Is quantum weirdness really weird?

In summary, the experts seem to believe that there are rational explanations for much of the weirdness in quantum mechanics, while many of the non-specialist popular authors seem to focus on the weirdness itself.
  • #106
PeterDonis said:
Please specify what mathematical assumption this is.

@rubi defined the mathematical assumption of "counterfactual definiteness" above:

rubi said:
It means that you can assign values to unperformed measurements. Mathematically, it's just the requirement that you have functions ##O_\xi : \Lambda\rightarrow \mathbb R## from the space ##\Lambda## of states to the real numbers for all possible measurements ##\xi##. If you want to prove Bell's theorem, it's enough to have these functions for all spin measurements ##\xi=(\text{Alice},\alpha)## of Alice and ##\xi=(\text{Bob},\beta)## for Bob. (Concretely, this means that the functions ##A(\alpha,\lambda)## and ##B(\beta,\lambda)## exist.)

Except in this case we're using four RV's (for CHSH inequality):

rubi said:
Yes, you can prove Bell-type inequalities for general random variables in a probability space. For example let ##A,B,C,D:\Lambda\rightarrow\{-1,1\}##. Then it is easy to show that ##\left|A(\lambda)B(\lambda)+A(\lambda)C(\lambda)+B(\lambda)D(\lambda)-C(\lambda)D(\lambda)\right|\leq 2##. Thus ##\left|\left<AB\right>+\left<AC\right>+\left<BD\right>-\left<CD\right>\right|\leq 2##.

So in this case it means that you can assume there exist definite values for all four RVs in each run of the experiment, even though you don't actually measure all of them.
 
  • Like
Likes Zafa Pi
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #107
rubi said:
I don't know a proof of the inequality that doesn't assume counterfactual definiteness.

I was asking about the assumption of locality in the particular question you responded to here.
 
  • #108
secur said:
@rubi defined the mathematical assumption of "counterfactual definiteness" above

Ah, ok, I had missed that.
 
  • #109
A. Neumaier said:
The sources have properties independent of measurement, and the beams have properties independent of measurement. These are the real players and the real objects.

I have no idea what you mean by this - especially not these days where manipulation and measurement of single quantum 'entities' is commonplace.

I think you're using 'properties' in a different sense than I was too.

Let's take the situation where we have a 2 level atom in its excited state fired through a high-Q cavity in which there is a vacuum. There's a 'beam' I guess, but it consists of just one atom. If we tailor the cavity flight time right the atom and field are going to be in an entangled state when the atom has left the cavity (if we send another 2 level atom in its ground state through with a different tailored flight time we can end up with atom 1 and atom 2 entangled and these kinds of experiments have been done).

In this case I don't see how the notion of 'beams' helps us understand the properties of the 2 entangled entities (one's an atom and one's a field, or in the second case we have 2 entangled atoms). Nor do I see how any subsequent correlation measurements (obviously we need to repeat the experiment lots of times) are going to be explicable by assuming some collection of variables (properties) that have an existence independent of measurement.

I don't think it matters that we begin with the atom and field in some definite (pure) states - which have some definite properties granted. If we assume that any collection of such definite properties (variables) that have an existence independent of measurement is sufficient to describe the subsequent atom-field interaction and resulting state of the overall system then we're not going to be able to construct a model that matches the experimental results.

The fact that there is no way to fully describe this using these kinds of 'realistic' properties means that this entangled entity (consisting of the atom and field, or the 2 atoms) does not possesses some of these properties independent of measurement.

So we've gone from a classical situation in which the assumption that things can be described by a collection of variables - even if we have to treat those variables statistically because we don't know their value - to the quantum situation where it's not even legitimate to think in these terms. There's no way we can replace QM with an 'ignorance' model; we can't say "oh the properties or variables exist but we just don't know them".

So the very properties we measure in experiments are inextricably bound with the measurement. Those properties, or variables, aren't 'there' just waiting to be discovered by the measurement - in a real sense they're not 'there' at all until we do the measurement.

I like the intro to Feynman's classic path integral paper in which he shows that the classical law for chaining conditional probabilities gets mapped to the same law but now applied to amplitudes in QM - he draws conclusions about the existence of 'properties' from this and I've always seen that as a kind of pre-cursor to Bell's treatment.

My view is that this is just one feature of the 'weirdness' of QM. Same 'probability' laws but now applied to amplitudes - I can't explain that in any satisfactory way other than to say "them there's the rules - get over it".

Another point of weirdness is the fact that in classical mechanics we can have two phase space points, arbitrarily close together, that we can always in principle distinguish. Distinguishability in QM is characterized by orthogonality and there's a sense in which two non-orthogonal states can 'mimic' each other with a certain probability. Can I explain this other than by saying "them there's the rules - get over it"? Nope.

If anyone else can then I'd love to be enlightened.
 
  • #110
rubi said:
It means that you can assign values to unperformed measurements. Mathematically, it's just the requirement that you have functions ##O_\xi : \Lambda\rightarrow \mathbb R## from the space ##\Lambda## of states to the real numbers for all possible measurements ##\xi##. If you want to prove Bell's theorem, it's enough to have these functions for all spin measurements ##\xi=(\text{Alice},\alpha)## of Alice and ##\xi=(\text{Bob},\beta)## for Bob. (Concretely, this means that the functions ##A(\alpha,\lambda)## and ##B(\beta,\lambda)## exist.)

I don't know a proof of the inequality that doesn't assume counterfactual definiteness.
Any scientific model has to make predictions. Doesn't it follow that any scientific model has to include some form counterfactual definiteness?
 
  • #111
A. Neumaier said:
Yes, that was me...
Thank you...
Carry on.
 
  • #112
ljagerman said:
I like a simplistic approach to "weirdness" in quantum mechanics, particularly when teaching amateur scientists. The big three weirdnesses are (1) the uncertainty principle, (2) wave-particle duality, and (3) entanglement.
1: Everything in the universe, notably subatomic particles, and always in at least some random motion. So if we try to pin down location, momentum is uncertain, and vice versa.
2: Particles are particles, but their locations in space-time may be wave-like if graphed or plotted. I.e., the waves in this duality are waves of probability in the behavior of particles.
3: Two entangled particles may show interdependent behavior, but that behavior is always, to at least some extent, uncertain. So only probabilities are entangled, not firm unequivocal information. Also, there may be more than four dimensions, and entangled particles may be immediately adjacent in one of those additional dimensions.
Of course, if you present QT like this, it's weird. The uncertainty principle is a quite straight-forward consequence of the structure of quantum theory. It's a mathematical consequence. Item (2) is a no-brainer since there is no wave-particle duality in quantum theory for more than 90 years by now. Fortunately we don't teach Aristotelian physics anymore to our high schoolers and university freshmen anymore. We also shouldn't teach "old quantum theory" anymore (or only in a class about the history of physics, which is a very interesting and important subject by itself but shouldn't be used as didactics to teach QT).

That leaves entanglement, and that's indeed a pretty amazing consequence of the formalism of QT we are unused to in everyday life. Here you need to get the concepts straight, particularly a good grasp of probability theory and the important difference between correlations and causal effects. Unfortunately this subject is presented wrong in almost all popular-science writings about QT. The trouble is that many popular-science authors like to present QT as weird, because they think this makes the subject more interesting for the readers, but it does no good in offering what's really done in the physics labs around the world for laymen. Rather one should try to tell the public what's really done in the labs and what's found in experimental and theoretical research!
 
  • #113
vanhees71 said:
The uncertainty principle is a quite straight-forward consequence of the structure of quantum theory. It's a mathematical consequence.

That's true - but lots of things in QM could be described as "straightforward consequences" of the formalism. I have never equated dicking about with formalism as being equivalent to 'understanding' - that's a very 'recipe' driven approach. Ultimately, and frustratingly for me, it may be all we can actually get from QM. We spend a lot of time learning classical physics and much of it is pretty intuitive, but I don't have the same kind of intuition when it comes to QM. I've had to learn a different kind of intuition when it comes to QM that mostly derives from the formalism and using the formalism. So I have an intuition about the formalism and how to use it but I have no real intuitive feel for what that formalism actually means in a 'physical' sense (OK that's vague I know but I hope you get the drift).

That's not a very satisfactory state of affairs, for me at least. Can I explain why we have to represent 'states' using an abstract mathematical object that might ultimately bear no relation to 'reality' but is just some abstract mathematical device we use to kind of update our 'probabilities' (or more accurately pre-probabilities)? I don't really have a good feel for why this should be so. Can I explain why the conditional probability chaining rule gets applied to amplitudes in QM and what that really means? I don't even have any idea how to think of that as being natural and 'obvious' - other than saying that's just how it is. Often things become 'natural' and 'obvious' when viewed from the right perspective - I don't think that 'right' perspective exists in QM just yet (except for large systems or ensembles where largely 'classical' thinking can be applied).

On the one hand we have the macroscopic classical world which can be described by a set of fairly intuitive laws or axioms - and these laws are all, to some greater or lesser extent reasonably intuitive. But underneath all of this is this quantum substrate from which these 'intuitive' laws and behaviours arise, almost certainly through decoherence. But the laws governing this quantum substrate are not at all intuitive to my mind. They are simply a recipe that must be learned from which we eventually gain a kind intuition about how it works through use and practice.

There is, of course, no reason why nature should behave according to a set of laws that appear 'intuitive' to our evolution-conditioned brains. Ultimately we have this picture in which underneath it all is this substrate that has to be described more in terms of potentialities from which our macroscopic world of actualities emerges. I think that's quite strange - but maybe it's not to some. The underlying quantum world seems somehow insubstantial and we only connect to it through measurement (or environmental 'measurement' perhaps).

If we consider a 'particle' in a box (maybe an ion in a trap, for example) then to ask what its momentum is, without reference to measurement, is meaningless. Not only that, to assume that it actually possesses some value for this momentum is incorrect because not only is that tantamount to assuming a hidden-variable description for QM, it also implies that the classical chain rule can be applied to the probabilities of those values. That could all certainly be described as a very straightforward consequence of the formalism.

I've seen lots of posts on these forums from (I assume) interested non-professionals trying to get a grasp of what QM means. Ultimately we can't satisfy them; the only answer we give essentially boils down to "learn the maths and the formalism". I wish we could do better :-)

Maybe all I'm saying is that the formalism isn't 'enough' for me. I get the feeling that I'm in the minority here :frown:
 
  • Like
Likes OCR, vanhees71 and Nugatory
  • #114
PeterDonis said:
I was asking about the assumption of locality in the particular question you responded to here.
See my post #100.

zonde said:
Any scientific model has to make predictions. Doesn't it follow that any scientific model has to include some form counterfactual definiteness?
No, because a model can make predictions about what happens without predicting what would have happened. That's the case in QM. The Kochen-Specker theorem excludes the possibility for these functions ##O_\xi## to exist. The value of the observable ##\hat O_1## depends on what other commuting observables ##\hat O_\xi## are measured simultaneously. Hence, ##\hat O_\xi## cannot possibly be modeled as functions on some state space, because the value of an ordinary function doesn't depend on what other functions you're looking at. If you give me a certain ##\lambda##, then ##O_1(\lambda)## will always be the same number, no matter what other ##O_\xi(\lambda)## I care to compute.
 
  • #115
ljagerman said:
The big three weirdnesses are (1) the uncertainty principle,
A similar uncertainty principle holds already in classical mechanics. Do you find it weird that one cannot resolve an oscillating signal arbitrarily well both in time and in frequency? If not, why do you find the same relation weird between position and momentum?
 
  • #116
Simon Phoenix said:
I think you're using 'properties' in a different sense than I was too.
You are talking about a different concept of 'object' than I. Thus you get weirdness where I get meaning.

It is somewhat inconsistent to cling to a weird philosophy of what an object is and at the same time complain that the result is weirdness.

Also you changed subject, whereas I was responding to your example of laser light and parametric downconversion.
 
Last edited:
  • #117
Nugatory said:
How does this compare with the EPR criterion: "A sufficient condition for the reality of a physical quantity is the possibility of predicting it with certainty, without disturbing the system"?

A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, Phys. Rev. 47 (1935), 777-781
defined the so-called EPR criterion verbatim as follows:
EPR said:
If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity.

I just added a slightly polished version of my contributions in this thread, including this quote, to my thermal interpretation FAQ.
 
  • #118
Simon Phoenix said:
Can I explain why we have to represent 'states' using an abstract mathematical object that might ultimately bear no relation to 'reality' but is just some abstract mathematical device we use to kind of update our 'probabilities' (or more accurately pre-probabilities)? I don't really have a good feel for why this should be so. Can I explain why the conditional probability chaining rule gets applied to amplitudes in QM and what that really means? I don't even have any idea how to think of that as being natural and 'obvious' - other than saying that's just how it is. Often things become 'natural' and 'obvious' when viewed from the right perspective
In my view the right perspective is given by my thermal interpretation of QM; see the link in my preceding post. At least I find nothing weird in it.

I abstracted this interpretation from paying attention to what I saw the majority of physicists actually do in their papers on applications of quantum mechanics (mostly in the shut-up-and-calculate mode), rather than listening to what the minority of physicists writing about quantum interpretations think about these issues. It made a huge difference! The latter had left me unsatisfied for many years...
 
  • #119
rubi said:
No, because a model can make predictions about what happens without predicting what would have happened.
Please explain or give simple example.
My position is that we use the model exactly the same way whether we ask "what will happen?" or we ask "what would have happened?". It's exactly the same input for the model and therefore it has to produce exactly the same output.
 
  • #120
zonde said:
My position is that we use the model exactly the same way whether we ask "what will happen?" or we ask "what would have happened?". It's exactly the same input for the model and therefore it has to produce exactly the same output.
That only works in models whose predictions are computed by functions that are defined on some state space. This is exactly not the case in QM.

Assume we have a model whose predictions are computed by functions ##O_\xi :\Lambda\rightarrow\mathbb R##. Then we can add these functions and multiply them as follows: ##(O_\xi + O_\zeta)(\lambda) := O_\xi(\lambda) + O_\zeta(\lambda)## and ##(O_\xi O_\zeta)(\lambda) := O_\xi(\lambda) O_\zeta(\lambda)##
Given some element ##\lambda\in\Lambda##, we can define define the evaluation map ##v_\lambda## that takes a function ##O_\xi## and evaluates it at ##\lambda##: ##v_\lambda(O_\xi) := O_\xi(\lambda)##
It is now easy to prove that ##v_\lambda(O_\xi + O_\zeta) = v_\lambda(O_\xi) + v_\lambda(O_\zeta)## and ##v_\lambda(O_\xi O_\zeta) = v_\lambda(O_\xi) v_\lambda(O_\zeta)##. We take these identities as the definining identities for an evaluation map.

In quantum mechanics, observables aren't functions ##O_\xi : \Lambda\rightarrow\mathbb R##, but rather operators ##\hat O_\xi## that are defined on a Hilbert space. We can now ask ourselves whether this is just an artifact of the formulation. It turns out that it is impossible to reformulate the theory in the previous language. If it were possible to map the operators ##\hat O_\xi## to ordinary functions ##O_\xi## on some state space ##\Lambda##, then there would be evaluation maps ##v## such that at least for commuting ##\hat O_\xi##, the defining identities of such evaluation maps would be satisfied, i.e. for commuting ##\hat O_\xi##, ##\hat O_\zeta##, we would have ##v(\hat O_\xi + \hat O_\zeta) = v(\hat O_\xi) + v(\hat O_\zeta)## and ##v(\hat O_\xi \hat O_\zeta) = v(\hat O_\xi) v(\hat O_\zeta)##. The Kochen-Specker theorem tells us that no such evaluation map ##v## exists. However, if the ##\hat O_\xi## could be mapped to ordinary functions on some state space ##\Lambda##, there would be plenty of these evaluation maps: One for every ##\lambda\in\Lambda##. Thus, not all quantum mechanical observables ##\hat O_\xi## can be represented as ordinary functions ##O_\xi:\Lambda\rightarrow \mathbb R## on some state space ##\Lambda##. Hence, QM violates counterfactual definiteness.

The simplest example of this is the GHZ state. See also http://www.phy.pku.edu.cn/~qiongyihe/content/download/3-2.pdf.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #121
Simon Phoenix said:
I've seen lots of posts on these forums from (I assume) interested non-professionals trying to get a grasp of what QM means. Ultimately we can't satisfy them; the only answer we give essentially boils down to "learn the maths and the formalism". I wish we could do better :-)

Maybe all I'm saying is that the formalism isn't 'enough' for me. I get the feeling that I'm in the minority here :frown:
Well, the danger of investigating nature in realms what are not immediately available to our everyday experience is that you have to change your view of the world and your intuition about it. Indeed, with QT we "zoom" into the smallest structures of matter our senses are unable to register without the help of technology. It's not surprising that this reveals a totally different structure than what we are used to in the macroscopic world that is directly senseable without technical aids. What you describe concerning your experience is precisely what the natural sciences are after: You observe nature and try to find a mathematical description of it, and this leads to intuition. The amazing thing is, how far this concept to comprehend the "inner workings" of nature leads in a pretty successful way. We are able to describe structures down to some femto meters with one pretty clear concept called quantum theory, and there's no hint that this theory is invalid at any point. The ability to formulate such a comprehensive mathematical theory and to apply the abstract findings within this theory to the real world, use it to construct all kinds of further technology and invent new experiments to investigate it even further shows that we've built already a pretty good understanding, if not intuition, for what goes on at a 15 orders of magnitude smaller scale than what is graspable by our bare senses!

That's amazing enough, and there's no need to invoke additional weirdness to make it interesting to the lay man. Of course, you cannot explain Hilbert space formalism and group-representation theory to everybody, but you can, in a qualitative way explain the results of this abstract thinking and the resulting practical experiments, observation, and finally technology forming more and more our daily life. E.g., the laptop I'm using right now to type this posting is just a very real thing originating from such abstract theories as electrodynamics (Maxwell 1865) and quantum theory applies to semiconductor materials (Born, Jordan, Heisenberg; Schrödinger; Dirac 1925/26)! The very possibility to do this, would have been very "weird" even to a 19th century engineer, but nowadays any kid can use it. I think that's the way one should think about the results of fundamental research in the natural sciences and not present it as some weird magic!
 
  • Like
Likes Simon Phoenix
  • #122
Zafa Pi said:
Bell's inequality is the result of Bell's theorem. Experiments show Bell's inequality is not valid. Thus there must be some part of the hypothesis of Bell's theorem that is not valid. What do you think it is?
It's locality assumption that does not hold.
 
  • #123
rubi said:
That only works in models whose predictions are computed by functions that are defined on some state space. This is exactly not the case in QM.

Assume we have a model whose predictions are computed by functions ##O_\xi :\Lambda\rightarrow\mathbb R##. Then we can add these functions and multiply them as follows: ##(O_\xi + O_\zeta)(\lambda) := O_\xi(\lambda) + O_\zeta(\lambda)## and ##(O_\xi O_\zeta)(\lambda) := O_\xi(\lambda) O_\zeta(\lambda)##
Given some element ##\lambda\in\Lambda##, we can define define the evaluation map ##v_\lambda## that takes a function ##O_\xi## and evaluates it at ##\lambda##: ##v_\lambda(O_\xi) := O_\xi(\lambda)##
It is now easy to prove that ##v_\lambda(O_\xi + O_\zeta) = v_\lambda(O_\xi) + v_\lambda(O_\zeta)## and ##v_\lambda(O_\xi O_\zeta) = v_\lambda(O_\xi) v_\lambda(O_\zeta)##. We take these identities as the definining identities for an evaluation map.

In quantum mechanics, observables aren't functions ##O_\xi : \Lambda\rightarrow\mathbb R##, but rather operators ##\hat O_\xi## that are defined on a Hilbert space. We can now ask ourselves whether this is just an artifact of the formulation. It turns out that it is impossible to reformulate the theory in the previous language. If it were possible to map the operators ##\hat O_\xi## to ordinary functions ##O_\xi## on some state space ##\Lambda##, then there would be evaluation maps ##v## such that at least for commuting ##\hat O_\xi##, the defining identities of such evaluation maps would be satisfied, i.e. for commuting ##\hat O_\xi##, ##\hat O_\zeta##, we would have ##v(\hat O_\xi + \hat O_\zeta) = v(\hat O_\xi) + v(\hat O_\zeta)## and ##v(\hat O_\xi \hat O_\zeta) = v(\hat O_\xi) v(\hat O_\zeta)##. The Kochen-Specker theorem tells us that no such evaluation map ##v## exists. However, if the ##\hat O_\xi## could be mapped to ordinary functions on some state space ##\Lambda##, there would be plenty of these evaluation maps: One for every ##\lambda\in\Lambda##. Thus, not all quantum mechanical observables ##\hat O_\xi## can be represented as ordinary functions ##O_\xi:\Lambda\rightarrow \mathbb R## on some state space ##\Lambda##. Hence, QM violates counterfactual definiteness.

The simplest example of this is the GHZ state. See also http://www.phy.pku.edu.cn/~qiongyihe/content/download/3-2.pdf.
Sorry I don't follow you. How replacing function with operator changes my argument? You take something as an input (be it vector or variable) and get something as output. And your motivation for making this calculation is not an input for the calculation(calculation doesn't care if you want to know "what will happen?" or "what would have happened?").
 
  • #124
zonde said:
Sorry I don't follow you. How replacing function with operator changes my argument?
I believe I have explained it in a crystal clear way. If you still don't understand it, I'm afraid, I can't help.

You take something as an input (be it vector or variable) and get something as output.
Please be more specific. We are working with quantum mechanics. What do you take as input and how are you going to calculate the predictions? How do you simultaneously calculate the value of spin in ##x## direction and spin in ##z## direction? You will find that the quantum mechanical formalism doesn't allow you to do it. Show your calculation, so we can point out your mistake.

And your motivation for making this calculation is not an input for the calculation(calculation doesn't care if you want to know "what will happen?" or "what would have happened?").
I don't understand this sentence.
 
  • #125
zonde said:
It's locality assumption that does not hold.
That is certainly one option. That's what Bohm proposed. However, if one wishes to accept that there is no faster than light communication, i.e. locality holds (which seems to be a majority opinion/interpretation) then one is left with giving up counterfactual definiteness, which for the Bell business is the same as realism, or hidden variables, or determinism. I still have not heard of any experiment that can decide the issue, and I personally vacillate.
 
  • #126
At least some (but possibly not all) of what seems weird in QM is the tendency to think of fundamental particles as though they were tiny billiard balls instead of something very different--as though they were property-carrying objects. Perhaps another way of viewing them would permit quantum entanglement, the double-slit experiment's making dots pile up in what looks for all the world like an interference pattern, and so on.

Please do not ask me what that way is.
 
  • #129
rubi said:
I believe I have explained it in a crystal clear way. If you still don't understand it, I'm afraid, I can't help.
Your explanation would make sense if counter-factual definiteness could be understood as simultaneous reality of measurement results with different measurement settings. But this is not the case.
rubi said:
I don't understand this sentence.
I am saying that calculation is exactly the same whether you are calculating "what will happen if I will measure spin along x axis?" or "what would have happened if I would have measured spin along x axis?" as long as starting point (preparation of input state) is described exactly the same way.
 
  • #130
zonde said:
Your link illustrates nicely how some physicist are trying to present QM as weird. Here is arxiv link: https://arxiv.org/abs/0704.2529
And here is criticism of that article: https://arxiv.org/abs/0809.4000

The paper by Tausk is good. He's right, "An experimental test of non-local realism" is flawed in a number of ways. Tausk mentions:

"Below I will present a brief analysis of some possible meanings for hypothesis (1), but let me emphasize that my main point here is that hypothesis (1) is simply not used in the deduction of Leggett’s inequality. It is a bit odd, to say the least, that an article that claims to be doing “an experimental test of non-local realism” is apparently trying to accomplish its goal by verifying the violation of an inequality whose proof does not use the very hypothesis that the authors call “realism”!"

Hypothesis 1 is:

"(1) all measurement outcomes are determined by pre-existing properties of particles independent of the measurement (realism)"

Tausk missed the reason that hypothesis is included. It's found in "APPENDIX I: AN EXPLICIT NON-LOCAL HIDDEN-VARIABLE MODEL" of the Groblacher ... Zeilinger paper:

"We construct an explicit non-local model compliant with the introduced assumptions (1)-(3). It perfectly simulates all quantum mechanical predictions for measurements in a plane of the Poincare sphere. In particular, the violation of any CHSH-type inequality can be explained within the model and, in addition, all perfect correlations state can be recovered."

That hypothesis is necessary not for Leggett inequality but for the task in this appendix, to replicate the CHSH experiment results. It's important to note the model does NOT replicate all QM results, it's carefully tailored for just this class of experiments. As they mention at the bottom of the appendix, "If this relation is not satisfied the model does not recover quantum correlations. ... This is the origin of the incompatibility with general quantum predictions."

What they're trying to do is give the general impression that this non-local model seems to match existing experimental results (but it doesn't) and they've disproven that "myth" with the Leggett inequality. Thus devaluing the fact that non-locality is important in Bell-type experiments.

Finally, I'd appreciate it if someone could explain this sentence from appendix 1:

"Therefore, in the next step, one must find the conditions for which both x1 and x2 take values from [0, 1] and x1 and x2 take values from [0, 1]."

Probably just a typo but I can't figure out what they meant to say.
 
  • #131
zonde said:
Your explanation would make sense if counter-factual definiteness could be understood as simultaneous reality of measurement results with different measurement settings. But this is not the case.
I gave a mathematical definition of counterfactual definiteness in my post #97. My post #120 then proves that it is violated by QM. It's irrelevant what vague words we choose to describe the definition. What matters is the mathematical definition, which appears in Bell's proof and is not satisfied by QM.

I am saying that calculation is exactly the same whether you are calculating "what will happen if I will measure spin along x axis?" or "what would have happened if I would have measured spin along x axis?" as long as starting point (preparation of input state) is described exactly the same way.
In QM, you neither calculate "what will happen" nor "what would have happened". The theory allows only probabilistic predictions. Nevertheless, we can show that these probabilistic predictions must be incompatible with counterfactual definiteness.

zonde said:
Your link illustrates nicely how some physicist are trying to present QM as weird. Here is arxiv link: https://arxiv.org/abs/0704.2529
And here is criticism of that article: https://arxiv.org/abs/0809.4000
Among the list of authors of the first paper are some of the most highly respected living scientists like Anton Zeilinger and Markus Aspelmeyer. The second paper doesn't seem to be accepted for publication and it's author isn't even affiliated with an university.
 
  • #132
zonde said:
Your explanation would make sense if counter-factual definiteness could be understood as simultaneous reality of measurement results with different measurement settings. But this is not the case.

It's not important how we define "counter-factual definiteness", but "simultaneous reality of measurement results with different measurement settings" is, I think, exactly the point. It's necessary to assume this, to prove Bell-type inequalities like CHSH. Of course, they're violated in reality, because this assumption is not true. Therefore, BTW, it appears you've understood rubi's explanation correctly - if we ignore the sentence "But this is not the case".

rubi said:
Among the list of authors of the first paper are some of the most highly respected living scientists like Anton Zeilinger and Markus Aspelmeyer. The second paper doesn't seem to be accepted for publication and it's author isn't even affiliated with an university.

What matters is how good a paper is, not how good its authors are.
 
  • #133
secur said:
It's not important how we define "counter-factual definiteness", but "simultaneous reality of measurement results with different measurement settings" is, I think, exactly the point. It's necessary to assume this, to prove Bell-type inequalities like CHSH.
Bell does not assume this. He assumes that there is a model that is local (remote measurements are independent) and it can reproduce QM prediction of perfect anticorrelations. From that it follows that in such a model there exist functions ##A_{EPR} :\Theta\rightarrow\mathbb \{-1;1\}## and ##B_{EPR} :\Theta\rightarrow\mathbb \{-1;1\}## such that ##A_{EPR}(\alpha)=-B_{EPR}(\beta)## when ##\alpha=\beta##.

So if we say that additional assumption is needed we have to disagree with Bell on that "it follows" part.
 
  • #134
zonde said:
Bell does not assume this. He assumes that there is a model that is local (remote measurements are independent) and it can reproduce QM prediction of perfect anticorrelations. From that it follows that in such a model there exist functions ##A_{EPR} :\Theta\rightarrow\mathbb \{-1;1\}## and ##B_{EPR} :\Theta\rightarrow\mathbb \{-1;1\}## such that ##A_{EPR}(\alpha)=-B_{EPR}(\beta)## when ##\alpha=\beta##.

So if we say that additional assumption is needed we have to disagree with Bell on that "it follows" part.
No, that doesn't follow. The locality assumption is ##A(\alpha,\beta,\lambda) = A(\alpha,\lambda)##. The EPR argument cannot be used to prove anything, because it is objectively invalid. The GHZ experiment shows that EPR's criterion for elements of reality must be rejected. See http://www.phy.pku.edu.cn/~qiongyihe/content/download/3-2.pdf that I have already posted earlier. The elements of reality that EPR think exist, just do not exist, no matter how intuitive the EPR argument might seem to you.
 
  • #135
zonde said:
Bell does not assume this. He assumes that there is a model that is local (remote measurements are independent) and it can reproduce QM prediction of perfect anticorrelations. From that it follows that in such a model there exist functions ##A_{EPR} :\Theta\rightarrow\mathbb \{-1;1\}## and ##B_{EPR} :\Theta\rightarrow\mathbb \{-1;1\}## such that ##A_{EPR}(\alpha)=-B_{EPR}(\beta)## when ##\alpha=\beta##.

So if we say that additional assumption is needed we have to disagree with Bell on that "it follows" part.

I didn't mean to disagree with Bell! To me, he's one of the good guys. So let me just say that with counterfactual definiteness, more or less as you stated it, we can demonstrate CHSH inequality. We could either assume CD, or else derive it from other assumptions, as (you apparently say) Bell did.
 
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #136
rubi said:
No, that doesn't follow.
I don't wan to go in long offtopic discussion, so I will end it here.
 
  • #137
zonde said:
I don't wan to go in long offtopic discussion, so I will end it here.
You don't get away with spreading unscientific claims like this. What you really don't want to do is to refrain from stubbornly denying established scientific facts. If the EPR argument was sound, then it should be straightforward for you to explain why the GHZ experiment didn't invalidate it. Neither would it be offtopic in a thread like this, nor would it take a long discussion. If your claim were a fact, you would be able to provide a mathematical proof and it would take no longer than one post to convince everyone. Apparently, you can't do that.
 
  • #138
rubi said:
You don't get away with spreading unscientific claims like this. What you really don't want to do is to refrain from stubbornly denying established scientific facts.
I am certainly ready to discuss this topic in separate thread.
rubi said:
If the EPR argument was sound, then it should be straightforward for you to explain why the GHZ experiment didn't invalidate it.
Because measurements of entangled particles are not independent.
rubi said:
If your claim were a fact, you would be able to provide a mathematical proof and it would take no longer than one post to convince everyone.
Which claim? And I don't see how anything in physics can take one post to convince everyone. Unless you mean a post with couple of references to model, prediction and subsequent experiment falsifying that prediction and model. That should convince everyone that particular model is false.
 
  • #139
zonde said:
I am certainly ready to discuss this topic in separate thread.
You aren't supposed to discuss it. You are just supposed to present evidence in form of a mathematical proof of your claim. That would fit in just one post and you could already have done it if it were possible. Do you realize that this is a completely hopeless endeavour, since there exist several accepted interpretations of QM that are known to be local?

Because measurements of entangled particles are not independent.
Even if that were the case, it would still be completely irrelevant to the EPR argument, since you can only predict the value of the remote spin with certainty after you performed the measurement and you wouldn't disturb it anymore afterwards. Therefore, if the EPR argument was valid, there would have to be a corresponding element of reality, which the GHZ experiment proves to not exist.

Which claim?
The claim that the EPR argument allows you to prove the existence of functions ##A,B:\Lambda\rightarrow\mathbb R##.

And I don't see how anything in physics can take one post to convince everyone. Unless you mean a post with couple of references to model, prediction and subsequent experiment falsifying that prediction and model. That should convince everyone that particular model is false.
Mathematical proofs are usually short and can be presented in just a few paragraphs. If the steps are performed correctly, then the proof automatically convinces everyone who understands the involved mathematics. If the proof is longer than just a few paragraphs, then either it is published in a journal or it would be a personal theory, which would violate the rules of PF. So please just show us how you formulate the EPR argument mathematically and how you deduce the existence of the functions ##A## and ##B## from it.
 
  • #140
rubi said:
Do you realize that this is a completely hopeless endeavour, since there exist several accepted interpretations of QM that are known to be local?
It seems you are referring to this post of mine, right?
zonde said:
It's locality assumption that does not hold.
If that's the case, then you have probably misunderstood me. The question was "What do you think it is?" and I meant to answer "I think, it's locality assumption that does not hold.". I thought that given the context (question) it will be clear. But I should be more careful.

I am certainly aware that it can't be "proved" that it's locality assumption that does not hold. What I think is possible is to critically examine other options and check if they are acceptable from perspective of scientific method. So if you have something to discuss along these lines I might join in.

I will answer other points in your post later.
 
Back
Top