatural, evolutionary explanations are usually required to actually get some explanatory value.

/Fredrik
 
  • #20
But the "theory defines", what fundamental entities are. In Newtonian mechanics the "fundamental entity" are "point particles", which of course are fictitious simplifications of "little bodies of final extent". Using the same fictitious simplification in classical electrodynamics ("electron theory" a la Lorentz et al) it becomes a problem making the whole edifice inconsistent, i.e., it's oversimplified.

In QM the "fundamental entities" are "elementary particles", very abstractly defined as described by irreducible (ray) representations of the underlying space-time-symmetry group.

"Macroscopic objects" are then built from the fundamental entities by deriving all kinds of "effective theories". We just celebrated the anniversary Andersons famous article "More is Different"!

https://www.science.org/doi/10.1126/science.177.4047.393
https://www.nature.com/articles/s42254-022-00483-x
 
  • #21
vanhees71 said:
you cannot formally define, what a measurement is
Which, if true, means that "measurements" should not appear in the formal definition of the theory at all. See below.

vanhees71 said:
the "theory defines", what fundamental entities are
Yes.

vanhees71 said:
"Macroscopic objects" are then built from the fundamental entities
And since measurements are made using macroscopic objects, we should be able to build measurements out of fundamental entities as well. Then "measurements" would not need to appear in the formal definition of the theory, any more than "macroscopic objects" do. Only the fundamental entities should need to appear in the formal definition of the theory. Yet no one has found a formalization of QM that does that.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #22
With this ambition, we don't have any physical theories at all ;-). You cannot even define, what a "point particle" in Newtonian mechanics is at the demand of rigor you want!
 
  • #23
Fra said:
I still see that is problematic as from my perspective the "observer" is technically at the center of the inference (and the organism learning and evolving), and probably can't be captured as a "state" in a fixed statespace.
An "observer" is a complex object, so one would not expect a single state to capture it, any more than such a thing could capture a macroscopic object in general. You would need to build an observer out of a large number of fundamental entities, and of course an observer would not be a static thing, it would be dynamic, changing with time as it interacts with the world.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #24
PeterDonis said:
observer would not be a static thing, it would be dynamic, changing with time as it interacts with the world.
Evolving unitarily, yet learning? :H

/Fredrik
 
  • #25
Fra said:
The problems are similar to reductionist approach to biology... it usually gets extremely unnatural, evolutionary explanations are usually required to actually get some explanatory value.
I'm not sure what you mean by the "reductionist approach to biology", but the fact that organisms are made of cells, which in turn are made of proteins, nucleic acids, etc., is essential in understanding how living organisms work. Evolutionary explanations are certainly important as well, but they're not the whole story. For example, understanding how metabolism works is independent of working out how the metabolic systems in current living organisms evolved.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #26
Fra said:
Evolving unitarily, yet learning? :H
Unitary evolution only applies to an entire closed system. Obviously an observer is not an entire closed system. Only the universe as a whole is.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #27
But we understand the "observer" (or rather measurement devices) at least to enough extent that we can construct them. E.g., a silicon pixel detector at the LHC is based on solid-state (semi-conductor) physics, which describes the corresponding solids with help of effective theories of many-body systems consisting of elementary particles. It's in a sense a more challenging part of theoretical physics to find these effective theories from a given more fundamental theory (in this case the "standard model of elementary particle physics").
 
  • #28
PeterDonis said:
Unitary evolution only applies to an entire closed system. Obviously an observer is not an entire closed system. Only the universe as a whole is.
So you need to model the whole universe to model the observers from fundamental parts unitarily? Is that a viable method?

/Fredrik
 
  • #29
Fra said:
So you need to model the whole universe to model the observers from fundamental parts unitarily?
No, you just need to recognize that when dealing with a subsystem, you won't necessarily have unitary dynamics for just that subsystem. You trace over the parts of the universe you're not including in your model. In some cases (if the subsystem's interactions with the rest of the universe are small enough during the time period of interest), the dynamics of the subsystem are close enough to unitary that they can be approximated as unitary to a good enough accuracy. But in general you would not expect a subsystem's dynamics to be unitary since it is interacting with the rest of the universe.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and Fra
  • #30
vanhees71 said:
Hm, but what makes this "only informally defined". It's a physical theory not a set of meaningless mathematical axioms. Of course math is always more rigorous, because it's just a "game of rules" without any observational meaning. That's the difference between a structural and a natural science.
Formally means in formal mathematical terms.

vanhees71 said:
With this ambition, we don't have any physical theories at all ;-). You cannot even define, what a "point particle" in Newtonian mechanics is at the demand of rigor you want!
The fundamental entities (such as point particles in classical mechanics) are simple and their complete collection of properties is postulated (in classical mechanics as irreducible Poisson representations of the Galilei or Poincare group).

For a formally complete description, everything more complicated (macroscopic objects, observer, observations) must be defined mathematically in terms of the states of the fundamental entities.

This is the case in classical mechanics but not in quantum mechanics. In the latter case, the missing piece is the content of the measurement problem.

vanhees71 said:
But the "theory defines", what fundamental entities are. In Newtonian mechanics the "fundamental entity" are "point particles", which of course are fictitious simplifications of "little bodies of final extent". Using the same fictitious simplification in classical electrodynamics ("electron theory" a la Lorentz et al) it becomes a problem making the whole edifice inconsistent, i.e., it's oversimplified.

In QM the "fundamental entities" are "elementary particles", very abstractly defined as described by irreducible (ray) representations of the underlying space-time-symmetry group.

"Macroscopic objects" are then built from the fundamental entities by deriving all kinds of "effective theories".
And since measurements are not among your fundamental entities, one must also tell how they are built from the fundamental entities by deriving some kind of "effective theory".
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #31
PeterDonis said:
Unitary evolution only applies to an entire closed system. Obviously an observer is not an entire closed system. Only the universe as a whole is.
Yes of course, this was my point, but I see I was expressing myself poorly.

My point was though that in order to understand/explain the observers evolution, in that view, you need to know everything and from the unitary evolution of everthing, them average out/reduce the environment. But that idea seems to not help when the observer is an "open system" as you say. I think it's a problem if you by "open system" implicitly assume it's a subset of a "closed system", because that hypothetical close system is out of reach for inference as long as it's unknown and not possible to manage from computational perspective at hand.

/Fredrik
 
  • #32
Fra said:
you need to know everything and from the unitary evolution of everthing, them average out/reduce the environment. But that idea seems to not help when the observer is an "open system" as you say. I think it's a problem if you by "open system" implicitly assume it's a subset of a "closed system",
All systems that we can observe are subsystems of the closed system called the universe, and hence are open systems, even when they may be regarded at unitary for sufficiently simple observables.
Fra said:
because that hypothetical close system is out of reach for inference as long as it's unknown and not possible to manage from computational perspective at hand.
The universe is not out of reach. On the contrary, we know quite a lot about the universe. The far away part matters only in terms of incoming light, which we understand quite well. The solar system and smaller scales are also known quite well. For most observations, nuch, much less from the environment must be known.
 
  • #33
PeterDonis said:
An "observer" is a complex object, so one would not expect a single state to capture it, any more than such a thing could capture a macroscopic object in general. You would need to build an observer out of a large number of fundamental entities, and of course an observer would not be a static thing, it would be dynamic, changing with time as it interacts with the world.
Yes, but the point of the argument which one can differ upon is to what extent an observer can learn a timeless dynamical law, and distinguish it from the state in a statespace in which the law operates, in a timely manner.

The argument is similar to this paper of Smolin https://arxiv.org/abs/1201.2632.

My original intent in the thread was supportive of Vanhees empirical/instrumental perspective and take on physical postulates, but i have a more abstract take on "emprisim/instrumentalism" which leads ot the abstracted observer centerted view, and here I learned by know Vanhees disagrees as it becomes too philosophical.

/Fredrik
 
  • #34
A. Neumaier said:
The universe is not out of reach. On the contrary, we know quite a lot about the universe. The far away part matters only in terms of incoming light, which we understand quite well. The solar system and smaller scales are also known quite well. For most observations, nuch, much less from the environment must be known.
I didn't mean we can't literally see, we can still see light back to the era of recombination etc, but I meant out of reach as in not beeing deductively inferrable from the perspective of the inside observer, according the reductionist model, imagined as computational simulation, due to limits of information capacity processing. We CAN infer it softly though by abduction, but then I think the mode of thinking as thinking of the universe as a closed fixed system in a timeless statespace of which we see a small parts is not helpful for me at least.

/Fredrik
 
  • #35
Fra said:
in order to understand/explain the observers evolution, in that view, you need to know everything
No, you don't. An observer does not observe everything, nor do we need an exact model of the entire universe in order to construct a model that is a reasonable approximation of a restricted subsystem, such as an observer and some particular object they are observing.

Note that tracing over the rest of the universe does not require you to know its state. Indeed, it presupposes that you don't know its state, because tracing means basically averaging over all possible states that the rest of the universe could have. You wouldn't have to do that if you knew the exact state of the entire universe. But of course we don't and we never will.
 

Similar threads

Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
100
Views
6K
Replies
26
Views
4K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
25
Views
3K
Replies
53
Views
6K
Back
Top