What Are the Empirical Challenges Facing Quantum Gravity Theories?

In summary, Rovelli points out three key pieces of observational evidence that should guide future research in quantum gravity. This includes abandoning Lorentz invariance violating theories, supergravity and string theory, and the anti-deSitter/conformal field theory relationship. Additionally, he suggests stopping work on models of dark matter that predict NFW particle distributions, as they have been repeatedly shown to be at odds with observational data. Rovelli argues that while these experimental data do not definitively rule out these theories, they should be taken into consideration and may decrease confidence in them. He also discusses the non-discovery of supersymmetry and the positive cosmological constant as further indications that certain theoretical approaches may need to be re-evaluated
  • #71
Nullstein said:
But there is no justification for enlarging the symmetry subgroup.
The general motivation they mention seems to be that the moduli space is too large, and unphysical. After all, what is the original justification for the continuous symmetry? This is why I asked "where the hilbert space is encoded" in the other post.

Fra said:
Separable Hilbert space in Loop Quantum Gravity
Winston Fairbairn, Carlo Rovelli, Oct 25, 2018

"However, the continuous moduli labeling these classes do not appear to affect the physics of the theory. We investigate the possibility that these moduli could be only the consequence of a poor choice in the fine-tuning of the mathematical setting. "
It seems well put to describe the continuum mathematics as a poor choice of fine tuning of the math.

If one add another constraint - that any observer for example have a finite perspective, or a finite information processing resources; set aside the details, this must necessarily make the set of possibilities smaller; as it must be encodable by the observer. I haven't seen a proper argumentation for this however in any of Rovellis papers before, but the general sense in what they say makes sense, and it's rather the original uncountable set of possible states that is what should be questioned.

But what seems be be going on to a certain extents in most approaches (not just LQG), is IMO starting with something that does not make sense (formal expressions which are pathological from the perspective of "inside agents"), then we are force to "make up" arguments to "tame it". Any arguments are likely flawed or ad hoc. The better way should IMO be to step back before we lost track of what we are doing and ended up with formal expressions that are extrapolated way outside their domain of corroboration. For example the whole continuum business, may well be an approximation of something more fundamental - rather than the other way around, which seems to be the more common attitude.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
Fra said:
The general motivation they mention seems to be that the moduli space is too large, and unphysical. After all, what is the original justification for the continuous symmetry? This is why I asked "where the hilbert space is encoded" in the other post.
What's unphysical is the singular structure of the theory. The non-separability of the Hilbert space is just a consequence of that. Usual QFTs with non-singular observables don't have this problem. The diffeomorphism symmetry is well motivated, because it's a consequence of classical GR. Any enlargement of this symmetry group is an ad-hoc assumption. If there wasn't the problem with the non-separable Hilbert space, nobody would bother to make it.
Fra said:
"However, the continuous moduli labeling these classes do not appear to affect the physics of the theory"
This claim is pretty unsubstantiated, given that not even a single physical observable (i.e. one that commutes with the constraints) is known in this version of LQG.
Fra said:
[...] it's rather the original uncountable set of possible states that is what should be questioned.
It is being questioned, but the solution is certainly not to just define the problem away. And if you check the literature, you will find that nobody in the LQG community actually uses the Hilbert space proposed in that paper in practice.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #73
Nullstein said:
... Can you give some references?
I think the talk gave some developments and references, including those external to the theory like the BMV tests
Witness gravity’s quantum side in the lab | Nature
Phys. Rev. Lett. 119, 240401 (2017) - Spin Entanglement Witness for Quantum Gravity (aps.org)
Also concerning testing, this is a paper concerning time
Frontiers | On the Possibility of Experimental Detection of the Discreteness of Time | Physics (frontiersin.org)
There may be allowances for incorporation of possible quantum or related aspects, but does the literature considered here include papers for instance like these
[2007.12635] Edge modes of gravity. Part III. Corner simplicity constraints (arxiv.org)
https://arxiv.org/abs/2104.12881 ?
 
  • #74
*now* said:
I think the talk gave some developments and references, including those external to the theory like the BMV tests
Witness gravity’s quantum side in the lab | Nature
Phys. Rev. Lett. 119, 240401 (2017) - Spin Entanglement Witness for Quantum Gravity (aps.org)
Also concerning testing, this is a paper concerning time
Frontiers | On the Possibility of Experimental Detection of the Discreteness of Time | Physics (frontiersin.org)
There may be allowances for incorporation of possible quantum or related aspects, but does the literature considered here include papers for instance like these
[2007.12635] Edge modes of gravity. Part III. Corner simplicity constraints (arxiv.org)
https://arxiv.org/abs/2104.12881 ?
In what sense do these articles provide any new insight into the separability of the LQG Hilbert space? The first three articles are concerned with experimental testing only. And the research by Freidel et al. on edge modes is an independent approach to developing a theory of quantum gravity and so far mostly classical analysis. Little is known yet about the potential quantum gravity theory that is supposed to arise from this. The fourth paper of the series, which is presumably supposed to be on Hilbert space aspects, has been announced, but not appeared yet, so even if you want to count this new approach towards the LQG family of theories, no conclusions about the separability of the Hilbert space can be drawn so far.
 
  • #75
Nullstein said:
allow geometry to be excited on neighborhoods
I find myself wondering what this dictum actually means. That the observables in question are associated with open sets? With submanifolds?
 
  • #76
mitchell porter said:
I find myself wondering what this dictum actually means. That the observables in question are associated with open sets? With submanifolds?
It means, as you have guessed, that the observables are associated (at least) with open sets. In QFT, operators can be smeared with test functions that are defined on extended, 4-dimensional regions and you can probe arbitrarily small regions with that. In loopy theories, operators are smeared along lower-dimensional objects such as edges or faces. These objects are nowhere dense subsets of spacetime, so no countable union of them can form an extended, 4-dimensional region. Since all states in the LQG Hilbert space can be obtained by repeatedly acting on the vacuum with these singularly smeared operators, no geometry can be excited on extended, 4-dimensional regions, because only countably many terms are allowed.
 
  • #77
Nullstein said:
What's unphysical is the singular structure of the theory.
Yes, this is unphysical, but why? I think it's not because physicists computations crash? I think the biggest problem with singularities, is that the are related to infinite information, in a sense that isn't easily renormalized.

But there are some infinites in other theories, that coincidentally are easily renormalized, but this coincidental success induces an unfortunatey illusion of that it makes universal sense. But the problem for me is the conceptual one with how a finite agent can _relate_ to arbitrary amount of information - in finite time even. So technically, even the curable infinites, are conceptually suspicious. This is why I see it as "unphysical", from the perspective of an observer/agent, which itself is made of matter.
Nullstein said:
The diffeomorphism symmetry is well motivated, because it's a consequence of classical GR. Any enlargement of this symmetry group is an ad-hoc assumption.
At least from my perspective, it is not trivial to heuristically carry over classical symmetries to an inferential framework where the standards are different(and better). This heuristic reasoning works sometimes, and sometimes not. In GR, I am not convinced that it's well motivated in the context of measurment theory with inside observers. That is "ad-hoc" to me.

/Fredrik
 
  • #78
Coming back to this, I have some questions.
Nullstein said:
That's the same model as the one given in Rovelli and Vidotto. It's formulated on a lattice and doesn't implement any spacetime symmetry at all. There is only the internal Lorentz symmetry at the vertices.

There is no way out. All Hilbert spaces in LQG/Spin Foam models fall under one of the following two cases:
  1. The Hilbert space contains uncountably many graphs and states on two different graphs are orthogonal. Then the Hilbert space is non-separable. Continuous symmetries may be implemented, but no nontrivial states can be invariant under a continuous group of symmetries.
  2. The Hilbert space is modeled on a lattice, then it may be separable, but no continuous group of spacetime symmetries can be implemented.
The problem is basically that in LQG/Spin Foams, geometry is excited only on lattice-like structures like foams or graphs, i.e. subsets of the manifold that are nowhere-dense. By the Baire category theorem, no neighborhood of any point can be the countable union of nowhere-dense sets. And since states can at most be defined on a countable set of graphs, most points of the neighborhood are not equipped with any kind of geometry and thus no neighborhood can be locally isometric to a region of Minkowski spacetime. In order to circumvent this simple result, there is no other option than to allow geometry to be excited on neighborhoods and no LQG-type model does that.
About 1. I assume you have something specific in mind, because it cannot be true in general without anything additional. For example take any group you like and let it act trivially, then all states are invariant. Do you have a group and and action in mind?

About 2. I don't understand this one. Why would be a spacetime group of symmetries be implemented? The graphs are not a lattice in a apriori space-time. Isn't the space-time and the symmetries supposed to emerge somehow?
 
  • #79
Fra said:
Yes, this is unphysical, but why? I think it's not because physicists computations crash? I think the biggest problem with singularities, is that the are related to infinite information, in a sense that isn't easily renormalized.
The use of the word "singular" here doesn't refer to something becoming infinite. It just means that the spacetime geometry is modeled on structures whose dimension is lower than the dimension of the spacetime manifold.
martinbn said:
About 1. I assume you have something specific in mind, because it cannot be true in general without anything additional. For example take any group you like and let it act trivially, then all states are invariant. Do you have a group and and action in mind?
Yes, of course I'm thinking of non-trivial group actions. But more specifically, the action of the diffeomorphism group in this formalism is given by ##(U_\phi\psi_\gamma)(\vec g) =\psi_{\phi(\gamma)}(\vec g)##, where ##\phi## is a diffeomorphism. And unless ##\phi=\mathrm{id}##, this action has the peculiar feature that ##U_\phi\psi_\gamma## is orthogonal to ##\psi_\gamma##.
martinbn said:
About 2. I don't understand this one. Why would be a spacetime group of symmetries be implemented? The graphs are not a lattice in a apriori space-time. Isn't the space-time and the symmetries supposed to emerge somehow?
A spacetime is a manifold equipped with a metric. The graphs are embedded into the spacetime manifold. The metric becomes a quantum field instead of a classical field. (LQG gives meaning only to coarse functions of the metric, smeared along lower dimensional submanifolds.) The points that don't lie on the graph are still there in the spacetime manifold and diffeomorphisms still act on the whole manifold. Such points just don't carry any geometry due to the peculiar nature of the theory. Now the hope is to construct states such that e.g. ##\left<\hat g_{\mu\nu}(x)\right>## (or at least the smeared versions of it) resembles classical solutions to the EFE with some quantum corrections. You can then ask for example if there are diffeomorphisms ##\phi## such that something like ##\left<(\phi^*\hat g)_{\mu\nu}(x)\right> = \left<\hat g_{\mu\nu}(x)\right>## holds. (It is not clear what properties really are desirable, but this is one reasonable thing one could ask for). Then you could call ##\phi## a quantum spacetime isometry.
 
Last edited:
  • #80
Nullstein said:
It just means that the spacetime geometry is modeled on structures whose dimension is lower than the dimension of the spacetime manifold.
Do you see this as a physical problem? How?

/Fredrik
 
  • #81
Fra said:
Do you see this as a physical problem? How?
I explained it in my earlier posts. It leads to difficulties with the existence of semiclassical states and the implementation of continuous symmetries.
 
  • #82
Nullstein said:
The graphs are embedded into the spacetime manifold. The metric becomes a quantum field instead of a classical field. (LQG gives meaning only to coarse functions of the metric, smeared along lower dimensional submanifolds.) The points that don't lie on the graph are still there in the spacetime manifold and diffeomorphisms still act on the whole manifold. Such points just don't carry any geometry due to the peculiar nature of the theory.
But I think the potential point is that this embedding, is not physically justified. It's an artifact of the mathematical formalism (that is well justified for OTHER domains).

This may be semantics, but I think this is not a physical problem, it's a problem of the choice of mathematics to describe the models, and it's an open question. Ie. there is not physical requirement, that we "must have" a continuum in the Planck domain. The embedding is a mathematical one, and problems with that, is not a physical problem.

/Fredrik
 
  • #83
Fra said:
But I think the potential point is that this embedding, is not physically justified. It's an artifact of the mathematical formalism (that is well justified for OTHER domains).

This may be semantics, but I think this is not a physical problem, it's a problem of the choice of mathematics to describe the models, and it's an open question. Ie. there is not physical requirement, that we "must have" a continuum in the Planck domain. The embedding is a mathematical one, and problems with that, is not a physical problem.
Sure, we don't know what the physics at the Planck scale is like and it may well be discontinuous. But Rovelli's point in the article in the OP is that we should abandon Lorentz-violating theories. Also the non-uniqueness of the discretization is a problem and may render the theory non-predictive if there isn't some kind of universality.
 
  • Like
Likes Fra
  • #84
It seems like one issue here, is whether you can get "Lorentz symmetry from superposition", to coin a phrase.

Consider a two-qubit superposition. The underlying observables are discrete, both in number and in spectrum, yet the space of quantum states is a continuum (a Riemann sphere) and possesses continuous symmetries, because superpositions have complex coefficients and complex numbers are a continuum.

Do any LQG theorists (or other quantum gravity theorists) explicitly say that they can obtain Lorentz or Poincare symmetry in an analogous way? Or perhaps as the n->infinity limit of something like that?

Penrose's spin networks are supposed to give you full rotational symmetry in such a limit, and I think one dream for twistor theory was that it would do the same for relativistic boosts too?
 
  • #85
mitchell porter said:
It seems like one issue here, is whether you can get "Lorentz symmetry from superposition", to coin a phrase.

Consider a two-qubit superposition. The underlying observables are discrete, both in number and in spectrum, yet the space of quantum states is a continuum (a Riemann sphere) and possesses continuous symmetries, because superpositions have complex coefficients and complex numbers are a continuum.

Do any LQG theorists (or other quantum gravity theorists) explicitly say that they can obtain Lorentz or Poincare symmetry in an analogous way? Or perhaps as the n->infinity limit of something like that?

Penrose's spin networks are supposed to give you full rotational symmetry in such a limit, and I think one dream for twistor theory was that it would do the same for relativistic boosts too?
Well, that's exactly what we have been discussion so far. The singlet state ##\frac{1}{\sqrt 2}\left(\left|\uparrow\downarrow\right>-\left|\downarrow\uparrow\right>\right)## is rotationally invariant, because you can expand the rotated state again in the up/down basis and it turns out to be the same. But in LQG, if you have a spin-network state ##\psi_\gamma## modeled on a graph ##\gamma## and you apply a diffeomorphism ##\phi## to it, then the transformed state ##\psi_{\phi(\gamma)}## is orthogonal to the initial state ##\psi_\gamma## (unless ##\phi=\mathrm{id}##) and hence has no chance to be equal to the initial state. Under no circumstances can two nonzero orthogonal vectors be equal. The next question is: Can a superposition of spin-network states, such as ##\sum_n c_n\psi_{\gamma_n}## be invariant? This can at most be true for a discrete group of transformations, because the sum can contain at most countably many terms and a continuous group will create new spin-network states that weren't present in the original sum and thus again be orthogonal.
 
  • #86
Nullstein said:
The graphs are embedded into the spacetime manifold. The metric becomes a quantum field instead of a classical field. (LQG gives meaning only to coarse functions of the metric, smeared along lower dimensional submanifolds.) The points that don't lie on the graph are still there in the spacetime manifold and diffeomorphisms still act on the whole manifold. Such points just don't carry any geometry due to the peculiar nature of the theory.
Why do you claim that the manifold "exists", and in what sense? That is not the way I usually hear people talking about LQG. They usually speak as if the amplitudes for the various graphs and their vertex/edge observables are the full content of the state; i.e. "all that is".

I also don't understand why we are discussing diffeomorphism invariance at all. I thought the graph observables were supposed to correspond to spacetime volumes as identified by measurable criteria, such as GPS readings. In that case, the diffeomorphism freedom (really just a redundancy, like all gauge freedom) has already been factored out.
 
  • #87
maline said:
Why do you claim that the manifold "exists", and in what sense?
Why do you claim the opposite? I claim it, because that's how it is and how it is written in the literature. Plenty of references have been given in this thread, not only by me but also by others. Spin networks / foams are embedded lower dimensional structures in the spacetime manifold. Quantum gravity is the theory of the quantized metric field ##g_{\mu\nu}(x)##, just like quantum electrodynamics is the theory of the quantized vector field ##A_\mu(x)## and so on. All these fields live on a manifold, quantization doesn't change that.
maline said:
I also don't understand why we are discussing diffeomorphism invariance at all. I thought the graph observables were supposed to correspond to spacetime volumes as identified by measurable criteria, such as GPS readings. In that case, the diffeomorphism freedom (really just a redundancy, like all gauge freedom) has already been factored out.
Diffeomorphism invariance is discussed in quantum gravity, just like gauge invariance is discussed in any other quantum gauge theory. By the way, no local observables exist in GR. All Dirac observables are necessarily non-local (see Torre, "Gravitational Observables and Local Symmetries"), so GPS readings can't constitute observables in QG. In fact, not a single Dirac observable is known so far, except in the very restricted setting of asymptotically flat spacetime.
 
  • #88
Nullstein said:
By the way, no local observables exist in GR. All Dirac observables are necessarily non-local (see Torre, "Gravitational Observables and Local Symmetries"), so GPS readings can't constitute observables in QG.
"Local observables" at some point in the manifold don't exist, precisely because you can do a diffeomorphism and move everything to somewhere else in the manifold. But the observable "curvature at the point identified by GPS readings (a,b,c,d)" is physically well defined. One could hope to have a theory where all of the quantum observables corresponded to invariants of this sort, and I was under the impression that LQG claims to do this. (After all, the whole idea of "loops" is based on the Wilson loop as an invariant operator in gauge theory...)
 
  • #89
maline said:
"Local observables" at some point in the manifold don't exist, precisely because you can do a diffeomorphism and move everything to somewhere else in the manifold. But the observable "curvature at the point identified by GPS readings (a,b,c,d)" is physically well defined.
No, that is not enough to define an observable in GR. Diffeomorphism invariance doesn't suffice. The observable also needs to commute with the Hamiltonian constraint.
maline said:
One could hope to have a theory where all of the quantum observables corresponded to invariants of this sort, and I was under the impression that LQG claims to do this. (After all, the whole idea of "loops" is based on the Wilson loop as an invariant operator in gauge theory...)
Wilson loops in LQG are only invariant under the additional internal symmetry group that arises when the theory is formulated in terms of vielbein fields instead of the metric. They are not invariant under the Bergmann-Komar group, i.e. they don't commute with the other constraints of the theory.
 
  • #90
Nullstein said:
Also the non-uniqueness of the discretization is a problem and may render the theory non-predictive if there isn't some kind of universality.
I agreee this is a key problem, but I find it conceptually a more tractable and rational quest than the similar uniqueness problem of ambigous ways to cure poorly defined formal expressions which are similarly unpredictive and conceptually lost.

/Fredrik
 
  • #91
Nullstein said:
Yes, of course I'm thinking of non-trivial group actions. But more specifically, the action of the diffeomorphism group in this formalism is given by ##(U_\phi\psi_\gamma)(\vec g) =\psi_{\phi(\gamma)}(\vec g)##, where ##\phi## is a diffeomorphism. And unless ##\phi=\mathrm{id}##, this action has the peculiar feature that ##U_\phi\psi_\gamma## is orthogonal to ##\psi_\gamma##.

A spacetime is a manifold equipped with a metric. The graphs are embedded into the spacetime manifold. The metric becomes a quantum field instead of a classical field. (LQG gives meaning only to coarse functions of the metric, smeared along lower dimensional submanifolds.) The points that don't lie on the graph are still there in the spacetime manifold and diffeomorphisms still act on the whole manifold. Such points just don't carry any geometry due to the peculiar nature of the theory. Now the hope is to construct states such that e.g. ##\left<\hat g_{\mu\nu}(x)\right>## (or at least the smeared versions of it) resembles classical solutions to the EFE with some quantum corrections. You can then ask for example if there are diffeomorphisms ##\phi## such that something like ##\left<(\phi^*\hat g)_{\mu\nu}(x)\right> = \left<\hat g_{\mu\nu}(x)\right>## holds. (It is not clear what properties really are desirable, but this is one reasonable thing one could ask for). Then you could call ##\phi## a quantum spacetime isometry.
I might be wrong, but this is not how I read Rovelli. For him the graphs are completely abstract combinatorial objects without an embedding in an apriori manifold. The space-time is a consequence. Even if you start with a manifold, representing space at a time or space-time, and consider graphs on them shouldn't you identify ones obtained after a diffeomorphisms? In other words for the state space the ##\gamma## and ##\phi(\gamma)## should be in the same equivalence class.
 
  • Like
Likes maline and weirdoguy
  • #92
martinbn said:
I might be wrong, but this is not how I read Rovelli. For him the graphs are completely abstract combinatorial objects without an embedding in an apriori manifold. The space-time is a consequence. Even if you start with a manifold, representing space at a time or space-time, and consider graphs on them shouldn't you identify ones obtained after a diffeomorphisms? In other words for the state space the ##\gamma## and ##\phi(\gamma)## should be in the same equivalence class.
No, there is definitely a manifold, upon which the theory is formulated. Of course, the diffeomorphism group is a gauge group, so it has to be modded out, but the equivalence classes depend on the background manifold. For example, in ##\mathbb R^4##, all circles are equivalent, while on a torus, two circles may not be transformed into one another by a diffeo. The equivalence classes depend on the manifold-dependend knot classes. And the fact that the geometry is singular survives the modding out of the diffeos as well. If one geometry is singular, then it remains singular after the application of a diffeo. It's perfectly valid to choose a representative of the equivalence class and demonstrate the singular nature of the state on this particular representative.
 
Last edited:
  • #93
Nullstein said:
No, there is definitely a manifold, upon which the theory is formulated.
Again, that is not how I read him. In the Zakopane lectures, he explicitly says that this is a purely combinatorial graph. Then there is a comment, where he says that there are constructions with graphs on manifolds and what he likes and what he doesn't about them.
Nullstein said:
Of course, the diffeomorphism group is a gauge group, so it has to be modded out, but the equivalence classes depend on the background manifold. For example, in ##\mathbb R^4##, all circles are equivalent, while on a torus, two circles may not be transformed into one another by a diffeo. The equivalence classes depend on the manifold-dependend knot classes. And the fact that the geometry is singular survives the modding out of the diffeos as well. If one geometry is singular, then it remains singular after the application of a diffeo. It's perfectly valid to choose a representative of the equivalence class and demonstrate the singular nature of the state on this particular representative.
Of course the equivalent classes depend on the manifold, the diff. group itself does. I am not sure I understand the relevance of the rest. If ##\gamma## is a graph, and ##\phi## a diffeomorphism, then ##\phi(\gamma)## is in the same class.
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #94
martinbn said:
Again, that is not how I read him. In the Zakopane lectures, he explicitly says that this is a purely combinatorial graph. Then there is a comment, where he says that there are constructions with graphs on manifolds and what he likes and what he doesn't about them.
The Zakopane lectures are a heavily abbreviated, pedagogical version of what's explained elaborately in a proper textbook like Thiemann or even his own books. You can read the full construction there, which starts from the classical manifold and performs a discretization of classical GR on embedded graphs. Then, after many pages of calculations, you can derive some of the results contained in the Zakopane lectures. The Zakopane summer school was a one week event directed at beginner students. The abstract says: "The theory is presented in self-contained form, without emphasis on its derivation from classical general relativity." Of course, a lecture for a summer school is heavily condensed and cannot contain all the details. Notice that he never explicitely defines the set ##\Gamma## of "combinatorial graphs" in these lecture notes. That's because a proper definition requires the manifold. The graphs are not really just combinatorical objects, that's just a good enough description for a one week introductory course. But if you don't believe me and don't want to look it up in a textbook either, then I'm afraid there's nothing I can do to convince you.
martinbn said:
Of course the equivalent classes depend on the manifold, the diff. group itself does. I am not sure I understand the relevance of the rest. If ##\gamma## is a graph, and ##\phi## a diffeomorphism, then ##\phi(\gamma)## is in the same class.
The relevance is to explain how the graphs in LQG are not just combinatorical objects, but equivalence classes of embedded graphs (two circles viewed as combinatorical objects are equivalent, but viewed as embedded graphs can be inequivalent). The metric isn't an observable in GR/QG, because it doesn't commute with the constraints. But (a smeared version of) it exists on the kinematical Hilbert space and you can use it to show that the states in LQG cannot locally look like Minkowski spacetime. You just pick a representative from the equivalence class, which is just one particular embedded graph with excitations on the edges, and calculate expectation values of geometric operators. This feature is preserved by diffeomorphisms, so it's really a property of the whole equivalence class.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #95
I will have to be satisfied by this and take your word for it, because I will not find the time to attempt to read the books.
 
  • #96
martinbn said:
I will have to be satisfied by this and take your word for it, because I will not find the time to attempt to read the books.
Well, you don't need to read a whole book, you can just skim to the page where the state space gets defined. This article is a preliminary version of Thiemanns full book and differs mostly in some introductory remarks and the appendix. You could just go to section I.2 and read a few pages.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen, Fra, maline and 2 others
  • #97
Maybe it has been said before, and maybe it's not even relevant in this topic. But somehow LQG reminds me a bit about how people tried to quantize Fermi's theory of weak interactions. The solution there wasn't changing the rules of quantizing, but adjusting the field theory by softening the amplitudes via the vector bosons. Somehow I feel LQG is analogous to attempts to quantize an incomplete field theory, i.e. GR.
 
  • Like
Likes physika, Demystifier and Fra
  • #98
haushofer said:
The solution there wasn't changing the rules of quantizing, but adjusting the field theory by softening the amplitudes via the vector bosons. Somehow I feel LQG is analogous to attempts to quantize an incomplete field theory, i.e. GR.
I share this view on LQG. When I started to look into Rovellis book years ago, I was lead to read up on his interpretation of QM (RQM), and there was IMO a weak spot. The big problem is that the nice relational standards, that Rovellis holds high, makes sense only at classical level. The way he conceptually connects it to QM essentially witout modicitation, seems unsatisfactory and somewhat conceptually inconsistent to me.

In Relativity, SR or GR. An observer is associated with a coordinate frame of reference (from which "observations" are made). In QM, the "observer" is the CONTEXT of the whole inference process.

In QFT whe almost get away with merging the external passive observer with unlimited information processing resources at infinity, and asymptotically flat spacetime. But this seems like a conincidental success that still is conceptually incomplete.

When entertaining the generalized observer equivalence in the quantum size, conceptual consistency suggets that considering ONLY the diffeomorphism constraint is missing out the observers internal complexity. This is an unsolved problem. ST does offer such internal complexity in the moduli spaces of the generalized background, but they are OTOH lost in it. It's for this reason I think that ant "extended diff" symmetry in itself is likely to be required in some way - because the moduli space of observers defined only by diff is bound to be larger than what is physically motivated, because the contraints of information processing is not accounted for.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes haushofer
  • #99
haushofer said:
Maybe it has been said before, and maybe it's not even relevant in this topic. But somehow LQG reminds me a bit about how people tried to quantize Fermi's theory of weak interactions. The solution there wasn't changing the rules of quantizing, but adjusting the field theory by softening the amplitudes via the vector bosons. Somehow I feel LQG is analogous to attempts to quantize an incomplete field theory, i.e. GR.
I don't even think there is anything wrong with quantizing GR. In fact, discretizing it on a lattice and then quantizing it with standard methods can't be completely off. Even if you may not obtain the theory of everything this way, it's a reasonable intermediate step. What's problematic, however, is the rather odd choice of canonical variables and the missing investigation of the continuum limit.
 
  • #100
Nullstein said:
I don't even think there is anything wrong with quantizing GR. In fact, discretizing it on a lattice and then quantizing it with standard methods can't be completely off. Even if you may not obtain the theory of everything this way, it's a reasonable intermediate step. What's problematic, however, is the rather odd choice of canonical variables and the missing investigation of the continuum limit.
An intermediate step, like quantizing Fermi's theory of the weak interactions :P

Can you e laborate on these canonical variables and what's odd about them?
 
  • Like
Likes physika
  • #101
haushofer said:
An intermediate step, like quantizing Fermi's theory of the weak interactions :P
It might as well become a success story, like quantizing classical electrodynamics. Nobody can tell at this point in time. At least, it's a reasonable approach, no less reasonable than quantizing classical electrodynamics. But it has to be done well. Sure it may fail, but it's worth a try.
haushofer said:
Can you e laborate on these canonical variables and what's odd about them?
They have no immediate physical meaning. What you do in LQG is to start from the vielbein formulation of GR, where the basic variables are the frame field and the spin connection. This is reasonable, one needs to do it anyway to allow for the inclusion of spinor fields. Then you make a 3+1 split, which is also reasonable if you want to obtain a Hamiltonian formulation. But then you go ahead and form new variables by adding the spin connection to the extrinsic curvature of the spatial slices. How is this a reasonable physical quantity? It's like adding apples and oranges and only accidentally works in 3 dimensions (because the adjoint representation of ##SO(3)## is equivalent to the defining representation). Morover, one introduces a new parameter (the Immirzi parameter), which classically cancels out, but remains important in the quantum theory. With these new variables, many equations simplify or become more elegant. The theory then looks like a Yang-Mills theory with additional constraints, but at the cost of having had to add apples to oranges in an early step of the calculation.
 
  • Like
Likes haushofer
  • #102
Nullstein said:
In what sense do these articles provide any new insight into the separability of the LQG Hilbert space? The first three articles are concerned with experimental testing only. And the research by Freidel et al. on edge modes is an independent approach to developing a theory of quantum gravity and so far mostly classical analysis. Little is known yet about the potential quantum gravity theory that is supposed to arise from this. The fourth paper of the series, which is presumably supposed to be on Hilbert space aspects, has been announced, but not appeared yet, so even if you want to count this new approach towards the LQG family of theories, no conclusions about the separability of the Hilbert space can be drawn so far.
Yes, I think I’ve previously linked e.g. a Lorentzian description in LQC somewhere in a thread here. There are varied alternatives and some crossovers and a description of Freidel’s recent work in a talk might interest Introduction to local holography - Laurent Freidel - Bing video . The tests linked for a start might add more weight towards distinguishing between differing descriptions, which might be related to papers such as this-Carlo Rovelli (Dated: February 8, 2018) [Written for the volume “Beyond Spacetime: The Philosophical Foundations of Quantum Gravity” edited by Baptiste Le Biha, Keizo Matsubara and Christian Wuthrich.]

Space and Time in Loop Quantum Gravity
Quantum gravity is expected to require modifications of the notions of space and time. I discuss and clarify how this happens in Loop Quantum Gravity.

https://arxiv.org/pdf/1802.02382.pdf
 
  • #103
haushofer said:
An intermediate step, like quantizing Fermi's theory of the weak interactions :P
mends and mends botches...
 
  • #104
*now* said:
Yes, I think I’ve previously linked e.g. a Lorentzian description in LQC somewhere in a thread here. There are varied alternatives and some crossovers and a description of Freidel’s recent work in a talk might interest Introduction to local holography - Laurent Freidel - Bing video . The tests linked for a start might add more weight towards distinguishing between differing descriptions, which might be related to papers such as this-Carlo Rovelli (Dated: February 8, 2018) [Written for the volume “Beyond Spacetime: The Philosophical Foundations of Quantum Gravity” edited by Baptiste Le Biha, Keizo Matsubara and Christian Wuthrich.]

Space and Time in Loop Quantum Gravity
Quantum gravity is expected to require modifications of the notions of space and time. I discuss and clarify how this happens in Loop Quantum Gravity.

https://arxiv.org/pdf/1802.02382.pdf
I think I've lost track of what we're talking about here. Are we still discussing Lorentz invariance? Then I don't see how these references support your point.
 
  • #105
I’d been thinking of issues generally that along with possible narrowing of alternatives discussed in the OP source there is breadth of other possible directions and emphases towards open questions, and those raised may be examples of, but replying has been problematic and on second thoughts I think that absent citing the author’s express words attempting to speak of the author’s possible opinions or intuitions or variations seems very problematic.
 

Similar threads

Replies
13
Views
3K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
15
Views
3K
Replies
2
Views
909
Replies
6
Views
697
Replies
5
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
8
Views
2K
Back
Top