The thermal interpretation of quantum physics

In summary: I like your summary, but I disagree with the philosophical position you take.In summary, I think Dr Neumaier has a good point - QFT may indeed be a better place for interpretations. I do not know enough of his thermal interpretation to comment on its specifics.
  • #351
stevendaryl said:
I don't. Quantum mechanics in its standard formulation is just inconsistent. As I have said before, it's a "soft" inconsistency.
Why do you say that, in what sense it is soft.
Just saw your post thanks. Ignore.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #352
stevendaryl said:
There is no need for the Born rule to apply to all observables; it is enough to apply it to macroscopic observables.
Now I remember your other post that you elaborated on this point. But isn't still you need to explain the wavefunction since it is a pre-measurement entity. I think this problem is related to physics where usually we define variable as related to some physical character, but psi is an after thought ( maybe it is correct we are forced into it, maybe the model is simply awkward).
 
  • #353
ftr said:
Why do you say that, in what sense it is soft.

Let's suppose that we have a measuring device that starts off in some start state, ##S_0##. It measures an electron's spin along the z-axis, and if it measures spin-up, it makes a transition to the state ##S_{up}##, and if it measures spin-down, it makes a transition to the state ##S_{down}##. Let ##S_{other}## be some third state of the measuring device.

Now, suppose we prepare the electron so that it's in a superposition of spin-up (with amplitude ##\alpha##) and spin-down (with amplitude ##\beta##). We want to compute the probability that the measuring device winds up in state ##S_{other}##.

We can first compute amplitudes, and then square them to get probabilities. Let ##\phi_{up, other}## be the amplitude for the device to transition from state ##S_{up}## to state ##S_{other}##. let ##\phi_{down, other}## be the amplitude to transition from ##S_{down}## to ##S_{other}##. Then the amplitude for the device to end up in state ##S_{other}## is given by:

##\chi_{other} = \alpha \phi_{up, other} + \beta \phi_{\beta, other}##

The probability is the absolute square of the amplitude, so the probability of ending up in state ##S_{other}## is:

##|\chi_{other}|^2 = |\alpha|^2 |\phi_{up, other}|^2 + |\beta|^2 |\phi_{down, other}|^2 + \alpha^* \phi_{up, other}^* \beta \phi_{down, other} + \alpha \phi_{up, other} \beta^* \phi_{down, other}^*##

If we define ##P_{other} = |\chi_{other}|^2##, ##P_{up, other} = |\alpha|^2 |\phi_{up, other}|^2 ##, ##P_{down, other} = |\beta|^2 |\phi_{down, other}|^2## and ##I = \alpha^* \phi_{up, other}^* \beta \phi_{down, other} + \alpha \phi_{up, other} \beta^* \phi_{down, other}^*##, then this becomes:

##P_{other} = P_{up, other} + P_{down, other} + I##

where ##I## is an interference term between the two intermediate possibilities.

This amounts to applying the Born rule only at the end. On the other hand, if we apply the Born rule at the point of measurement, then we get:

##P_{other} = P_{up, other} + P_{down, other}##

(without the ##I##). So saying that the Born rule applies to every measurement gives a different answer for probabilities than if you only apply the Born rule at the end. That's a contradiction, it seems to me.

On the other hand, the difference between the two predictions is the interference term ##I##. Interference terms between macroscopically distinct configurations are practically impossible to measure. It's impossible to calculate, in the first place, and is likely to be completely negligible.

So the contradiction is that there are two different ways to compute a probability, and they give different values. But it's a soft contradiction in the sense that those two different values are neglibly different.
 
  • #354
DrDu said:
The articles are very interesting. Nevertheless I do not like the style, especially of paper I.
It insinuates that there is only one universal "traditional" way of learning QM which follows the steps listed in 5.2.
Although it is more than 30 years now that I learned QM, this was certainly not the way I learned it.
Thanks for your critique. This section was kind of a caricature. Of course, not everyone is exposed to everything mentioned, also the order may be quite different. Nevertheless, one comes across all this stuff sooner or later when one is doing enough quantum mechanics.

I learned quantum mechanics not in a course but by self-teaching from books and later, articles. Certainly all these things puzzled me when I encountered them, and it took me a long time to figure out how to think of all this in a coherent way.
 
  • #355
stevendaryl said:
No, people have been living with this contradiction for nearly 100 years. It doesn't bother them any more.

Asking for an experiment in which a contradiction shows up doesn't make any sense. A contradiction is a property of a theory. The real world can't have any contradictions.
Ok, then tell me what you consider a contradiction. As far as I know there's no intrinsic contradiction in QT at all.
 
  • #356
ftr said:
I think it all boils down to what experiment proves that the position of a particle is an eigenvalue of the corresponding operator. can you name one?
Well, the spectrum of any position operator is ##\mathbb{R}##. I don't think it makes sense to ask this very question in this case since by definition we measure positions with real numbers. It was not me who made the bold claim that there's a contradiction within QT! I don't think that there is one!
 
  • #357
vanhees71 said:
Ok, then tell me what you consider a contradiction. As far as I know there's no intrinsic contradiction in QT at all.

I already told you the contradiction.
  1. On the one hand, the minimal interpretation claims that a measurement of an observable produces a result that is one of the eigenvalues of that observable.
  2. On the other hand, if the system being measured is in a superposition of eigenstates, and we treat the measuring device quantum-mechanically, then the device itself ends up in a superposition of different results.
That's a contradiction. According to 1, the device will end up in one of a number of possible macroscopic states, with probability given by the Born rule. According to 2, the device will definitely end up in a superposition state that is none of those possibilities.
 
  • #358
stevendaryl said:
I already told you the contradiction.
  1. On the one hand, the minimal interpretation claims that a measurement of an observable produces a result that is one of the eigenvalues of that observable.
  2. On the other hand, if the system being measured is in a superposition of eigenstates, and we treat the measuring device quantum-mechanically, then the device itself ends up in a superposition of different results.
That's a contradiction. According to 1, the device will end up in one of a number of possible macroscopic states, with probability given by the Born rule. According to 2, the device will definitely end up in a superposition state that is none of those possibilities.
That's not a contradiction in my opinion, more a sign of possible incompleteness. So if we have the system:
$$\mathcal{H}_t = \mathcal{H}_{s}\otimes\mathcal{H}_{d}\otimes\mathcal{H}_{e}$$
where ##s## is the atomic system, ##d## is the device and ##e## is the entire rest of the lab environment.

A quantum mechanical model will say that the state of the whole system ##|\psi\rangle \in \mathcal{H}_t## is in a superposition after measurement and a superobserver will use such a superposed state.

However to date nobody has produced an actual proof that this is in contradiction with the subsystem ##s + d## being in a definite state. Frauchiger-Renner and Brukner's objectivity theorems are attempts at this, but the consensus by now is that they don't succeed.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #359
DarMM said:
would you say that because a system is in a state for which
$$P\left(S_z = \frac{1}{2}\right) = 1$$
that means the particle in fact already has the spin value of ##S_z = \frac{1}{2}## or does it only mean if you set up an ##S_z## measurement it's guaranteed to produce a specific result?

The answer to this would allow me to know if you're closer to Brukner-Zellinger or others like Haag.
Guaranteed? With probability zero (but still in finitely many of infinitely many cases) it could also have another value, form a purist point of view...
 
  • #360
A. Neumaier said:
Guaranteed? With probability zero (but still in finitely many of infinitely many cases) it could also have another value, form a purist point of view...
It is a discrete outcome space though.
 
Last edited:
  • #361
DarMM said:
Is a discrete outcome space though.
This doesn't help: ##S_z## could still be ##-1/2## in finitely many cases, without affecting the probability (which in statistics is a limiting concept only).
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #362
DarMM said:
However to date nobody has produced an actual proof that this is in contradiction with the subsystem ##s + d## being in a definite state. Frauchiger-Renner and Brukner's objectivity theorems are attempts at this, but the consensus by now is that they don't succeed.

Well, the FR paradox is easily resolved (in my mind) in a number of ways, but every one of those ways means a departure from the minimalist interpretation of quantum mechanics. If you assume that a measurement collapses the wave function, then there is no paradox, because you can't have a superposition of different measurement results. But assuming the collapse of the wave function means a violation of the minimalist interpretation. You can also resolve it by going to Many-Worlds, or by going to the Bohmian interpretation. But you can't resolve it using the minimal interpretation.
 
  • #363
A. Neumaier said:
This doesn't help: ##S_z## could still be ##-1/2## in finitely many cases, without affecting the probability (which in statistics is a limiting concept only).
Quite right.
 
  • #364
DarMM said:
A quantum mechanical model will say that the state of the whole system ##|\psi\rangle \in \mathcal{H}_t## is in a superposition [...]
However to date nobody has produced an actual proof that this is in contradiction with the subsystem ##s + d## being in a definite state.
How could it be theoretically possible that system S plus environment E is in a superposition but system S is in a definite state for some of its observables A? This is surely impossible in a nonsubjective setting, where not subjective knowledge but only objective facts of preparation and measurement count.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #365
A. Neumaier said:
This doesn't help: ##S_z## could still be ##-1/2## in finitely many cases, without affecting the probability (which in statistics is a limiting concept only).
This (embarrassingly obvious to forget!) fact means a view like @vanhees71 would have to view the values as being generated on the spot as opposed to being prepossessed even in the ##P(a) = 1## case for discrete events ##a##. I think at least.
 
  • #366
A. Neumaier said:
How could it be theoretically possible that system S plus environment E is in a superposition but system S is in a definite state for some of its observables A? This is surely impossible in a nonsubjective setting, where not subjective knowledge but only objective facts of preparation and measurement count.
Spekkens toy model provides a nice example in a local classical theory that still has superposition. However in general people have been trying to show there is a contradiction and constantly failing.

It's avoided by the quantum state being epistemic.

I can give some references for the discussion if you wish.
 
  • #367
DarMM said:
It's avoided by the quantum state being epistemic.

I can give some references for the discussion if you wish.
Not needed. I am not interested in epistemic views. For me physics is about objective facts only. The subjective views are compromises that attempt to cope with insufficient understanding.
 
  • #368
A. Neumaier said:
Not needed. I am not interested in epistemic views. For me physics is about objective facts only.
I don't think they're mutually exclusive though. The macrostate in statistical mechanics can be seen as epistemic without the results of statistical mechanics not being objective facts.

The use of epistemic quantities like probability distributions doesn't preclude objective facts, unless I'm missing something.
 
  • #369
DarMM said:
The use of epistemic quantities like probability distributions doesn't preclude objective facts, unless I'm missing something.
You are missing the point mentioned in #373. It means that probability distributions strictly speaking predict nothing at all for any finite number of experiments. This is one of the reasons why one can never get beyond FAPP arguments when starting with irreducible quantum probability.
 
Last edited:
  • #370
stevendaryl said:
Well, the FR paradox is easily resolved (in my mind) in a number of ways, but every one of those ways means a departure from the minimalist interpretation of quantum mechanics. If you assume that a measurement collapses the wave function, then there is no paradox, because you can't have a superposition of different measurement results. But assuming the collapse of the wave function means a violation of the minimalist interpretation. You can also resolve it by going to Many-Worlds, or by going to the Bohmian interpretation. But you can't resolve it using the minimal interpretation.
Perhaps it does require a modification of the minimalist view, I've never been clear on what that really is.

What I mean is that a superposition of the total system is not in contradiction with definite outcomes for subsystems even in Copenhagen or similar views like Healey and Bub, but these probably add things beyond the minimal view such a intervention sensitivity mentioned in Healey's paper.
 
  • #371
DarMM said:
a superposition of the total system is not in contradiction with definite outcomes for subsystems even in Copenhagen
Standard Copenhagen (Heisenberg, Bohr) always considers the state of a single quantum system only, never that of a system and a subsystem (except in the separable case before interaction), where this has a clear interpretation. See post #284.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #372
DarMM said:
the minimalist view, I've never been clear on what that really is.
There is no written account of it. The postulates of @vanhees71 in his various lecture notes (partly in German) are only an approximation to his actual (somewhat sloppy) views as revealed in discussions - he doesn't value the precision of mathematical physicists.

The book by Peres is perhaps the most consequent exposition of the minimalist view. But even he wavers when considering applications to large systems (p.424f):
Asher Peres said:
This would cause no conceptual difficulty with quantum theory if the Moon, the planets, the interstellar atoms, etc., had a well defined state ##\rho##. However, I have insisted throughout this book that ##\rho## is not a property of an individual system, but represents the procedure for preparing an ensemble of such systems. How shall we describe situations that have no preparer? [...] Thus, a macroscopic object effectively [...] mimics, with a good approximation, a statistical ensemble. [...] You must have noted the difference between the present pragmatic approach and the dogmas held in the early chapters of this book.
The mimicking is of course only FAPP (pragmatic), not in any logically convincing sense. But at least he acknowledges it while @vanhees71 insists on the absence of all problems in his version of the minimal interpretation.

The thermal interpretation has no such problems and still is minimalist in a similar (but content-wise diametrically opposed) way.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #373
A. Neumaier said:
You are missing the point mentioned in #373. It means that probability distributions strictly speaking predict nothing at all for any finite number of experiments.
I see, you would like to see the removal of epistemic quantities from physics since they strictly speaking don't predict anything.

It's an "extreme" (not meant pejoratively) view that I haven't seen before, so I didn't consider it.

A. Neumaier said:
Standard Copenhagen (Heisenberg, Bohr) always considers the state of a single quantum system only, never that of a system and a subsystem (except in the separable case before interaction), where this has a clear interpretation. See post #284.
I'm referring to a very nebulous "Copenhagen" since the phrase simply cannot refer to something specific and yet is a standard term for these views. Matt Leifer has a good summary of the kind of view I mean in his lecture notes here:
http://mattleifer.info/wordpress/wp-content/uploads/2018/05/Lecture26.pdfWhat he calls Copenhagenish.

I find it hard to know exactly what Old Copenhagen is sometimes as I find it very hard to understand the subtleties of what Heisenberg and Bohr's disagreements over the cut were about. Though I think I might get it, but there are still the points where they disagreed with Pauli etc.
 
  • #374
A. Neumaier said:
There is no written account of it. The postulates of @vanhees71 in his various lecture notes (partly in German) are only an approximation to his actual (somewhat sloppy) views as revealed in discussions. The book by Peres is perhaps the most consequent exposition of the minimalist view. But even he wavers when considering applications to large systems (p.424f):
I in fact just read Peres yesterday! I see he has statements like "There are no super-observers". Maybe @vanhees71 thinks the same.
 
  • #375
DarMM said:
I find it hard to know exactly what Old Copenhagen is sometimes as I find it very hard to understand the subtleties
The strength of Old Copenhagen is precisely their lack of precision about details that would be needed to get definite statements that can be refuted. This allowed (almost) everyone to accept it with small reservations only, which was enough for the first 40 years. Those who try to make it precise (all in their own way) only create problematic variants of it!
 
  • Like
Likes stevendaryl, julcab12 and Mentz114
  • #376
DarMM said:
you would like to see the removal of epistemic quantities from physics since they strictly speaking don't predict anything.
Not from physics; only from the foundations! If the foundations have no logical force then any argument built on them will have the same problem. I don't have reservations about introducing probability as an approximate concept as in tossing classical dice!
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #377
DarMM said:
I'm referring to a very nebulous "Copenhagen" since the phrase simply cannot refer to something specific and yet is a standard term for these views. Matt Leifer has a good summary of the kind of view I mean in his lecture notes here:
http://mattleifer.info/wordpress/wp-content/uploads/2018/05/Lecture26.pdfWhat he calls Copenhagenish.
Matt Leifer said:
  • Objective: There is an objective fact of the matter about what an observer observes.
  • Perspectival: What is true depends on where you are sitting.
I don't see how these are disjoint. Classical relativity is deemed objective although what is true depends on where the observer sits. Does he mean with perspectival ''What is true depends on a not further investigated state of mind of the observer?'' When he distinguishes ''facts of the matter'' (or ''objective facts'') and ''facts for you'', doesn't he turn subjective opinions into some sort of facts?

I doubt very much that this gives clearer notions than the original Copenhagen spirit.
 
  • #378
It's like Rovelli's relational interpretation. A system only has a property ##P## relative to me, i.e. all propeties of an object ##A## can have a separate value depending on the observer ##B##, so they'd be indexed as ##P_{A,B}## roughly. There's no "universal" value for a property. Schrodinger had similar thoughts if I remember correctly (though he wasn't committed to them).

In the Objective case he mentions this is not the case.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #379
DarMM said:
all properties of an object ##A## can have a separate value depending on the observer ##B##, so they'd be indexed as ##P_{A,B}## roughly. There's no "universal" value for a property.
But this is the same as with the length of an object ##A## in special relativity (or even Euclidean geometry at a distance). Every observer ##B## sees a different length and measures it objectively as this length. It is just a convention to define the ''true'' length as the eigenlength that would be measured in the rest frame located at the center of mass of ##A## to give the appearance of being non-relational.

Maybe one needs eigenproperties in the quantum domain?
 
  • #380
A. Neumaier said:
But this is the same as with the length of an object ##A## in special relativity (or even Euclidean geometry at a distance). Every observer ##B## sees a different length and measures it objectively as this length. It is just a convention to define the ''true'' length as the eigenlength that would be measured in the rest frame located at the center of mass of ##A## to give the appearance of being non-relational.

Maybe one needs eigenproperties in the quantum domain?
This would require a thread of its own, but the rough idea would be imagine if there were only the relative quantities. An analogy would be relativity with only frame dependent quantities, but no rules indicating they were the coordinate "reflections" of coordinate independent Tensors. Of course relativity is not like this.

Relativity would still ascribe an objective state to me that has different forms in different coordinates, but they are coordinate expressions of one thing. In the relational view a piece of matter genuinely has several different states, not different expressions of the same state, one for each other piece of matter.

QBism is perspectival in a different sense that would take us too far afield, but just to mention.
 
  • #381
DarMM said:
In the relational view a piece of matter genuinely has several different states
So each observer ##B## has for each bounded part ##A## of the universe (disjoint from ##B##?) a different ##\psi_{A,B}## and nothing at all defines how these are related?

No surprise that weird stuff comes out...
 
  • #382
It's not an interpretation I have much confidence in, in case that might affect my description.

More so it would be saying that there are ontic states ##\mathcal{O}_{AB}##, which aren't wavefunctions, but since each observer doesn't know what their state for ##A## is like until they look at it, they use ##\psi## to manage their expectations.

So imagine you and I are in a laboratory, you could have a particle with DarMM-spin ##\frac{1}{2}## and Neumaier-spin ##-\frac{1}{2}##. And these are separate properties. However we'd both use the same ##\psi## when we haven't observed it yet.

It would make for a strange world.
 
  • #383
DarMM said:
It's not an interpretation I have much confidence in, in case that might affect my description.

More so it would be saying that there are ontic states ##\mathcal{O}_{AB}##, which aren't wavefunctions, but since each observer doesn't know what their state for ##A## is like until they look at it, they use ##\psi## to manage their expectations.

So imagine you and I are in a laboratory, you could have a particle with DarMM-spin ##\frac{1}{2}## and Neumaier-spin ##-\frac{1}{2}##. And these are separate properties. However we'd both use the same ##\psi## when we haven't observed it yet.

It would make for a strange world.
It would also make QM very incomplete, as the universe now consists of objects, observers (a vaguely defined class of objects) and is described by QM states ##\psi## and, in addition, mostly unknown (unless watched) ontic states ##\mathcal{O}_{AB}##, with very little connection between these. Not a good start for doing physics...
 
  • #384
In it any object can be an observer. So there is Neumaier-spin, but also X-spin, where X can be a helium atom in the air or a photon.

So just remove the observers part and the rest of what you say is true, especially the enormous set of mostly unknown ontic states.
 
  • #385
DarMM said:
In it any object can be an observer. So there is Neumaier-spin, but also X-spin, where X can be a helium atom in the air or a photon.

So just remove the observers part and the rest of what you say is true, especially the enormous set of mostly unknown ontic states.
In particular, all ontic states ##\mathcal{O}_{AX}## would remain for ever unknowable and irrelevant, since a helium atom in the air or a photon cannot look at ##A##. Very heavy overparameterization, an ideal opportunity for applying Ockham's razor.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM

Similar threads

Replies
24
Views
4K
Replies
4
Views
877
Replies
42
Views
6K
Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
25
Views
3K
Replies
53
Views
6K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Back
Top