What Do Newton's Laws Say When Carefully Analysed

In summary: N2 and N3.Is that really the historical context? Do you have any sources discussing that? I'm seeing a lot discussing the need for an explicit refution of Aristotelian physics, but then only... considering the matter closed, and moving on to N2 and N3.In summary, the conversation discusses the issue of Newton's Laws and their significance in understanding nature. While the first law is often considered a definition, it has been experimentally tested and forms the basis of Einstein's first postulate of relativity. The third law, while important, is not equivalent to conservation of momentum. Additionally, there is a suggestion to view force as a prescription for analyzing mechanical problems rather than a
  • #106
vanhees71 said:
Newton III says nothing about the range of interactions.

That's not the point. The range of interactions doesn't matter if forces would need no interactions at all. How do you exclude that without Newton III?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #107
That was clear. #103. In fact I rather enjoyed that math.

It reinforces what @vanhees71 said about Newton's assumption re Euclidean background space-time.

It also clarifies what bothers me... in what space-time does this co-variant derivative exists? It feels like an "arbiter of all Newtonian dilemmas" but I don't get what gives it reference, how does it avoid being accused of being a "preferred frame" or in some sense occupying one, like some background geometry?

Unless the idea of the third law is to say that the covariant derivative is a benign and strictly helpful artifice because it always treats any two frames it connects as equals (forces are always equal and opposite). IOW, it's reference is only physically defined via interactions - for which no frame is considered preferred?
 
  • #108
vis_insita said:
The formulation of both Laws is completely covariant. Since they are indepenent of frames of reference, they are not restricted to inertial frames. In particular, this means that the vector field FF\boldsymbol{F} only describes interactions. You may not add any “fictitious forces” on a whim. Fictitious forces only ever enter the picture when expressing the equation of motion with respect to a reference frame which is non-inertial in the above defined sense.

I guess that's kind of what @vis_insita said?
 
  • #109
Thank you, @Dale, for the friendly welcome.

A reference I intended, but forgot, to include in my first post is Misner, Thorne, Wheeler, Gravitation, which contains a chapter dedicated to the covariant formulation of Newtonian Gravity. This approach goes back to Cartan and is also known as Newton-Cartan-Theory. I am only aware of one other book that also discusses it, but it is in German: Dirschmid, "Tensoren und Felder".

To be honest, I haven't really thought about how the Third Law fits in, since it always appeared somewhat unimportant to me. It may be true or false without affecting much of the rest of the theory as far as I can tell. Because the formulation of the first two laws I have given is completely local, I don't expect that the Third Law can be included in a natural way, since it appears inherently nonlocal to me. (But I am attempting one formulation below.) Still I believe that even in this local formulation the theory is general enough to incorporate all cases of physical interest. As long as the influence of the other particle can be described by a field equation, that has to be solved simultaneously with the equations of motion of the particles I don't see a fundamental problem.

Consider gravity which is a paradigmatic two-body-force obeying the Third Law. Yet, in Newton-Cartan-Theory there is a field equation (very similar to the Einstein equation)

$$(\text{Ricci-Curvature}) = (\text{mass density})\mathrm{d}t\otimes\mathrm{d}t,$$

wich makes the equation of motion of every particle completely local. Of course the fields thus defined will in general not be independent degrees of freedom, since the field equations will not contain time derivatives in the characteristic ways, as is necessary in Relativity. But this doen't invalidate their appearance in Newtonian Mechanics. Also, I think in view of the equivalence principle, gravity is more naturally included among the inertial forces, since it shows up only implicitely in ##\nabla##, not in the force law ##\boldsymbol{F}##. So here the Third Law used as a criterion for the distinction between real force and fictitious force is somewhat in the way of a covaraint formulation of the equivalence principle.

Now, if one wanted to include non-local interactions, I think one must rephrase the 2nd law. The n-particle force ##F_i## on particle i is not a vector field on space time anymore, but a more complicated object that assigns a vector field to each absolute time t and n-1 events happening at that time. So for every events ##x_1, x_2, ...,## with ##t(x_1)=...=t(x_{n-1})## (all happening at the same absolute time) there is a vector field: ##x \mapsto \boldsymbol{F}_i(x, x_1, ...)## which is tangent to x and spatial. But, since I just made all that up, I'm not sure if it makes sense.

In any case, I believe the Third Law must be regarded as a condition on two body forces which reads "action equals reaction at each point in absolute time". This can be formulated on Newtonian space time as

$$\boldsymbol{F}_1(x(t), y(t)) = -\boldsymbol{F}_2(y(t), x(t))$$

where ##x## and ##y## are the world lines of both particles. This condition makes sense since all vectors are taken at the same absolute time and are thus contained in the same absolute Euclidean space.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #110
Jimster41 said:
It also clarifies what bothers me... in what space-time does this co-variant derivative exists? It feels like an "arbiter of all Newtonian dilemmas" but I don't get what gives it reference, how does it avoid being accused of being a "preferred frame" or in some sense occupying one, like some background geometry?

A covariant derivative does not define a preferred frame.

The principle of relativity is very elegantly incorporated in the structure of space time. Note that the usual approach to Newtonian Mechanics gives space time a structure ##\mathbb{R}\times\mathbb{E}^3##. This somewhat contradicts the principle of relativity since it allows to define absoluet rest as "staying at the same point in absolute space ##\mathbb{E}^3## for all times."

In the covariant formulation one potulates a more general structure: Spacetime is a 4-dimensional manifold ##\mathbb{N}^4##, say, on which a scalar field ##t: \mathbb{N}^4 \rightarrow \mathbb{R}## is definied, which assigns each event the absolute time at which it happens. (Of course there are some requirement on ##t##, like ##\mathrm{d}t\neq 0## without which the following wouldn't make much sense.) Now you define absolute space at time ##\tau## as the set of events ##x##, that satisfy ##t(x)=\tau##. The crucial thing is that each time t has its own absolute space. It makes no sense to talk about two events at different times happening in the same place. Thus, you cannot define absolute rest here. The covariant derivative doesn't change anything about that fact. You can easily verify this by showing that for each inertial frame with origin ##O(t)## there is a different one, whose origin ##O'(t)## has a nonvanishing constant relative velocity to the first one, i.e.

$$\nabla_{e_0}(O'(t) -O(t)) \neq 0.$$

I think there is an interesting pattern to recognize here

1) The elementary formulations of Newtonian Mechanics involve a global split of space and time. This makes the Principle of Relativity a pure accident of the dynamics, which only shows up as a symmetry of the force laws that is in no way reflected in the fundamental structure of space time. To remedy this you have to unify space and time, even in Newtonian Mechanics.

2) The elementary formulations of Newtonian mechanics treat gravity as a normal interaction force. This makes the Principle of Equivalence a pure accident of the equality of "inertial" and "gravitational" mass. To adequately represent that principle in the Laws of Motion as well as in the spacetime structure you have to make spacetime curved, even in Newtonian Mechanics.
 
  • Like
  • Informative
Likes weirdoguy, Jimster41 and Dale
  • #111
vis_insita said:
By the way it is natural to include Newtonian Gravity as curvature of space time, by stating the equivalence principle in the form "inertial motion = free fall". Then the Second Law formally holds as stated above. Only ##\boldsymbol{F}## is also free of gravitational forces, which are instead included in ##\nabla## and are in this sense more on par with inertial forces. Also all "inertial frames" become "local inertial frames".

This is important, and shows a great difference between your presentation and the usual Newton's laws that we have been discussing. While the overall physics is the same, the definition of force is not the same in both formalisms.
 
  • #112
atyy said:
This is important, and shows a great difference between your presentation and the usual Newton's laws that we have been discussing. While the overall physics is the same, the definition of force is not the same in both formalisms.

Since I am not using the Third Law anywhere I believe the definition of force is a little more general. But I think this is only a minor difference, not a great one. The point was more that even absent the Thrid Law there is no conceptual problem in formulating the other two laws of motion, or in treating inertial forces, or in defining inertial frames. The Third Law doesn't seem necessary for that.

The treatment of the Equivalence Principle, however, is independent of the treatment of all non-gravitational forces. It is possible to incorporate gravity as spacetime curvature in a covariant formulation, as well as in a non-covariant one. But it is not necessary in either. You can also postulate the existence of a field ##\Phi## on spacetime, which satisfies ##\Delta\Phi = \rho## on each slice of constant absolute time, and couples to the particles via

$$m\nabla_{u}u = -m\nabla\Phi + \boldsymbol{F}.$$

But the gravitational force ##-m\nabla\Phi## is a little elusive and cannot be unambiguously (i.e. observer-independently) assigned to a particular event without further assumptions. Since ##\partial_i \Phi## can always be absorbed in the redefinition

##\tilde{\Gamma}^i_{00} = \Gamma^i_{00} + \partial_i\Phi,##

mechanics provides no basis to distinguish a locally vanishing gravitational field observed by a non-inertial observer with linear acceleration ##b^i = \Gamma^i_{00}## from a non-vanishing field of strength ##\Gamma^i_{00} = \partial_i\Phi## observerd by an inertial oberver.

This is a real physically important difference to other forces and can justifiably influence the way we see and define forces.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #113
vis_insita said:
Since I am not using the Third Law anywhere I believe the definition of force is a little more general. But I think this is only a minor difference, not a great one. The point was more that even absent the Thrid Law there is no conceptual problem in formulating the other two laws of motion, or in treating inertial forces, or in defining inertial frames. The Third Law doesn't seem necessary for that.

The treatment of the Equivalence Principle, however, is independent of the treatment of all non-gravitational forces. It is possible to incorporate gravity as spacetime curvature in a covariant formulation, as well as in a non-covariant one. But it is not necessary in either. You can also postulate the existence of a field ##\Phi## on spacetime, which satisfies ##\Delta\Phi = \rho## on each slice of constant absolute time, and couples to the particles via

$$m\nabla_{u}u = -m\nabla\Phi + \boldsymbol{F}.$$

But the gravitational force ##-m\nabla\Phi## is a little elusive and cannot be unambiguously (i.e. observer-independently) assigned to a particular event without further assumptions. Since ##\partial_i \Phi## can always be absorbed in the redefinition

##\tilde{\Gamma}^i_{00} = \Gamma^i_{00} + \partial_i\Phi,##

mechanics provides no basis to distinguish a locally vanishing gravitational field observed by a non-inertial observer with linear acceleration ##b^i = \Gamma^i_{00}## from a non-vanishing field of strength ##\Gamma^i_{00} = \partial_i\Phi## observerd by an inertial oberver.

This is a real physically important difference to other forces and can justifiably influence the way we see and define forces.

Would it be correct to think that what you have added beyond the traditional Newton's first and second, is that you have specified their transformation properties in arbitrary coordinates?
 
  • #114
DrStupid said:
That's not the point. The range of interactions doesn't matter if forces would need no interactions at all. How do you exclude that without Newton III?
Now I'm completely lost. If the forces are not interactions, Newton III doesn't make any sense.

It's of course clear that a physical theory is not simply a system of axioms as in mathematics but you have to operationally define it. Again, I can only repeat the logic of Newton's arguments:

Newton I: Assumes the existence of an absolute time and space, where the law of inertia holds, i.e., bodies which are not "influenced" by other bodies (and for Newton there's nothing else than material bodies of course, because fields haven't been discovered yet) move in rectilinear uniform motion in such an "inertial frame".

Newton II: Forces acting on a body change the state of motion within an inertial frame, being proportional to the acceleration of a body. The proportionality constant is a measure for the inertia of the body and also a meausure for "amount of substance".

Newton III: Forces act pair-wise and if ##\vec{F}_{12}## is the force on body 1 through interaction with body 2, the force on body 2 through interaction with body 1 is ##\vec{F}_{21}=-\vec{F}_{12}##.

As we know today, that's not even complete since also within Newtonian physics there are generic ##N##-body forces with ##N>2## (e.g., the nucleon-nucleon interaction in relativistic models).

It's anyway a very complicated issue, and from a modern point of view it's simpler to just state the space-time model and analyze its symmetries, but that we've also discussed already above.
 
  • #115
atyy said:
Would it be correct to think that what you have added beyond the traditional Newton's first and second, is that you have specified their transformation properties in arbitrary coordinates?

I would say that the transformation properties to arbitrary coordinates are made especially transparent in this approach. But really the only thing that is added beyond traditional approaches is, I think, clarity. It is perfectly valid to base Newtonian Mechanics on the notion of inertial frames and derive everything, including the form of the equations of motion, in non-inertial frames or arbitrary coordinate systems from that.

But personally I always found that a little confusing. And I encountered many statements that I suspect are the result of similar confusions. Some such statements are plainly false, e.g. the very common claim that Newton's axioms are only valid in inertial frames. Against such claims a generally covariant formulation of those axioms should provide a decisive argument.

One of the subtleties that can in the traditional approach become the more confusing the more you think about it, is the derivation of inertial forces. It usually involves a discussion of the time-dependence of basis vectors which goes like this:

In an inertial frame S we have
$$\frac{d v}{d t} = \dot{v}^i e_i \qquad (1).$$
But in a non-inertial frame S' the basis vectors move, so we have to take that into account too. Thus
$$\frac{d v}{d t} = \dot{v}^ie'_i + v^i\dot{e}'_i.$$
But what justifies the asymmetry? The basis vectors of S' clearly appear to move if viewed from S. But so do the basis vectors of S appear to move when viewed from S'. I once had a discussion where I pointed out that condition (1) is precisely one of the characteristics of an inertial frame. My opponent replied that this cannot be true, since from the point of view of an observer at rest in a rotating frame, the basis vectors don't move. So for that observer the same condition holds. I said that the time derivative of a vector is again a vector, which is a geometric object. So it either is or isn't zero. But, in any case, that statement is independent of any reference frames. I believe he remained unconvinced, but I wonder how he would derive inertial forces.

I think the cause for this confusion is that an important part of mathematical structure, namely the covariant derivative, is completely absent from the discussion. It is never really made clear what the inertial motion of particles has to do with time derivatives of basis vectors. The covariant approach makes that perfectly clear: ##\nabla## defines straightness, i.e. inertial motion, as well as vector derivatives.
 
Last edited:
  • #116
vis_insita said:
I would say that the transformation properties to arbitrary coordinates are made especially transparent in this approach. But really the only thing that is added beyond traditional approaches is, I think, clarity. It is perfectly valid to base Newtonian Mechanics on the notion of inertial frames and derive everything, including the form of the equations of motion, in non-inertial frames or arbitrary coordinate systems from that.

In practice the covariant first law is still useless if there are no non-interacting particles, so that seems the same as the elementary version.

The covariant second law is still a force definition, as in the elementary version, since it is empty unless F is specified.

The covariant second law seems able to distinguish non-inertial forces from real forces, but similarly to the elementary version, you add something. In the elementary version, one of the things one can add is Newton's 3rd law, but that doesn't have to be the extra ingredient, it can also be the transformation properties of the forces.

However, in the elementary version, adding transformation properties does not distinguish between an accelerated frame and a uniform gravitational field. Thus an accelerated frame can cancel a uniform gravitational field not only locally, but over a large region of space and time. Does the covariant version have any advantage in distinguishing an accelerated frame from a uniform gravitational field?
 
  • #117
atyy said:
In practice the covariant first law is still useless if there are no non-interacting particles, so that seems the same as the elementary version.

The covariant second law is still a force definition, as in the elementary version, since it is empty unless F is specified.

It is true that both the covariant and the non-covariant version have the same content. This is so by intention. But we have to be clear about what that content is.

The First Law both defines what "straight uniform motion" means, and states a physical condition under which it occurs. The latter condition would also follow from the Second Law. But the definition of "straight uniform motion" is not useless in the sense that it could be discarded without substitution. From a theoretical point of view I think it is most important.

Also it seems to me that traditional expositions are usually not very consistent in applying that definition even if they carefully formulate it. E.g. a non-covariant formulation that would be (absent gravitation) equivalent to the one I have given is

1st Law: "There exists a frame of reference in which all straight uniform trajectories have the form
$$\left(\frac{\mathrm{d}^2 x^i}{\mathrm{d} t^2}\right)\boldsymbol{e}_i = 0. \qquad (1)$$
Isolated, non-interacting particles follow those straight uniform trajectories."


Now, changing to an arbitrary reference frame will in general violate condition (1) in a well-defined way, but it will not change anything about the straightness or the uniformity of the motion, because both properties have absolute, frame-independent meaning within the theory. One cannot neglect defining them in a frame-independent way without confusing everything. Yet, some authors seem to say that condition (1) defines straightness in any frame which absolutely makes no sense. Thus inertial forces are introduced to "explain" the departure from straight uniform motion in light of the Second Law, which is completely backwards. Inertial forces occur even if the motion is straight and uniform merely as a consequence of chosing a non-inertial reference frame.

The covariant second law seems able to distinguish non-inertial forces from real forces, but similarly to the elementary version, you add something. In the elementary version, one of the things one can add is Newton's 3rd law, but that doesn't have to be the extra ingredient, it can also be the transformation properties of the forces.

I think here you are saying that inertial forces arise as a consequence of the transformation properties of forces. They do not; at least not in the way they are usually introduced in textbooks. They arise because the time derivative that defines acceleration is caluclated in a time-dependent basis. Thus, the only transformation property involved is that of the time derivative
$$\left(\frac{\mathrm{d}}{\mathrm{d}t}\right)_{S}[\cdot] = \left(\frac{\mathrm{d}}{\mathrm{d}t}\right)_{S'}[\cdot] + \boldsymbol{\omega}\times[\cdot]$$
which is of fundamental importance to the theory and is, as the covariant formulation makes clear, nothing but a special case of the usual "transformation law" of an affine connection.

(Maybe this equation is that something you say must be "added" to make a clear distinction between real and fictitious forces. I think I would agree with that.)

However, in the elementary version, adding transformation properties does not distinguish between an accelerated frame and a uniform gravitational field. Thus an accelerated frame can cancel a uniform gravitational field not only locally, but over a large region of space and time. Does the covariant version have any advantage in distinguishing an accelerated frame from a uniform gravitational field?

Why would that be an advantage? I think it is precisely the content of the Equivalence Principle that you cannot distinguish both situations. In the Newton-Cartan-Theory both the uniform acceleration and the "local gravitational field" originate from
$$\nabla_{\boldsymbol{e}_0}\boldsymbol{e}_0 = \Gamma^i_{00}\boldsymbol{e}_i$$
As in General Relativity that term can always be made to vanish at the origin, by changing to a local inertial frame. If there is only a uniform "gravitational force" (which really isn't a gravitational force at all) it vanishes everywhere and the local inertial frame is a global one.
 
  • Informative
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and Dale
  • #118
vis_insita said:
There exists a frame of reference in which all straight uniform trajectories
Would it be better to just say “geodesic” here?
 
  • #119
Dale said:
Would it be better to just say “geodesic” here?

In my opinion this is exactly the meaning that should be attributed to "straight uniform motion" also in Newtonian Mechanics, yes.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and Dale
  • #120
vanhees71 said:
If the forces are not interactions, Newton III doesn't make any sense.

I'm not sure what you mean. Newton III defines forces to be interactive. Thus, I would reather say that non-interactive forces make no sense (due to Newton III).

vanhees71 said:
Again, I can only repeat the logic of Newton's arguments:

As we can't ask Newton anymore, nobody knows for certain what the logic of his arguments really is. You just repeat your opinion about them. Here is my opinion, based on the original wordings1,2:

Newton’s laws of motion are about forces. That’s why it makes sense to start with Newton’s definition of force:

"Def. IV: Vis impressa est actio in corpus exercita, ad mutandum ejus sta-tum vel quiescendi vel movendi uniformiter in directum."
(An impressed force is an action exerted upon a body, in order to change its state, either of rest, or of moving uniformly forward in a right line.)

With this definition we have a general impression what forces are (something that changes the state of motion of bodies) and what they not are (something that preserves the state of motion [e.g. in contrast to the Aristotelian concept of force]). But it is not ready to use. There are some questions open:

1. The definition of force says that it is an action that changes the state of motion of a body, but are there other reasons for a body to change its motion, in particular, can it spontaneously change its motion without an action exerted upon it? That is answered by

"Lex I: Corpus omne perseverare in statu suo quiescendi vel movendi uniformiter in directum, nisi quatenus a viribus impressis cogitur statum illum mutare."
(Law I. Every body perseveres in its state of rest, or of uniform motion in a right line, unless it is compelled to change that state by forces impressed thereon.)

That means that forces are the only reason for a change of the state motion.
Now we know that every force changes the state of motion of a body (according to Def. IV) and every change of motion is caused by a force (according to Law I). Or

##F = 0 \Leftrightarrow a = 0##

which is logical equivalent to

##F \ne 0 \Leftrightarrow a \ne 0##

2. Now we have a full qualitative relation between forces and changes in the state of motion but what how to quantify it? That is answered by

"Lex II: Mutationem motus proportionalem esse vi motrici impressae, & fieri secundum lineam rectam qua vis illa imprimitur."
(Law II: The alteration of motion is ever proportional to the motive force impressed; and is made in the direction of the right line in which that force is impressed.)

In modern notation and with a unified system of units this means

##F = \dot p##

3. Together with the definition of momentum (Def. II) we now have a full qualitative and quantitative relation between forces and changes in the state of motion. But where do forces come from? That is answered by

"Lex III: Actioni contrariam semper & aequalem esse reactionem: sive corporum duorum actiones in se mutuo semper esse aequales & in partes contrarias dirigi."
(Law III: To every action there is always opposed an equal reaction: or the mutual actions of two bodies upon each other are always equal, and directed to contrary parts.)

That implies (but is not limited to)

##action \Rightarrow reaction##

which is logical equivalent to

##\neg reaction \Rightarrow \neg action##

Forces are limited to interactions. Without interaction there is no force.

Law III says furthermore that the interactions need to be symmetrical. For two bodies A and B the force ##F_{AB}## exerted by A upon B and the counter-force ##F_{BA}## exerted from B upon A must comply with

##F_{AB} = - F_{BA}##

That also implies that the interactions are binary only. For more than two bodies the additivity of forces (resulting from the additivity of momentum and also described in Corollary I) would for infinite different linear combinations. Newton III tells us that the combination of symmetric pairs of forces shall be used only.

That’s what Newton’s laws of motion say to my understanding.

What has that to do with inertial frames? The laws of motion (with the wording above) are not valid in all frames of reference. In #85 I demonstrated how rotating frames violate them. They can either comply with Law I and II or with Law III but not with all of them at once. Frames of references that comply with all laws of motion are called inertial. Of course there are other possibilities to define inertial frames, but that’s how it works with the laws of motion as given above.

If and how the laws of motion define inertial frames strongly depends on the exact wordings. There are a lot of different versions out there, resulting in different conclusions. In #34 I already mentioned a version that has been introduces by Newton himself. By deleting the first part of Newton III ("To every action there is always opposed an equal reaction") he allowed fictitious forces and therefore extended the laws of motion to non-inertial frames. There are a lot of cases where something like this is very useful. But with this modification the laws of motion alone do not define inertial frames anymore.

That’s why it is very important to clarify what we actually mean with “Newton’s laws of motion”. I refer to the original or equivalent wordings. If you refer to another version that please post the wording.1Latin original: http://cudl.lib.cam.ac.uk/view/PR-ADV-B-00039-00001/1
2 Eglish translation: https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/The_Mathematical_Principles_of_Natural_Philosophy_(1846)
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #121
Of course, you can describe everything in any frame you like, but to establish the laws you need "absolute time" and "absolute space", i.e., (the equivalence class of) inertial frames. There's no problem with accelerated reference frames though, and the laws can be formulated covariantly, introducing covariant time derivatives acting on the components of vectors (and general tensors) wrt. any basis. There's also no problem to introduce genereric 3- and N-body forces/interactions in addition to pair interactions.
 
  • #122
vis_insita said:
(Maybe this equation is that something you say must be "added" to make a clear distinction between real and fictitious forces. I think I would agree with that.)

Yes, that is what I am saying. To distinguish between real and inertial forces, one could add N3, but one could also do as you did and add the transformation criteria.

vis_insita said:
Why would that be an advantage? I think it is precisely the content of the Equivalence Principle that you cannot distinguish both situations. In the Newton-Cartan-Theory both the uniform acceleration and the "local gravitational field" originate from
$$\nabla_{\boldsymbol{e}_0}\boldsymbol{e}_0 = \Gamma^i_{00}\boldsymbol{e}_i$$
As in General Relativity that term can always be made to vanish at the origin, by changing to a local inertial frame. If there is only a uniform "gravitational force" (which really isn't a gravitational force at all) it vanishes everywhere and the local inertial frame is a global one.

Yes, if the gravitational field is truly uniform over all space, then one cannot distinguish it from an accelerated frame. However, suppose we have an infinite plane mass that produces a uniform gravitational field over the half space. N3 can distinguish between a real uniform gravitational field and an accelerated frame, since N3 would predict that the real gravitational field is produced by matter.
 
  • #123
atyy said:
Newton's 3rd law helps because inertial forces are not part of action-reaction pairs.
If the noninertial frame of reference is bounded to a body that is aceelereating with constant acceleration and is not spinning in inertial frame of reference,
then Newton 3. law would still be valid in it.

If you have no information (for examle force as function of coordinates and speeds) about (noninertial) force, then Newton 3. law is same as conservation of momentum.
 
  • #125
olgerm said:
If the noninertial frame of reference is bounded to a body that is aceelereating with constant acceleration and is not spinning in inertial frame of reference, then Newton 3. law would still be valid in it.

That only works as long as the reason for the acceleration of the body remains unknown. It is no surprise that such a lack of information may lead to wrong conclusions.

olgerm said:
If you have no information (for examle force as function of coordinates and speeds) about (noninertial) force, then Newton 3. law is same as conservation of momentum.

Newton 3 implies conservation of momentum but it is not the same.
 
  • #126
DrStupid said:
That only works as long as the reason for the acceleration of the body remains unknown.
Lets say than that the it not bounded to a body, but is just accelerating like it were bounded to a body that was constantly accelerating in inertial frame of reference. aka a frame of reference with homogeneous and constant inertial force.
 
  • #127
olgerm said:
Lets say than that the it not bounded to a body, but is just accelerating like it were bounded to a body that was constantly accelerating in inertial frame of reference. aka a frame of reference with homogeneous and constant inertial force.

Momentum is not conserved in such a frame of reference. That violates Newton III.
 
  • Like
Likes olgerm
  • #128
DrStupid said:
Momentum is not conserved in such a frame of reference. That violates Newton III.
You are right. But how would you define inertial frame of reference WITH Newton's 3. law?
 
  • #129
DrStupid said:
What has that to do with inertial frames? The laws of motion (with the wording above) are not valid in all frames of reference. In #85 I demonstrated how rotating frames violate them. They can either comply with Law I and II or with Law III but not with all of them at once.

From post #85:

DrStupid said:
Newton I: As the particle remains ar rest, there is no force acting on it.
Newton II: As the acceleration is zero, the force acting on the particle is ##F = m \cdot a = 0##

Now I switch to another frame of reference that is rotating around the origin with the angular velocity ##\omega##. In this frame the particle is moving on circular paths around the rotational axis. That means according to

Newton I: As the particle doesn't remain at rest or uniform translation, there is a force acting on it.
Newton II: As the acceleration is ##- \omega ^2 \cdot r##, the force acting on the particle is ##F = m \cdot a = - m \cdot \omega ^2 \cdot r##

But there is a catch. I think nothing in your (or Newton's) formulation of the axioms implies that switching to a rotating frame changes the particle's acceleration to ##-\omega^2 r##. You probably think that you are just using standard definitions here, but you are not. It is your definition of "acceleration" that only applies to inertial frames, not any of Newton's axioms.

I suppose we agree that acceleration is just the time derivative of velocity, both of which are represented as vectors. The velocity can be calculated as time derivative of position, which may also be represented as vector relative to the common origin. Now we just have to carefully apply those definitions: Since both the inertial frame S, ##\boldsymbol{e}_i##, and the rotating frame S', ##\boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i## always share the same origin, the position vector ##\boldsymbol{r}## at every instant of time is given by (left hand side is always S, right hand side is S' in the following)
$$ r^i\boldsymbol{e}_i = \boldsymbol{r} = \tilde r^i\boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i.$$
Its time derivative gives the velocity
$$\dot{r}^i \boldsymbol{e}_i = \boldsymbol{v} = \dot{\tilde r}^i\boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i + \boldsymbol{\omega}\times\boldsymbol{r}$$
You assumed ##\dot{r}^i \equiv 0##, so ##\boldsymbol{v}=0##.

Note that the velocity w.r.t both systems is just ##\boldsymbol{v}=0##. It is not given by ##\dot{\tilde r}^i\boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i## in the rotating system, because that vector simply isn't equal to the time derivative
$$\boldsymbol{v} = \frac{\mathrm{d}\boldsymbol{r}}{\mathrm{d}t},$$
which I just defined as velocity. Although velocity is relative to the frame of reference, this relativity only produces a difference if both origins are in relative motion, which they are not in the situation you described. (If you think of it, it really makes sense that way. Relative velocity is just a vector in absolute space. It may depend on time, but why would it depend on an arbitrary frame, that someone sets up in space? A vector, as a geometric object, is supposed to be independent of basis.)

Now proceeding to acceleration, using ##\boldsymbol{v}=0##, ##\boldsymbol{\omega}=\text{const.}##, and -- obviously -- ##\boldsymbol{r}\cdot\boldsymbol{\omega}=0##, we get
$$ \ddot{r}^i\boldsymbol{e}_i = \boldsymbol{a} = \ddot{\tilde r}^i \boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i + \dot{\tilde r}^i \boldsymbol{\omega}\times \boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i = \ddot{\tilde r}^i \boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i - \boldsymbol{\omega}\times(\boldsymbol{\omega}\times\boldsymbol{r}) = \ddot{\tilde r}^i\boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i + \omega^2 \boldsymbol{r}$$
which again vanishes since the left hand side vanishes by assumption. Now it is clear that what you call "acceleration" is just the term
$$\ddot{\tilde r}^i\boldsymbol{\tilde e}_i = -\omega^2 \boldsymbol{r}.$$
But again, this is not the time derivative of velocity relative to the rotating system, because it neglects the rotation of the axes, which change with time. It is no accident that textbooks introduce a special notation for this kind of operation, usually
$$\left(\frac{\mathrm{d}^2\boldsymbol{r}}{\mathrm{d}t^2}\right)_{S'}$$
because it needs to be distinguished from the covariant time derivative ##\mathrm{d}/\mathrm{d}t##.

Now another point needs to be mentioned. Just as the relative velocities are equal, iff the origins are not in relative motion, so the accelerations -- calculated in the way above -- are equal only if the origins have constant relative velocity. Now, from what I just said it seems to follow that the application of Newton's axioms will be ambiguous if both origins are accelerating relative to each other. Because in that situation both systems seem to assign different accelerations to the same particle. But this is only apparent. Let's review the basic assumption that real forces, according either to the Third Law or to our general understanding of the interactions of that particular system, represent the cause for change of the particle's state of motion. Any causal effects on this state can only depend on the particle's state and properties, not on how arbitrarily definable "origins" are moving. This is why the acceleration in ##m\boldsymbol{a} = \boldsymbol{F}## must be covariantly defined, by

$$\nabla_{\boldsymbol{u}} \boldsymbol{u} = \boldsymbol{a},$$

which manifestly depends only on the particles motion through spacetime.
This acceleration equals the second derivative of position ##\frac{\mathrm{d}^2 \boldsymbol{r}}{\mathrm{d}t^2} = \nabla_{\boldsymbol{e}_0}\boldsymbol{v} = \nabla_{\boldsymbol{e}_0}(\boldsymbol{u} - \boldsymbol{e}_0) = \boldsymbol{a} - \nabla_{\boldsymbol{e}_0} \boldsymbol{e}_0## only under the condition that ##\nabla_{\boldsymbol{e}_0}\boldsymbol{e}_0 = 0##, i.e. if the origin itself is moving on a straight and uniform trajectory (geodesic). This should be an immediately intuitive result.

That a definition based on the (second order) change of position can only be correct in special situations is, I think, not surprising. "Change of position" is an ill-defined concept anyway in light of the Principle of Relativity. It is only defined relative to an object of reference, which can itself change its state of motion arbitrarily. What objects are suitable references for this purpose is completely explained within the theory by means of the analysis above. What is always well-defined, however, without any reference are deviations from geodesic (straight and uniform) motions in spacetime.

In elementary treatments this complication doesn't show up, because there is always one inertial system involved relative to which all accelerations can be unambiguously equated with the second derivative of position (which is therefore used as a universal definition of acceleration). This makes it less obvious how a fully covariant formulation looks like and it seems that one inertial frame is always required. That this is not so, is only apparent when the laws are formulated in Newtonian spacetime. In any case, as shown by the Newton-Cartan-Theory, it is possible to formulate Newton's laws in a fully covariant way, which means the claim that some of these laws must be violated in non-inertial reference frames seems untenable to me. Furthermore, this spurious violation cannot be a valid basis for the definition of inertial frames.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #130
atyy said:
Yes, if the gravitational field is truly uniform over all space, then one cannot distinguish it from an accelerated frame. However, suppose we have an infinite plane mass that produces a uniform gravitational field over the half space. N3 can distinguish between a real uniform gravitational field and an accelerated frame, since N3 would predict that the real gravitational field is produced by matter.

Newton-Cartan-Theory also predicts that all gravity is produced by matter. In both formulations of the theory you can cancel a homogeneous gravitational field by constant acceleration. Where exactly do you see a difference here?

Also, I am not arguing that the Third Law is useless for everything. I am just saying that it is not needed to define inertial frames.
 
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #131
Indeed, the reason for the confusion when considering non-inertial (particularly rotating) frames is to mix up the components of vectors wrt. the rotating basis with the vectors themselves.

You can simply work with the vectors, and nothing particular happens, i.e., if ##\vec{e}_j## are (time-independent) Cartesian basis vectors wrt. the intertial frame and ##\vec{e}_k'(t)## the basis vectors wrt. the rotating frame you have for any vector (Einstein summation convention used)
$$\vec{V}(t)=V_j(t) \vec{e}_j=V_k'(t) \vec{e}_k'(t),$$
and then
$$\dot{\vec{V}}(t)=\dot{V}_j (t) \vec{e}_j =\dot{V}_k'(t) \vec{e}_k'(t) + V_k'(t) \dot{\vec{e}}_k'(t).$$
Now since ##\vec{e}_k'(t)## also Cartesian since they are just the rotated vectors of the inertial Cartesian basis vectors, you have
$$\dot{\vec{V}}(t)=[\dot{V}_k'(t) + \epsilon_{klm} \omega_l(t) V_{m}'(t)]\vec{e}_k',$$
i.e., there's an additional term from the time derivative of the rotating basis vectors. Defining the covariant time derivative for vector components (not vectors!) as
$$\mathrm{D}_t V_k'=\dot{V}_k' + \epsilon_{klm} \omega_l V_m',$$
The equation of motion reads
$$m \mathrm{D}_t^2 x_k'=F_k'.$$
There are only "true forces", no "fictitious" or "inertial" forces. Only if you insist to bring the corresponding terms of the 2nd covariant time derivative to the other side solving for ##m \ddot{x}_k'##, you get these additional "forces".

If all forces are pair forces obeying Newton III, momentum conservation holds in any frame too. You just have in terms of the components wrt. the inertial frame
$$p_k'=m \mathrm{D}_t x_k'.$$
 
  • Like
Likes vis_insita
  • #132
vis_insita said:
Also, I am not arguing that the Third Law is useless for everything. I am just saying that it is not needed to define inertial frames
Did you ever mention how you include the third law in your description of the force as a field?
 
  • #133
Dale said:
Did you ever mention how you include the third law in your description of the force as a field?

I tried to give an answer here. The short version is that it is not possible. If you want to include the Third Law in a covariant way, you have to substitute force fields for other geometric objects depending on 2 (or n) simultaneous events, not just a single event. Thus they can't be seen as fields or even functions F(x, y, ...) of multiple events in spacetime. I don't think it would be impossible to introduce such a concept to Newtonian spacetime. But it is probably unnecessary to do so. I'm not aware that such objects are studied in the context of Newton-Cartan-Theory, which seems to be really only concerned with gravity. And gravity is described by a field equation (reinterpreting the Laplacian of the potential as Ricci-Curvature). But for me this only underlines that the Third Law is of minor importance to the theory. What do you think?
 
  • #134
vis_insita said:
I tried to give an answer here. The short version is that it is not possible.
Ah, I don't know how I missed that, particularly since you tagged me even!

vis_insita said:
If you want to include the Third Law in a covariant way, you have to substitute force fields for other geometric objects depending on 2 (or n) simultaneous events, not just a single event. Thus they can't be seen as fields or even functions F(x, y, ...) of multiple events in spacetime. I don't think it would be impossible to introduce such a concept to Newtonian spacetime. But it is probably unnecessary to do so. I'm not aware that such objects are studied in the context of Newton-Cartan-Theory, which seems to be really only concerned with gravity. And gravity is described by a field equation (reinterpreting the Laplacian of the potential as Ricci-Curvature). But for me this only underlines that the Third Law is of minor importance to the theory. What do you think?
I don't think that I would say the 3rd law is of minor importance since it produces conservation of momentum. However, I guess that the proper approach would be to apply Noether's theorem to the covariant formulation (with the assumption of spatial homogeneity), and derive the corresponding restriction on F that leads to conservation of momentum. Then that restriction could be considered a generalization of Newton's 3rd law.
 
  • Like
Likes vis_insita and vanhees71
  • #135
vis_insita said:
I think nothing in your (or Newton's) formulation of the axioms implies that switching to a rotating frame changes the particle's acceleration to ##-\omega^2 r##.

Your argumentation is based on the assumption that Newton's laws of motion must be used with proper acceleration and not with coordinate acceleration. Is there any indication that Newton didn't refer to positions, velocities and accelerations that are measured within (and with respect to) a given frame of reference?
 
  • Like
Likes olgerm
  • #136
olgerm said:
But how would you define inertial frame of reference WITH Newton's 3. law?

Inertial frames of reference always comply with the laws of motion.

That's it.
 
  • Like
Likes olgerm
  • #137
DrStupid said:
OK, let's say you have your non-interacting particles. How do you define an inertial frame with Newton I but without Newton III?
I think you may have be even right all along. misunderstanding is due to vague definition of ineraction and force (are inertial forces forces, are inrtial interactions interactions).

Just definition: "inertial frame of reference is frame of reference in which, forceless particles are moving without acceleration"
is not fine, because according to ##F=\frac{\partial^2 x}{\partial t^2}*m## inertial force is force and according to following this bad definition all frames of references were inertial.

definition: "inertial frame of reference is frame of reference in which, non-interacting particles are moving without acceleration"
is fine only if inertial forces are not considered interactions. Maybe it is possible to state it without using Newton's 3. law.
 
Last edited:
  • #138
DrStupid said:
Is there any indication that Newton didn't refer to positions, velocities and accelerations that are measured within (and with respect to) a given frame of reference?
I don't think that the concept of a reference frame had even been invented at that time. Certainly, he does not explicitly discuss distinctions between inertial frames, non-inertial frames, and covariant formulations.

This is partly why the seminal authors do not get the final say on their work, there is simply no way that they could foresee subsequent theoretical and experimental developments. His unavoidable ignorance on such topics makes his stance somewhat irrelevant to a modern dialog on these specific aspects of his theory.

This is physics, not history, and physics can be rewritten by each new generation of physicists (whereas history should not!).
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #139
Dale said:
I don't think that I would say the 3rd law is of minor importance since it produces conservation of momentum. However, I guess that the proper approach would be to apply Noether's theorem to the covariant formulation (with the assumption of spatial homogeneity), and derive the corresponding restriction on F that leads to conservation of momentum. Then that restriction could be considered a generalization of Newton's 3rd law.

Yes, but still you would have presuppose non-local interactions for this to work, wouldn't you? The only homogeneous force field that conserves momentum is F(x) = 0. Only if F depends on more than one particle location at the same time can there be less trivial solutions like F(x-y) etc.

I guess that non-locality is why I said "unimportant". The other two laws appear much more universal. They can be carried over to relativistic theories almost verbatim. (Of course the meaning of the terms change in accordance with space time structure.) But in relativity, momentum conservation cannot be formulated as a condition on forces anymore. But maybe what I really meant is not "unimportant", but rather "imposing too strong conditions on interactions".
 
  • Like
Likes kith and Dale
  • #140
vis_insita said:
Yes, but still you would have presuppose non-local interactions for this to work, wouldn't you?
I would believe so, with the caveat that I have not worked out the math to make sure. But without going through the math I cannot see any way that it could work out with purely local interactions. However, in Newtonian theory there is no a priori reason to forbid non-local interactions.

vis_insita said:
I guess that non-locality is why I said "unimportant". The other two laws appear much more universal. They can be carried over to relativistic theories almost verbatim. (Of course the meaning of the terms change in accordance with space time structure.) But in relativity, momentum conservation cannot be formulated as a condition on forces anymore. But maybe what I really meant is not "unimportant", but rather "imposing too strong conditions on interactions".
I like that better. I think you are correct here.
 

Similar threads

Replies
117
Views
8K
Replies
10
Views
1K
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
53
Views
3K
Replies
11
Views
1K
Replies
10
Views
4K
Replies
30
Views
4K
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
5
Views
5K
Back
Top