- #1
Ackbach
Gold Member
MHB
- 4,155
- 92
So far in Landau, we've covered the following:
Axiom 0: The "equals sign" is an equivalence relation (reflexive, commutative, and transitive).
Axiom 1: $1$ is a natural number.
Axiom 2: For each $x$ there exists exactly one natural number, called the successor of $x$, which will be denoted by $x'$. If $x=y$, then $x'=y'$.
Axiom 3: $x'\not=1$.
Axiom 4: If $x'=y'$, then $x=y$.
Axiom 5: Let there be given a set $M$ of natural numbers, with the following properties:
Theorem 1: If $x\not=y$, then $x'\not=y'$.
Theorem 2: $x'\not=x$.
Theorem 3: If $x\not=1$, then there exists a (unique) $u$ such that $x=u'$.
Theorem 4: To every pair of numbers $x,y,$ we may assign in exactly one way a natural number, called $x+y,$ such that
I'm in the proof of Theorem 4, and uniqueness is straight-forward. I'm on existence. You let $M$ be the set of all natural numbers for which it is possible to make this definition. It's straight-forward to show that $1\in M$. I'm trying to show that $(x\in M) \implies (x'\in M)$. So, we get to assume that there exists an $x+y$ for all $y$ such that $x+1=x'$ and $x+y'=(x+y)'$. We need to show that $x'+1=(x')',$ (trivial - by definition) and that $x'+y'=(x'+y)'$. It's this last equation that is giving me conniptions. Landau has the series of equations
$$x'+y'=(x+y')'=((x+y)')'=(x'+y)'.$$
I can see the middle equality - it's by assumption and Axiom 2. But I cannot see why the first equality is true, nor can I see why the last equality is true. That is, why are
\begin{align*}
x'+y'&=(x+y')' \qquad \text{and} \\
((x+y)')'&=(x'+y)'?
\end{align*}
Important point: Associativity is Theorem 5 (proof depends on Theorem 4), and Commutativity is Theorem 6 (proof depends on Theorem 4's proof). So we're not allowed to use associativity or commutativity.
Thanks so much for your time!
Axiom 0: The "equals sign" is an equivalence relation (reflexive, commutative, and transitive).
Axiom 1: $1$ is a natural number.
Axiom 2: For each $x$ there exists exactly one natural number, called the successor of $x$, which will be denoted by $x'$. If $x=y$, then $x'=y'$.
Axiom 3: $x'\not=1$.
Axiom 4: If $x'=y'$, then $x=y$.
Axiom 5: Let there be given a set $M$ of natural numbers, with the following properties:
- $1$ belongs to $M$.
- If $x$ belongs to $M$, then so does $x'$.
Theorem 1: If $x\not=y$, then $x'\not=y'$.
Theorem 2: $x'\not=x$.
Theorem 3: If $x\not=1$, then there exists a (unique) $u$ such that $x=u'$.
Theorem 4: To every pair of numbers $x,y,$ we may assign in exactly one way a natural number, called $x+y,$ such that
- $x+1=x'$ for every $x$, and
- $x+y'=(x+y)'$ for every $x$ and $y$.
I'm in the proof of Theorem 4, and uniqueness is straight-forward. I'm on existence. You let $M$ be the set of all natural numbers for which it is possible to make this definition. It's straight-forward to show that $1\in M$. I'm trying to show that $(x\in M) \implies (x'\in M)$. So, we get to assume that there exists an $x+y$ for all $y$ such that $x+1=x'$ and $x+y'=(x+y)'$. We need to show that $x'+1=(x')',$ (trivial - by definition) and that $x'+y'=(x'+y)'$. It's this last equation that is giving me conniptions. Landau has the series of equations
$$x'+y'=(x+y')'=((x+y)')'=(x'+y)'.$$
I can see the middle equality - it's by assumption and Axiom 2. But I cannot see why the first equality is true, nor can I see why the last equality is true. That is, why are
\begin{align*}
x'+y'&=(x+y')' \qquad \text{and} \\
((x+y)')'&=(x'+y)'?
\end{align*}
Important point: Associativity is Theorem 5 (proof depends on Theorem 4), and Commutativity is Theorem 6 (proof depends on Theorem 4's proof). So we're not allowed to use associativity or commutativity.
Thanks so much for your time!