Is Chomsky's View on the Mind-Body Problem Redefining Materialism?

  • Thread starter bohm2
  • Start date
In summary, according to Chomsky, the mind-body problem can't be solved because there is no clear way to state it. The problem of the relation of mind to matter will remain unsolved.
  • #71
Gold Barz said:
So the free energy principle is a mind-like process?

No, that would be the general material basis for the theory. So out of thermodynamics as a physical-level description of reality, we have a bunch of robust mathematical models that are to do with symmetry breaking, dissipation, and these kinds of processes. We also have the concepts of information and entropy as a measure of what is going on. So you have that general material paradigm that gives you the set of tools, then you build your model of the brain from that.

Contrast this with the old computer science approach where the attempt was to use computational theory as a basis.

Or indeed the dynamical systems approach which tried to tap into chaos and non-linear dynamics for a source of modelling tools.

This free energy story is a sort of hybrid of these two. But the computational aspects are more like neural network modelling and the dynamical aspects are more based on dissipative structure principles than chaos theory.

And both these things are moves away from straight reductionist thinking (cogsci and deterministic chaos) towards a systems view (hierarchical and self-organising neural nets and dissipative structures).

So you can see it as a hardening up of the view of the correct modelling language to describe the brain/mind as a system. But then you still have to build the model.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
PhizzicsPhan said:
As for Bohm...Another way of saying that is that everything material is also mental and everything mental is also material, but there are many more infinitely subtle levels of matter than we are aware of."

He's kind of forced to throw in russian dolls downwards because of the properties of his quantum/guiding/pilot wave, since it has unusual properties (e.g. non-local and propagates not in ordinary space but in a multidimensional-configuration space)

Bohm argues that this isn't like other force fields but is an "active information" field:

We therefore emphasize that the quantum filed is not pushing or pulling the particle mechanically, any more that the radio wave is pushing or pulling the ship that it guides. So the ability to do work does not originate in the quantum field, but must have some other origin...Such a notion suggests, however, that the electron may be much more complex than we thought (having a structure of a complexity that is perhaps comparable, for example, to that of a simple guidance mechanism such as an automatic pilot.

Hence the russion dolls...

Some have criticized this "radio wave" metaphor:

The radio metaphor is worrisome for a number of reasons. First, there is the concern about where the electron (or other particles) are getting the energy to put the information they receive to work. Radios have batteries or some other power source to draw on. Metaphorically speaking, where are the electron’s batteries? Second, the radio metaphor suggests that just as radio waves are too weak to move a ship, so too the force given by
taking the appropriate partial derivative of Q is too weak to move an electron (or some other particle). But this is false (and Bohm knew that). The quantum potential is such that when the appropriate partial derivative is taken, we arrive at the required force to move the particle.


http://www.tcm.phy.cam.ac.uk/~mdt26/local_papers/guarini_2003.pdf
 
  • #73
I found Stoljar’s epistemic “solution” to the "hard problem” of consciousness interesting (this is a summary of U. Kriegel’s review):

1. There are phenomenal facts-these are supported by direct introspection

2. If there are phenomenal facts, they are necessitated by physical facts because

(i) apparently everything else is necessitated by the physical facts and
(ii) facts cited in the manifest image are generally necessitated by facts cited in the scientific image

3. But there are phenomenal facts, that are not necessitated by physical facts-this is supported by stuff like Chalmers’ conceivability argument and Jackson’s knowledge argument, etc. (i.e. conscious experience involves “non-physical” properties)

Stoljar denies 3 above because he argues that we are ignorant of a whole class of facts about “matter”. These unknown facts about matter, in combination with the known ones, do necessitate the phenomenal facts. But because

(i) we are ignorant of them and
(ii) the facts of which we are not ignorant do not by themselves necessitate the phenomenal facts, the phenomenal facts seem unnecessitated by the physical facts.

Why are we ignorant of certain “physical” facts?

(i) as a natural, evolved system, there is no reason to expect the human intellect to understand all the facts about our universe or its physical makeup, let alone understand them especially at this time in our history
(ii) tremendous philosophical and empirical difficulties surrounding consciousness occur because of the ignorance hypothesis: physics can tell us only about the dispositional or relational properties of matter, but since dispositions ultimately require categorical properties as bases, and relations ultimately require intrinsic properties as relata, there must also be categorical or intrinsic properties about which physics is silent. Yet these are properties of physical objects and thus are physical properties in one central sense. Instantiations of such properties would therefore constitute physical facts of which we are ignorant, as per the ignorance hypothesis
(iii) intellectual and chemical facts (respectively) that were not necessitated by physical facts in the past turned out later to be frustrated by thitherto unknown physical facts (e.g. unification of chemistry with physics didn’t happen until the physics changed via quantum mechanics)

If we are ignorant of a certain class of facts about matter, then the conceivability and knowledge arguments fail. So phenomenal facts seem not necessitated by the physical facts even though they are. He then goes on to argue that in the future when we go on to discover a previously unknown but otherwise quite ordinary set of physical facts when combined together with the familiar physical facts it will necessitate the phenomenal facts.

http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/25270-ignor...temic-origin-of-the-problem-of-consciousness/

http://www.uriahkriegel.com/downloads/slugfest.pdf

This seems like a more detailed argument proposed by people like Russell, Eddington, Chomsky, etc. Chomsky makes that point when he argues:

It has been common in recent years to ridicule Descartes's "ghost in the machine" in postulating mind as distinct from body. Well, Newton came along and he did not exorcise the ghost in the machine: he exorcised the machine and left the ghost intact. So now the ghost is left and the machine isn't there.

But, do we really need to know the intrinsic properties of matter to truly understand qualia/the experiential? Since the intrinsic properties of matter are likely forever beyond scientific inquiry, is the hard problem "chronic and incontrovertible"?
 
  • #74
bohm2 said:
But, do we really need to know the intrinsic properties of matter to truly understand qualia/the experiential? Since the intrinsic properties of matter are likely forever beyond scientific inquiry, is the hard problem "chronic and incontrovertible"?

Stoljar sets up his argument to preserve reductionism. He presumes something in the microscale must be the secret, we just haven't found it yet.

But we already know from biology that ontology is more complex. In particular, Pattee's epistemic cut shows that semiosis - symbols, memory, computation - stands as antithetical to material causes.

http://informatics.indiana.edu/rocha/pattee/pattee.html

9. The irreducibility of the epistemic cut

The concept of constraint is not considered fundamental in physics because the (internal, geometric reactive) forces of constraint can, in principle, be reduced to active impressed forces governed by energy-based microscopic dynamical laws. The so-called fixed geometric forces are just stationary states of a faster, more detailed dynamics. This reducibility to microscopic dynamics is possible in principle for structures, even if it is computationally completely impractical. However, describing any bridge across an epistemic cut by a single dynamical description is not possible even in principle.

The most convincing general argument for this irreducible complementarity of dynamical laws and measurement function comes again from von Neumann (1955, p. 352). He calls the system being measured, S, and the measuring device, M, that must provide the initial conditions for the dynamic laws of S. Since the non-integrable constraint, M, is also a physical system obeying the same laws as S, we may try a unified description by considering the combined physical system (S + M). But then we will need a new measuring device, M', to provide the initial conditions for the larger system (S + M). This leads to an infinite regress; but the main point is that even though any constraint like a measuring device, M, can in principle be described by more detailed universal laws, the fact is that if you choose to do so you will lose the function of M as a measuring device. This demonstrates that laws cannot describe the pragmatic function of measurement even if they can correctly and completely describe the detailed dynamics of the measuring constraints.

This same argument holds also for control functions which includes the genetic control of protein construction. If we call the controlled system, S, and the control constraints, C, then we can also look at the combined system (S + C) in which case the control function simply disappears into the dynamics. This epistemic irreducibility does not imply any ontological dualism. It arises whenever a distinction must be made between a subject and an object, or in semiotic terms, when a distinction must be made between a symbol and its referent or between syntax and pragmatics. Without this epistemic cut any use of the concepts of measurement of initial conditions and symbolic control of construction would be gratuitous.

"That is, we must always divide the world into two parts, the one being the observed system, the other the observer. In the former, we can follow up all physical processes (in principle at least) arbitrarily precisely. In the latter, this is meaningless. The boundary between the two is arbitrary to a very large extent. . . but this does not change the fact that in each method of description the boundary must be placed somewhere, if the method is not to proceed vacuously, i.e., if a comparison with experiment is to be possible." (von Neumann, 1955, p.419)

Or more is different, as Philip Anderson famously put it. The fundamental laws of physics are shaped to describe the symmetries of nature. And fail to describe how those symmetries are broken. And complexity is all about systems that are living/mindful because they have gained local control over certain symmetry breakings (via semiotic mechanism).

http://robotics.cs.tamu.edu/dshell/cs689/papers/anderson72more_is_different.pdf

So the flaw is always to presume everything must reduce to microscale physical laws. You first have to get past the arguments that essential aspects of life and mind are irreducible in this fashion.

If symmetries get broken from the top-down (by information acting as constraint), then you can inspect those fundamental microscale symmetries forever and not discover any brokenness. The cause just does not lie within them, but without.
 
Last edited:
  • #75
apeiron said:
Stoljar sets up his argument to preserve reductionism. He presumes something in the microscale must be the secret, we just haven't found it yet.

But we already know from biology that ontology is more complex. In particular, Pattee's epistemic cut shows that semiosis - symbols, memory, computation - stands as antithetical to material causes.

I'm guessing these authors would ask: What is Pattee's definition of "material"?
 
  • #76
bohm2 said:
I'm guessing these authors would ask: What is Pattee's definition of "material"?

Did you not read the paper? The whole point is that "all is material". But causality is both micro and macro when it comes to complexity.

So to use the Aristotelean frame, material and effective cause are "down there" at the level of micro-physics. But formal and final cause are the "up there" as the global material constraints.

Pattee defines the bit you mean as material as "the rate dependent dynamics of construction". It is what reductionists would like to believe is the whole of materiality. But Pattee shows how non-holonomic constraints are also part of material reality.

This is important because the conventional computational view of symbols is "physics-free" as Pattee says. There is something obviously right about computationalism (which is why it seems central to scientific theories of mind), but as a discourse it is not actually grounded in the physical, in the material. Instead it floats free in a rather Platonic fashion that leads to all kinds of familiar philosophical problems (like Searle's chinese box).

So that is why I single Pattee out here. He is a strict materialist (though his background in QM would already make him say the material is not so simple). And he shows how more is different. Materiality has this hidden face of semiotic control lurking within it.

You can see Pattee arguing against the other side - those who fail to ground the computational in the material - in his paper, Artificial life needs a real epistemology.

http://www.google.co.nz/url?sa=t&so...2OH9Cw&usg=AFQjCNHYxZCLgUMfAu5Yrcj9cbrQaKm7cA
 
  • #77
Hi bohm,
bohm2 said:
I found Stoljar’s epistemic “solution” to the "hard problem” of consciousness interesting (this is a summary of U. Kriegel’s review):

1. There are phenomenal facts-these are supported by direct introspection
Does Stolijar’s solution suggest that phenomenal consciousness is epiphenomenal? If so, how can phenomenal facts be supported? Have you heard of the “knowledge paradox”?
3. But there are phenomenal facts, that are not necessitated by physical facts-this is supported by stuff like Chalmers’ conceivability argument and Jackson’s knowledge argument, etc. (i.e. conscious experience involves “non-physical” properties)

Stoljar denies 3 above because he argues that we are ignorant of a whole class of facts about “matter”. These unknown facts about matter, in combination with the known ones, do necessitate the phenomenal facts. But because

(i) we are ignorant of them and
(ii) the facts of which we are not ignorant do not by themselves necessitate the phenomenal facts, the phenomenal facts seem unnecessitated by the physical facts.

Why are we ignorant of certain “physical” facts?
How does Stolijar define “physical”? Is he using the term as others would use the term “natural”? Or does he use the term to refer to objectively observable phenomena such as the interactions of molecules, etc… ? If he’s using the term physical to mean the latter, then does he (or anyone else you know of) try to come to grips with how additional physical information in the form of phenomenal facts, might somehow be missing from a complete description of these objectively observable interactions? I keep hearing folks suggest that “we are ignorant of a certain class of facts about matter” but if some day we have a complete description of all the objectively observable interactions then what more do we need? Why even bother talking about phenomenal facts at that point? At the point we can accurately predict the interaction of all of matter, any additional theory about phenomenal facts would appear to be superfluous.
 
  • #78
This is the part that confuses me. I understand that wholeness or top-down and down-up (synergistic) relationships/causality is likely required to explain "real systemic or emergent properties" (e.g. the whole is greater than the sum of it's parts, etc.). This is suggested even the micro-level (e.g. Bell's experiments, QM, etc.). But even if one assumes some level of wholeness or top-down (synergistic) relationship/causality to explain emergence, novelty, etc. is that sufficient to spit out the mental/qualia from the non-mental? It seems that even this 2-way macroscopic/microscopic synergetic stuff only spits out more non-mental stuff (up to this point in our history of science)?
 
Last edited:
  • #79
I think physicalism last hope is causal overdetermination. In fact it's a choice between overdetermination and epiphenomenalism, with both facing huge problems.

If we discuss the 3 materialistic theories - reductive physicalism, reductive functionalism and non-reductive physicalism, we see that none of them can successfully account for both mental causation and qualia, if we abandon causal overdetermination.

The 2 reductive theories - reductive physicalism and reductive functionalism - imply that the mental (M) can be reduced to either a physical (P) or a functional (F) state. So we have a kind of identity (M = P) or (M = F). And here comes the two huge problems for the reductionists known as http://www.iep.utm.edu/qualia/" .
The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism - http://www.iep.utm.edu/know-arg/ said:
Frank Jackson gives the argument its classic statement (in Jackson 1982 and Jackson 1986). He formulates the argument in terms of Mary, the super-scientist. Her story takes place in the future, when all physical facts have been discovered. These include “everything in completed physics, chemistry, and neurophysiology, and all there is to know about the causal and relational facts consequent upon all this, including of course functional roles” (Jackson 1982, p. 51). She learns all this by watching lectures on a monochromatic television monitor. But she spends her life in a black-and-white room and has no color experiences. Then she leaves the room and sees colors for the first time. Based on this case, Jackson argues roughly as follows. If physicalism were true, then Mary would know everything about human color vision before leaving the room. But intuitively, it would seem that she learns something new when she leaves. She learns what it’s like to see colors, that is, she learns about qualia, the properties that characterize what it’s like. Her new phenomenal knowledge includes knowledge of truths. Therefore, physicalism is false.

Multiple Realizability - http://www.iep.utm.edu/identity/#H4 said:
Putnam’s argument can be paraphrased as follows: (1) according to the Mind-Brain Type Identity theorist (at least post-Armstrong), for every mental state there is a unique physical-chemical state of the brain such that a life-form can be in that mental state if and only if it is in that physical state. (2) It seems quite plausible to hold, as an empirical hypothesis, that physically possible life-forms can be in the same mental state without having brains in the same unique physical-chemical state. (3) Therefore, it is highly unlikely that the Mind-Brain Type Identity theorist is correct.


These two arguments point that the non-reductive physicalism is the best materialistic choice. We can have P1 and P2, so that P1 is not identical with P2, but both generate the same mentality M. We say that the mental state supervenes on the physical state, but is not identical with it. We can't reduce M and qualia is still there. Everything looks good until the famous "Supervenience Argument" from Jaegwon Kim appears.
The Waning of Materialism said:
The Supervenience Argument incorporates three central assumptions. The first one specifies that the physical world is causally closed:
Closure: If a physical event has a cause at t, then it has a physical cause at t. (Kim 2005: 15)

The second one stipulates that mental properties supervene upon physical properties:
Supervenience: If any system s instantiates a mental property M at t, there necessarily exists a physical property P such that s instantiates P at t, and necessarily anything instantiating P at any time instantiates M at that time.

And the third is an exclusion principle expressing the prohibition of systematic overdetermination:
Exclusion: If an event e has a sufficient cause c at t, no event at t distinct from c can be a cause of e (unless this is a genuine case of causal overdetermination).

According to Kim, if we further assume that mental properties are neither reducible to not identifiable with physical properties, what results is a set of propositions inconsistent with the causal relevance of mental properties:
The problem of mental causation: Causal efficacy of mental properties is inconsistent with the joint acceptance of the following four claims: (i) physical causal closure, (ii) causal exclusion, (iii) mind–body supervenience, and (iv) mental/ physical property dualism—the view that mental properties are irreducible to physical properties.

The reasoning behind this contention is as follows. Suppose we wish to identify a mental property instance, M, as the cause of a subsequent physical property instance, P. By Supervenience we know that there must be some physical property instance upon which M supervenes and by Closure we know that if P has a cause at a time t, it has a physical cause at t. Let us suppose that P has a cause at t and that the physical cause of P (at t) is P0, and let us assume that P0 is the physical property instance upon which M supervenes. By Exclusion we know that P has no cause other than P0 unless this is a case of genuine causal overdetermination, which, we will assume, it is not. From this it follows that M is the cause of P only if M = P. But given that no mental property is identical with or reducible to any physical property, it follows that the putative mental cause, M, is not in reality a cause of P. Since there is nothing special about M, P, or P0, the argument generalizes to show that instances of irreducible mental properties do not have physical effects, so that nonreductive physicalism entails epiphenomenalism: ‘That then is the supervenience argument against mental causation, or Descartes’s revenge against the physicalists’ (Kim 1998: 46).


Basically the "Supervenience Argument" shows that if we does not assume that causal overdetermination is possible, than antireductionism entails epiphenomenalism.
http://www.iep.utm.edu/mult-rea/#H4 said:
They could (a) deny the causal status of mental types; that is, they could reject Mental Realism and deny that mental types are genuine properties. Alternatively, they could (b) reject Physicalism; that is, they could endorse the causal status of mental types, but deny their causal status derives from the causal status of their physical realizers. Or finally, they could (c) endorse Mental Realism and Physicalism, and reject Antireductionism.


Kim than favors the reductionist approach and believes that we can have scenario in which "intentional/cognitive properties are reducible, but qualitative properties of consciousness, or 'qualia', are not" (see "Physicalism, or Something Near Enough"). However he was strongly criticized for this, because such variant will separate the http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-unity/" .

So physicalism is faced with a hard choice between overdetermination and epiphenomenalism, and we are back at the beginning.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #80
apeiron, I'd like to be able to go through all the replies and counter-replies and respond in detail but I just don't have time. I did, however, go back and review our old thread discussing pansemiotism, panpsychism, and Pattee. I detailed the problems in Pattee's thinking there and won't bother to repeat them here.

Rather, I'll point out that I think, again, that pansemiotism and panpsychism are essentially the same thing - but you've gotten stuck on some contradictory notions within your own version of pansemiotism.

Pansemiotism cannot hold that "all is material" unless we re-define material to include meaning/mind. The traditional meaning of material is the opposite of that which holds meaning. it is inherently non-meaningful, inherently without mind.

So, again, any systems theory that seeks to explain mind must have some plausible mechanism by which mind emerges from non-mind, or make clear that there is no emergence and that mind is there from the beginning.

You wrote in post #109 in this thread https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=485718&page=7:

"Either you are a reductionist and believe that everything reduces to stuff - the local properties of substance - or you are a systems thinker and believe that everything develops, everything emerges from pure potential by way of an interaction between the local and the global, between local construction (the substantial causes) and global constraints (the formal causes).

Panpsychism takes the reductionist approach. Reality is made of a stuff that has material and psychic properties inherently.

Pansemiosis is a systems approach. Reality starts beyond stuff. It starts out as a raw potential. Then stuff emerges as a bootstrap process of self-organisation."

We're actually very close in our positions, terminology aside. My version of panpsychism does not proceed as you describe, however. Rather, it's much closer to how you describe pansemiosis - emergence of stuff (which is both mind and matter, from inside and outside, respectively) from the realm of pure potentiality. That's why I describe my version of panpsychism, when I am obliged to be technical, as "panexperiential neutral monism." That is, there is a neutral substrate, which is neither mind nor matter, from which matter/mind emerge (thus "panexperiential").

So I think we're saying much the same thing at the end of the day but you have yet to see the difficulty with your position in terms of the emergence of mind (and life, as we previously discussed). Your position would be stronger and more consistent if you recognized that neither mind nor life "emerge"; they are there from the very initial emergence of stuff from the realm of pure potentiality - and as stuff complexifies so mind and life complexify.
 
Last edited:
  • #81
bohm2 said:
is that sufficient to spit out the mental/qualia from the non-mental? It seems that even this 2-way macroscopic/microscopic synergetic stuff only spits out more non-mental stuff (up to this point in our history of science)?

The problem here becomes the expectation that mental/qualia is a valid output to be spat out.

A qualia is imagined as a fundamental atom of experience. An irreducible smallest jot of subjectivity. You can take the redness or smell of a rose as an isolated substantial entity that stands alone, without reference to a context.

And a systems view is that no such thing exists in this fashion. If you focus in on just the experience of redness at some particular instance, there is still in fact everything else that is going on that is the global part of this act of conscious attention (such as all the other potential experience being actively suppressed).

If instead you are talking about the mental as the whole of this material activity, then this makes more sense. But now you are also treating as "mental" all the other activity that is involved - including that non-experience of activity being suppressed. The not-A which is the context forming the A.

What were we saying in another thread on Kuhn? Paradigms suggest the nature of their own evidence. What I would call evidence for a systems approach is not what you would call evidence for a reductionist approach, and vice versa. The two paradigms continually talk past each other.
 
  • #82
PhizzicsPhan said:
So I think we're saying much the same thing at the end of the day.

Oh no, we're definitely not. :rolleyes:

PhizzicsPhan said:
Your position would be stronger and more consistent if you recognized that neither mind nor life "emerge"; they are there from the very initial emergence of stuff from the realm of pure potentiality - and as stuff complexifies so mind and life complexify.

But why would I recognise positions for which you have failed to provide support because you are "too busy"?

And anyway, as I keep pointing out, saying stuff is conscious because consciousness is stuff is no form of explanation at all. It is an evasion of explanation.

Pansemiosis describes a general process (global constraints breaking local symmetries, as I have argued). So it is specific about the way the same (the symmetric) becomes the different (the broken). And it connects with a lot of modelling tools (hierarchy theory, self-organising criticality, modelling relations, epistemic cut).

So yes, the pan- would be justified in this approach as something that is there from the very beginning. But it is semiosis as a general causal principle that is there from the start. Not life(!) or mind, which are meant to be the explanandum here.

It is really annoying that you keep trying to make a false suggestive connection between pansemiosis and panpysychism, just as you do between panpsychism and QM.

Pansemiosis would be a general theory about the process of emergence and self-organisation.

Panpsychism is the claim that the mental (and living apparently!) is a fundamental property of stuff.

As I have pointed out in posts which you are too busy now to rebut, this is not a theory but merely an animistic belief.
 
  • #83
Ferris_bg said:
So physicalism is faced with a hard choice between overdetermination and epiphenomenalism, and we are back at the beginning.

Not really because Kim is again just restating the consequences of a reductionist paradigm.

If you believe that all causality is atomistic and constructive, then you will run into paradoxes. You are giving yourself no language with which to talk about global, downward acting, constraints.

So Kim proves that reductionism is inadequate to the task of fully accounting for systems. But we knew that.
 
  • #84
apeiron, for an obviously bright guy you don't read very closely. I've mentioned at least three times that my version of panpsychism does NOT hold that mind is a property of matter. Not. Rather, mind and matter are dual aspects of all actuality. There is not "stuff" that has mind. There is only actuality, which bubbles up from potentiality, and this actuality has mind-like and matter-like aspects, from different perspectives (inside and outside) and that oscillate with each moment in the creative advance.

I've also explained many times how my version of panpsychism goes far beyond a mere assumption.

I enjoy the dialogues with you, but how about this: I'll go back and read and respond to your detailed points if you do the same and don't simply ignore what I write?

More later...
 
  • #85
apeiron said:
So Kim proves that reductionism is inadequate to the task of fully accounting for systems. But we knew that.

You should re-read the post, his argument is against non-reductionism. I already explained it in details in a https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?p=3202969#post3202969" and told you that the system view, which you support, is a type of NRP.

As for the pan-topic, there is a slight difference between the three, which apeiron summed up in the https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=523765" (which was again not related to panpsychism, that's why I asked this thread to be separated, but it looks like mods can only close threads, so I ask you PhizzicsPhan to make us all a favor and open a special thread related to panpsychism only).

Apeiron wrote:
Panexperientialism believes Q --> C
Panpsychism believes Q = C
Pansemiosis believes C --> Q

PhizzicsPhan replayed "Cognition is just complex qualia. That's it."

Basically the difference I see is that for panpsychism, since you have M (C + Q) present in all particles, you are not commit to strong emergence to solve the combination problem. While by the other two you need to involve strong emergence to make the step from C/Q to M.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #86
PhizzicsPhan said:
apeiron, for an obviously bright guy you don't read very closely. I've mentioned at least three times that my version of panpsychism does NOT hold that mind is a property of matter.

Again, what I pointed out was that this is still saying that there is a "stuff" which posesses properties. So it is a claim about substance and essence. Neutral monism (in this reductionist version you are advancing) is still saying the same thing, except that instead of the fundamental stuff being matter, it is something else (that is still matter-like in conception in being fundamental, essential, possessing inherent properties, etc).

Saying that both matter and mind are the essential properties of some further unspecified stuff buys you nothing in terms of explanation here. It just pushes reductionism back another step into the mysterious and unexplained. It hopes to push the need for a causal explanation at the crucial juncture out of sight, where with any luck, critics won't bother to follow.

It doesn't matter how much you talk in handwavy fashion about oscillation and prehension and actuality and creative advance. You have failed to articulate the nature of the causal link between matter and mind. You have simply claimed that they are the same stuff (but then somehow not the same thing). And I am asking for specifics on how they are not the same thing if they are properties of the same stuff?

You may reply, well they just are. Even if I don't know how. At which point you demonstrate that there is no theory here.
 
  • #87
Ferris, I think I will start a separate panpsychism thread at some point but I think the discussion is working well enough for now.

With respect to your breakdown I don't think you have panexperientialism right. To me, panexperientialism and panpsychism are exactly the same (and pansemiosis, for that matter) because they posit that mind (whether we call it experience, psyche, consciousness or fried eggs) is fundamental to actuality. Whitehead and Griffin do make a distinction between experience and consciousness, but it's not a qualitative distinction; rather, it's just a matter of degree. It's also a matter of salesmanship. To many, it's more palatable to suggest that some type of experience is present in all things than to say that consciousness is present in all things. But these terms reduce to the same thing in their fundamental mind-ness, as opposed to non-mind-ness.
 
  • #88
PhizzicsPhan said:
To me, panexperientialism and panpsychism are exactly the same (and pansemiosis, for that matter) because they posit that mind (whether we call it experience, psyche, consciousness or fried eggs) is fundamental to actuality.

If this is what you believe, can you now provide a source to back it up?

Where does Peirce posit that mind is fundamental rather than the process of semiosis?

Take for example...

http://books.google.co.nz/books?id=...&resnum=6&ved=0CEIQ6AEwBQ#v=onepage&q&f=false
 
  • #89
Q_Goest said:
Does Stolijar’s solution suggest that phenomenal consciousness is epiphenomenal?
No

Q_Goest said:
How does Stolijar define “physical”? Is he using the term as others would use the term “natural”?

Stolijar (see his article on “physicalism” in link below) considers himself a physicalist but he defines it so broadly that it could be compatible with just about anything :

The theory-based conception:
A property is physical iff it either is the sort of property that physical theory tells us about or else is a property which metaphysically (or logically) supervenes on the sort of property that physical theory tells us about.

The object-based conception:
A property is physical iff: it either is the sort of property required by a complete account of the intrinsic nature of paradigmatic physical objects and their constituents or else is a property which metaphysically (or logically) supervenes on the sort of property required by a complete account of the intrinsic nature of paradigmatic physical objects and their constituents.


http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physicalism/

Even panpsychism is compatible with physicalism as he defines it. I think, like Chomsky, he doesn’t think we can unify the “mental” with current science because of our (current) ignorance of the physical.

Q_Goest said:
I keep hearing folks suggest that “we are ignorant of a certain class of facts about matter” but if some day we have a complete description of all the objectively observable interactions then what more do we need? Why even bother talking about phenomenal facts at that point? At the point we can accurately predict the interaction of all of matter, any additional theory about phenomenal facts would appear to be superfluous.

I think that depends on how one defines a “complete description of all the objectively observable interactions”. I think any theory that doesn’t somehow explain how the experiential fits into nature will not be a complete description . Some like Strawson demand quite a bit. He writes (see "The Impossibility of an Objective Phenomenology" on p. 62-65):

My claim is not that non-experiential or N properties cannot in fact be paired with experiential or E properties in correlation statements of the form ‘[N1→E1]’. It consists of two main points.

1. Even if we attempted to put forward correlation statements of the form ‘[N1 → E1]’, we could never hope to verify such statements across a human population by checking independently on E1 and N1 and thereby establishing the correlations, because we could never check independently on E1. If we somehow knew some of the correlation statements to hold true in the case of a single individual, we could perhaps take their general truth to be guaranteed by the truth of the supervenience thesis, but it is unclear whether even this would be acceptable, given the extent of our ignorance of the nature of the physical. Further, even if some statement of the form ‘[N1 → E1]’ were somehow known to be true, the only people who could know for sure what ‘E1’ referred to would be those who had been shown to have N1 and had been told which of their experiences was specially correlated with, or realized by, N1 (‘It’s whatever visual experience you are having...wait...now’).

2. We could never make a start on testing interpersonally applicable correlation statements of the form ‘[E1 → N1]’, because we could never be sure that we had distinguished the same experiential property in the case of two different people, even if they fully agreed in language about what experiences they were having. It is plausible that ‘[E1 → N1]’ correlation statements would have to be of the form ‘[E1 → N1 ∨ N2 ∨ N3 ∨... ]’: they would have to be disjunctive and open-ended on the righthand side, because of the possible “variable physical realization” of any experiential property. The present point, however, is that even if one could identify exactly which nonexperiential neural goings-on were involved in the occurrence of a particular type of experience in one’s own case, and at a given time, one could never fill out the disjunctive right-hand side of the correlation statement by including other people, because one could never know that one was really dealing with the same type of experience in their case.


http://books.benjibear.com/mind-info/MIT.Press.Mental.Reality.2nd.Edition.Nov.2009.eBook-ELOHiM.pdf
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #90
Ferris_bg said:
I already explained it in details in a https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?p=3202969#post3202969" and told you that the system view, which you support, is a type of NRP.

I tried to explain how it wasn't. Your claim was based on a few misconception as I outlined.

https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3203487&postcount=311
https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3203901&postcount=318

Ferris_bg said:
Apeiron wrote:
Panexperientialism believes Q --> C
Panpsychism believes Q = C
Pansemiosis believes C --> Q

Sorry, in which post did I write this?

What are Q, C and M here?
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #92
Ferris_bg said:
see for yourself in which category the http://philpapers.org/browse/systems-theory" is.

Are you trying to draw attention to some paper in this list? It is not clear what you mean to say here.

Ferris_bg said:
C, Q, M stand for cognition, qualia, mental obviously; https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?p=3253646".

Thanks for pointing to the actual post. And in fact it wasn't obvious that M was mental. I thought you may have meant matter.

Ferris_bg said:
While by the other two you need to involve strong emergence to make the step from C/Q to M.

That is not actually true of the approach I am taking. The development of a system (it's emergence) goes from a state of vagueness to one of crispness. So you would go from the vaguest form of mentality to the most crisply developed. In other words, the model is not an on/off binary story but one of a gradient of development.

So this is neither strong, nor weak, emergence I am talking about. It is a different ontological view of emergence.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #93
PhizzicsPhan said:
4. The No Sign Problem. There appears to be no direct evidence whatsoever that every element of reality has an associated mentalistic and in fact conscious aspect.

To the contrary, there is abundant evidence of rudimentary mentality. Dyson describes explicitly how what we call random behavior in electrons is better described as choice. So where today's science so often posits chance as an explanation, panpsychists see free choice. Obviously, there is even more abundant evidence of mentality in the domains of life, from bats to bacteria.

In many ways, this is the heart of the problem, for me. How do you know when you've come across this "rudimentary mentality" at the micro-level? It's kind of like trying to pass the "Turing test" but on the micro-level. I can't see how that is possible, given that we can't literally "see" this intrinsic, proto-mental aspect of stuff. It's easier with other conscious macro-stuff like ourselves because at least we have something to compare it to (our own subjectivity). I mean what kind of "behaviour" would more fundamental stuff (e.g. electrons, etc.) need to display to us so we get that "aha" feeling like: "Oh, well...now it's obvious how consciousness/experientiality/qualia can emerge from this basic stuff". I'm not sure if I'm making any sense?

While emergence/genuine novelty of stuff studied by current physics might not be predictable, there isn't this "awe" in the same way there appears to be with emergence of the experiential. Even synergestic top-down/down-up models don't seem to cut it in my opinion. Dyson's arguments that electrons have free choice versus randomness just isn't convincing to me. Maybe someone could elaborate on what properties they think would be required at the more "fundamental" level so that given that plus the synergestic stuff could lead to consciousness. I still can't see how this is possible because ultimately any such property will likely have to be some mathematical description and I don't see how such a mathematical object can give us that "aha" feeling. I find McGinn's point below interesting but I think we may have already reached that point in QM, but it doesn't appear of any help but I'm not sure?

I am now in a position to state the main thesis of this paper: in order to solve the mind-body problem we need, at a minimum, a new conception of space. We need a conceptual breakthrough in the way we think about the medium in which material objects exist, and hence in our conception of material objects themselves. That is the region in which our ignorance is focused: not in the details of neurophysiological activity but, more fundamentally, in how space is structured or constituted. That which we refer to when we use the word 'space' has a nature that is quite different from how we standardly conceive it to be; so different, indeed, that it is capable of 'containing' the non-spatial (as we now conceive it) phenomenon of consciousness. Things in space can generate consciousness only because those things are not, at some level, just how we conceive them to be; they harbour some hidden aspect or principle.

http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/consciousness97/papers/ConsciousnessSpace.html

There have been some attempts that I've come across to model qualia mathematically or as the authors write, to "begin translating the seemingly ineffable qualitative properties of experience into the language of mathematics" but even these authors concede:

Some experiences appear to be ‘‘elementary,’’ in that they cannot be further decomposed. Sub-modes that do not contain any more densely tangled sub-sub-modes are elementary modes (i.e., elementary shapes that cannot be further decomposed). According to the IIT (integrated information theory) such elementary modes correspond to aspects of experience that cannot be further analyzed, meaning that no further phenomenological structure is recognizable. The term qualia (in a narrow sense) is often used to refer to such elementary experiences, such as a pure color like red, or a pain, or an itch.

Finally, we have argued that specific qualities of consciousness, such as the ‘‘redness’’ of red, while generated by a local mechanism, cannot be reduced to it, but require considering the shape of the entire quale, within which they constitute a q-fold.

http://ntp.neuroscience.wisc.edu/faculty/fac-art/tononi5.pdf
 
Last edited:
  • #94
Hi Bohm,
Thanks for the very interesting write ups. Always good to see someone knowledgeable of philosophy stop by for a discussion.

I’d like to introduce you to what Gregg Rosenberg, “A Place for Consciousness” (pg. 119) calls the “knowledge paradox”. Rosenberg actually quotes Shoemaker, though reading Shoemaker, I think Rosenberg has a much better description of the paradox.

I think we all would agree that mental states (M) are supervenient on physical states (P). By mental states, I mean the phenomenal ones such as defined for example by Chalmers, “The Conscious Mind”. By physical states, I mean the objectively observable phenomena. Hopefully that’s clear.

Many of the philosophers you’ve quoted have suggested there is a correlation between the mental and physical states, and they certainly aren’t in the minority. Kim for example suggests that there is a correlation P1 (P1 is a physical state P at time 1) with M1 (mental state M at time 1) and Strawson whom you’ve quoted similarly calls this [N1→E1]. The quote from Strawson proposes to use this for the basis of comparison to verify that M exists in a given person. Perhaps we could also use this correlation to verify M in any physical system. Functionalism of course, would also suggest that this is true. Any functionally equivalent physical system should produce the equivalent mental states, if any. In other words, functionalism suggests that if a physical system duplicates all the functionality of a known system that is phenomenally conscious, that physical system must also be phenomenally conscious. One of the most heavily quoted examples of this is the thought experiment (Chalmers) that suggests we remove a brain cell and replace it with a microchip which performs all the identical functions that the brain cell did. Then we continue to replace one brain cell after another until we’re left with a functionally equivalent brain made of microchips. Thus, the argument goes, “at what point does phenomenal consciousness disappear?” The obvious implication is that there has been no change in any of the phenomenal states. If we were to disagree, we might suggest it disappears the moment we replace one brain cell or we might suggest it fades away slowly, but how could we possibly know? All the mental states are now represented by functionally identical physical states and any Turing test would certainly not be able to tell any difference between the two.

If we examine any physical state P1 of the brain described by the thought experiment, we’d find that each subsequent physical state P2 is causally determined by the prior state P1 as given for example by Kim. In the case of a deterministic computer such as the ones we have on our desktop, this causal link couldn’t be more clear. P2 is caused by P1 simply because each switch transistor is designed to operate under only one condition, an electrical charge must be applied to the base for the emitter and collector to be either open or close as shown in the figure below.
[PLAIN]http://mboffin.net/wp-content/uploads/2009/03/pnp-transistor.png
So we could examine P2 and we could determine exactly which state P3 will become, simply by examining the physical process. The mental states that are believed to be present (ie: M1 when P1, M2 when P2, etc…) can make no causal difference to any subsequent physical state. Again, this concept is nicely explained by Kim (Mind in a Physical World) and other literature by Kim. Also, the fact that our computer is fully determined by and dependant on the physical states should be quite obvious.

What makes the digital computer a useful conceptual tool here is the simple fact that it has distinct, physical states but that shouldn’t be construed as a limitation. Clearly, nonlinear physical systems require integrating physical states over time if we use the presumption as everyone does that phenomenal consciousness is dependent on classical mechanical causal interactions. This is done in neuroscience for example in the study of neurons using compartmental methods both in vivo, in vitro and modeled using numerical methods.

Returning to the model of a digital computer, we can see that all physical states over time dt are defined by prior physical states, so P3 follows P2 follows P1. We can know why the physical states occur since they are causally determined by the prior physical state. This can’t be more clear than for a digital computer which, like a series of dominoes falling over, simply proceeds from step to step with no potential for there to be a deviation from those steps. The physical states and any input/output are all that is needed to determine the function of the machine.

We can now ask the question, can we know if this computer harbors any mental states? Strawson would suggest we look for a correlation [N1→E1]. After all, if we can map these correlations (N) in the computer and we find they can be mapped to (N) in the human brain, then there must also be experiential phenomena (E) occurring. The knowledge paradox can now be seen in that assuming the causal closure of the physical, there is a physical cause for each physical state and there is no room for mental states to make a causal contribution to those physical brain events. Further, our claims about having mental states completely depend on those physical states. Both our claims about mental states and our behavior are determined solely by the objectively measurable physical states. So if mental states are irrelevant to the causal dynamics of the brain, those mental states can play no role in producing any of our claims (or behaviors) about those states. We can have no way of knowing from physical statements or behaviors if anyone is conscious nor even if we ourselves are conscious if only physical states are causally relevant. We like to believe there is a 1 to 1 correlation between P and M however, our physical brains would cause us to utter that we are p-conscious, and mere serendipity would have it that we were in fact correct. If the laws enforcing the epiphenomenal correlation between brain events and p-conscious events were to somehow be shut off, we would go on (falsely) claiming that we are p-conscious, none the wiser.

hypnagogue said:
3. The knowledge paradox
If physicalism is false, and if the world is causally closed under physics, it appears as if there is no room for p-consciousness to make a causal contribution to brain events. But clearly, our knowledge claims about p-consciousness (e.g. "I know that I am conscious right now") are driven by physical brain events. If p-consciousness is irrelevant to the causal dynamics of the brain, then, it seems that it can play no role in producing our knowledge claims about it. In short, it seems as if our knowledge claims about p-consciousness should bear no relevance to the phenomenon itself; we should have no way to really know that we are p-conscious, even though we claim that we are.

It appears as if the knowledge paradox forces the Liberal Naturalist to be caught on the dual horns of interactionist dualism and epiphenomenalism. We can escape the conundrum of the knowledge paradox if we deny the causal closure of the physical and claim that non-physical p-consciousness really does directly influence the physical dynamics of the brain. The resulting interactionist dualist ontology presents significant further problems, however, and there is no strong evidence that the world is not causally closed under physics. If we reject interactionism, we can bite the bullet and propose that p-consciousness is epiphenomenal on brain events. On this view, p-consciousness is lawfully correlated with brain events, but still does not make any contribution to their causal dynamics. Epiphenomenalism is not much better than interactionism, as it still presents us with significant problems. While knowledge claims about p-consciousness would be true under epiphenomenalism, it seems they would not be justified. Rather, they would be more like lucky coincidences, since there would be no mechanism by which we could attain reasons for making these claims. Our physical brains would cause us to utter that we are p-conscious, and mere serendipity would have it that we were in fact correct. If the laws enforcing the epiphenomenal correlation between brain events and p-conscious events were to somehow be shut off, we would go on (falsely) claiming that we are p-conscious, none the wiser.

The knowledge paradox is a deep problem for Liberal Naturalism, and on the surface, it seems as if the Liberal Naturalist is forced to choose between two highly problematic views. But perhaps the paradox does not turn on the nature of p-consciousness so much as it turns on our understanding of causation and its relationship to physics. A deeper theory of causation might allow the Liberal Naturalist to maintain that physicalism is false without being forced into either interactionist dualism or epiphenomenalism.

Rosenberg and Shoemaker aren’t of course, the only ones to see this problem. Another good example regards an argument in favor of epiphenomenalism by Susan http://psych.dbourget.com/readings/Pockett.pdf" , “Is Consciousness Epiphenomenal?” There are others.

To conclude, the proposal that there can be a mapping between non-experiential physical states and experiential mental states such as proposed by Strawson and others as well as the problem facing any purely objectively observable physical theory of nature requires that we address these kinds of logical dilemmas.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #95
Q_Goest said:
I think we all would agree that mental states (M) are supervenient on physical states (P).

No, I certainly don't agree, as this already hardwires the axioms of material reductionism into the discussion.

The systems perspective is irreducibly hierarchical and scale-based. It is about the interaction between parts and wholes, the local and the global, so the standard definition of a state (a complete description of a system in terms of parameters such as positions and momentums at a particular moment in time) does not apply.

The synchronic view taken by the notion of state cannot capture global dynamics which live in time (as history, as memory, as anticipation, as intentionality, as meaning, as development, as goals, etc, etc).

Reductionism collapses the global to the local and no longer "sees it". And we know the ontological paradoxes this regularly causes in physics, from special relativity and the block universe to the QM observer issue, to the question of where the laws of physics reside.

If you create a time-less model of reality (using state-speak), then of course you break the material connection between the different spatiotemporal scales of a system and arrive at a forced dualism. You have just stated that only the local is real - and yet it is bleeding obvious that the global is also as real, even if it is now being treated as the unreal.

This is what reductionism does to people. It puts them in the impossible bind of at the same time trying to believe that the global is unreal (according to science or logic) when also it must be real (as in the Platonic forms of maths, the immaterial laws of nature, the subjective impression of being a causal agent, etc).

Then to recover what has escaped explanation while still doing reductionism, there are various bad choices like suggesting the global is epiphenomenal (an a-causal illusion) or some component of the local - some further micro-physical property - which reductionism so far has just missed in its investigations.

But anyway, it is plain enough that if you wire in reductionism as axiomatic to your thought experiments, then a reductionist paradox is all that your arguments can spit out at the end.

For all the talk of dealing with the issue of synergistic interactions or global causal dynamics, that is actually impossible in terms of what has been assumed at the start.
 
Last edited:
  • #96
apeiron, you ask what evidence I have for suggesting that pansemiosis is equivalent to panpsychism. As we discussed previously, Peirce states explicitly that what is objective to others is subjective for itself. Here's my previous post to you in an earlier thread:

"Look, there are different levels of explanation and terms such as idealism, monism and panpsychism (not to mention physicalism, materialism, etc.) are themselves a bit squishy. Here's how I see it: there is a non-psychical substrate to reality (which I've mentioned previously) that we can call Brahman/apeiron/ether or simply the "vacuum" as modern physics sometimes does. This is the neutral monist substrate from which reality grows. Matter, as Peirce points out, springs from this substrate.

Peirce himself states, as I quoted previously that matter is what is viewed "from the outside" and mind what a thing is for itself "from the inside."

How is this not panpsychism?

Peirce also uses the term "hylopathy" - all things feel. How is this not panpsychism?

Now, we could split hairs and I suspect you will by saying that dual aspect panpsychism isn't the same as "objective idealism." But when we square Peirce's various statements it seems quite clear that his intent was to stress that mind is omni-present. And this is panpsychism. "
 
  • #97
bohm2 said:
In many ways, this is the heart of the problem, for me. How do you know when you've come across this "rudimentary mentality" at the micro-level? It's kind of like trying to pass the "Turing test" but on the micro-level. I can't see how that is possible, given that we can't literally "see" this intrinsic, proto-mental aspect of stuff. It's easier with other conscious macro-stuff like ourselves because at least we have something to compare it to (our own subjectivity). I mean what kind of "behaviour" would more fundamental stuff (e.g. electrons, etc.) need to display to us so we get that "aha" feeling like: "Oh, well...now it's obvious how consciousness/experientiality/qualia can emerge from this basic stuff".

bohm2, this is in fact a problem with all knowledge and all conscious beings. How do you know I'm conscious? How do I know you're conscious? We don't. We infer it. The ONLY thing we know is our own consciousness. Literally. All else is inference. So we can infer that electrons have an extremely rudimentary consciousness, as Dyson and Bohm (and many other panpsychists) did, but we can never know this is so. It's all about what conceptual framework best explains the evidence.

See my series of essays on "absent-minded science" for more: http://www.independent.com/news/2010/aug/11/absent-minded-science/
 
  • #98
PhizzicsPhan said:
apeiron, you ask what evidence I have for suggesting that pansemiosis is equivalent to panpsychism. As we discussed previously, Peirce states explicitly that what is objective to others is subjective for itself.

I quite agree that in "Man's Glassy Essence", Peirce gets very carried away and ends up arguing for telepathy and group-mind (do you follow him there too?). But you can't just pick and choose your quotes to suit your beliefs here.

In that essay, Peirce was developing a train of thought in which he was trying to account for the evidence of "feeling" right at the protoplasmic level of life. Now if you have read it, you can see Peirce lacked a critical piece of information about how life is actually "mechanistic" in having genes and other forms of systems memory. There is a place where habit is encoded.

So his reasoning goes wrong from there. Because Peirce could not find a place for accumulated habit to reside in a global fashion, he had to speculate about an atomistic level memory.

Likewise, because there was not enough neuroscience to explain how attention is a global brain mechanism, he again had to try and place the "feeling of attending" at the atomistic moment when some habit is being eroded by the vagaries of spontaneity.

So you are jumping in where Peirce is clearly wrong (due to a lack of better knowledge in his day) rather than focusing on where he was right (which is in his hierarchical approach to logic itself - treating causality in self-organising systems terms).

His semiosis does not actually support his own argument towards the end of the essay. But it is modern biologists who are developing the field of biosemiosis on the back of his triadic process. And the critical modification they make is the clear recognition that both words and genes function as symbols - ie: Pattee's epistemic cut.

Then pansemiosis (again, a modern development) would be based on Peirce's logic, but be able to fill in the blanks properly.

So semiosis as a triadic process was a proto-theory in Peirce's hands. He polished up the essential logic. But a modern systems thinker can also see that Peirce failed to deal explicitly with the issue of the epistemic cut, and also the centrality of scale to hierarchy.

Coming back to your panpsychism = pansemiosis, if you read Man's Glassy Essence carefully, what happens is that he stretches semiosis as far as he can, then starts talking in a handwavy panpsychic way that is unsupported by the notion of semiosis.

He takes a correct subjective observation (attention loosens habits) and tries to associate it with some micro-physical event. But that is because he lacked a better understanding of brain architecture. If you asked a neuroscientist to explain the relation between habit and attention today, you would get a pretty straightforward account in terms of cortico-striatal interactions.

eg: http://web.mit.edu/bcs/graybiel-lab/pub.html

It would be unfairly anachronistic to use Peirce as a champion of panpsychism when the thrust of his work was instead a focus on systematic causality. That is what scientists are actually using today (biosemiotics does not exist because it supports a panpsychic view of life).

So by all means, try to square Peirce's statements. But you will have to deal with the fact that the panpsychism is not properly derived from the semiotics even in Peirce's own writings. It was a jump he made in handwavy fashion when he ran out of facts that would allow him to imagine the world differently.

Fortunately we now know about genes, neural circuits, and suchlike.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #99
Q_Goest,

The defense of the epiphenomenalist against the knowledge paradox is that "when Sarah knows that she has a toothache or remembers the feeling she had when she first fell in love, there is a causal chain which leads from the neurophysiological cause of her toothache or her feeling to her current state of knowledge or memory... The causal relation she says holds between mental states and their neurophysiological correlates ensures that whenever her opponents appeal to a mental cause to account for some apparently undeniable fact, she can appeal to a physical cause which is correlated with the alleged mental cause with nomological necessity and does exactly the same causal job."

http://www.iep.utm.edu/epipheno/#SH5f

I don't know, for me epiphenomenalism is an option, not very possible, but an option.
 
  • #100
Hi Ferris, Thanks for that... I'm not understanding what the defense is though. They say, "Since the epiphenomenalist admits that we have experiences and since we cannot have experiences without knowing that we have them, the epiphenomenalist can admit that we can have knowledge of our experiences." Question is, how can the epiphenomenalist say that?

Remember:
- For a mental state to be epiphenomenal, M can't cause P, not now or ever.
- If we make statements about mental events, remembered or otherwise, the mental event must have inflicted some kind of causal influence on the physical state and is therefore no longer epiphenomenal; M has to cause a change in P for it to be remembered.

Take the case of the computer example; epiphenomenalism is the concept that what caused the transistor to change state isn't the mental event, it is the charge on the transistor's base. Not a single transistor will ever change state because a mental event took place, despite there being claims and behaviors by the computer. Therefore any claim has a purely physical reason for being made, that is; the transistors were arranged in such a way and energized in a given pattern that caused the computer to make that claim. Appeals to mental events are not only not required, they are superfluous to the transistor's function and by extension, to the computer's function. We can't know the computer had a phenomenal experience because we can understand everything about what it does by understanding the circuitry and the physical states and inputs.

I think they're trying to claim that the mental state can cause a memory somehow and that's incorrect. That concept disagrees with the definition of epiphenomenalism taken by Rosenberg and Gomes. Check the paper by Gomes for further explanation.
 
  • #101
Q_Goest said:
Appeals to mental events are not only not required, they are superfluous to the transistor's function and by extension, to the computer's function.

Of course, computers are a terrible analogy to a conscious biological system. One is predictable, and scale-segregated (we separate noise from signal to fit the computer's operations to abstract human definitions with logic gates) and it waits for instructions to do anything

The other is spontaneous and irregular. It's behavior follows exponentially diverging trajectories (i.e. it's chaotic) when compared to a minimally perturbed clone. It wasn't designed, but emerged from nature, in the wake of several different uncorrelated perturbations. It requires several parallel redundancies to be built throughout the system for it to persist in the first place.

If the system is to correlate particularly relevant information (through synchronicity, for instance as per the Varela paper) than we can reason why cognition may have a functional component (though we can agree that cognition is not important to immediate survival, it's function is geared towards long-term survival).

We can't know the computer had a phenomenal experience because we can understand everything about what it does by understanding the circuitry and the physical states and inputs.


For a computer, I agree. But with biological systems, particularly humans, we have the special treat of having the experience of consciousness and we have developed language to communicate about it. From birth, we can read each others facial expressions and body language (and even that of other mammals). This is only possible because there is a consistent relationship between the kind of stress on an organism and the muscle groups associated with them.

The muscle groups are correlated by interneurons that take central pattern generators (CPGs) and inputs (that either interact with the CPG or the motor pool itself, or booth). The CPG is something that developed over an evolutionary history, while the inputs are representative of the current moment for the organism. The interneurons allow input patterns to be associated with meaningful outputs.

Now, with all the knowledge of functional anatomy and mere "circuitry" (circuitry is, of course, and oversimplification) I can affect mental states in predictable ways by making physical alterations. The more I know about the receptor diversity of a particular physical circuit (and given the appropriate drugs) the more precisely I can target only the receptor variations that participate in a particular functional effect I want you to experience.

Furthermore, I can target particular experiences you don't want to feel and remove them from your experiences without removing the kinds of experiences you'd like to remain?

Which is why this is incorrect:

Knowing how and why every observable molecule in the brain does what it does says nothing about our subjective experience and never will because explaining interactions are the wrong kind of explanations to look for when explaining subjective phenomena.
 
  • #102
PhizzicsPhan said:
How do you know I'm conscious? How do I know you're conscious? We don't. We infer it. The ONLY thing we know is our own consciousness. Literally. All else is inference. So we can infer that electrons have an extremely rudimentary consciousness, as Dyson and Bohm (and many other panpsychists) did, but we can never know this is so. It's all about what conceptual framework best explains the evidence.
What property of electrons do you believe suggests rudimentary consciousness? The non-locality or non-separability implied by QM? With objects like ourselves we have a conception via introspection to make inferences with other objects similar to us but that is not the case when trying to compare proto-mental electrons versus non-mental electrons.

I believe Chalmers makes this point when he argues:

Of course it would be very desirable to form a positive conception of protophenomenal properties. Perhaps we can do this indirectly, by some sort of theoretical inference from the character of phenomenal properties to their underlying constituents.

I think that’s a really good proposal but what are some of those protophenomenal conceptions that we can infer from the character of phenomenal properties?
 
Last edited:
  • #103
bohm2, as with all inferences about other consciousnesses we make such inferences based on observed behavior, including movement, speech, etc. In the case of non-human consciousnesses, obviously the repertoire of behaviors doesn't include speech. Dyson's point, which I agree with, is that it makes more sense to ascribe a very rudimentary consciousness to electrons and other simple structures, on up the chain to us, because even these subatomic particles display behavior that suggests consciousness. As Dyson states, instead of ascribing such behavior to chance (the traditional QM interpretation, which is based on probabilistic predictions because predictions in any given instance are not possible due to the chance/choice nature of each instance), it makes more sense to ascribe such behavior to choice. So choice not chance. Chance is the modern idol in scientific explanations. Where we don't understand something it's presumed to be chance. However, in the panpsychist view of the world, it's choice not chance that pervades reality.

Again, Skrbina's Panpsychism in the West is a great introduction to these ideas.
 
  • #104
What does it mean to "know you have a toothache"? Could you have a toothache and not know it? Could you be in pain and not be aware of it?
 
  • #105
To know you have a headache is to have that realm of sense-data accessible to the dominant consciousness that you call "you." Pain could certainly exist in the body and not be accessible to the dominant consciousness - during local anesthesia for example. Under a holonic view of consciousness, each natural individual has its own sensations and is part of a hierarchy. In humans, what we call our conscious self is at the top of this hierarchy.
 

Similar threads

Back
Top