When does entanglement actually end?

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of entanglement and when it ends in the context of polarizing beam splitters and filters. There is a disagreement on whether entanglement ends when particles collide with other particles or when there is an irreversible measurement made. The possibility of reversing a measurement and the role of decoherence in entanglement are also mentioned. The idea of entanglement being a manifestation of the measurement process is brought up, and the concept of polarization by reflection is briefly discussed.
  • #36
DrChinese said:
Of course I essentially agree with this. But here is something that is puzzling me. The question is often asked: Is collapse a physical process? I see (sorta) how MWI and orthodox QM handle it. But I really don't see how the dBB (Bohmian) theory would address it, because it postulates that there is an underlying mechanism (even though uncertainty is supplied to match experiment). Now I ask: if there is such a mechanism, how can we have *partial* collapse of the wave function? As long as we focus on the formalism (going no further), everything fits. But going a step further (which is the point of dBB), it seems we get into a pretty strange place.

In Bohmian mechanics, there is no collapse: the "guiding field" (deduced from the unitarily evolving wavefunction) goes on without collapsing (just as in MWI). The actual "collapse" just comes about because the particles HAVE specific positions, and hence go this or that way under the quantum force (and in doing so, change the quantum force on all other particles, that's the famous "action at a distance" in BM). However, because before the measurement, we didn't know what the position was, and the possible positions of the particles are such that we need the "entire wavefunction" to predict the possible evolutions of all those possible positions ; after measurement, we've reduced the probability distribution of the positions (because of the measurement result), and hence we now don't NEED anymore the "other branches" of the wavefunction. We can keep them, though. They won't affect future evolution of the particle positions anymore. So we can just as well "cut them away" from the wavefunction (collapse it). But you're not obliged to do so.
Simply because we now KNOW that the particles are in certain positions (or regions), so our probability distribution has "retracted", and we don't need the evolution anymore of pieces of wavefunction (of configuration space), simply because there's no probability there anymore.

EDIT: the behaviour of particles in BM is exactly as in statistical (classical) mechanics: you suppose that they HAVE a specific position, but you only KNOW about a distribution. So you need the dynamics that handles ALL of these potential positions until you learn more about the positions, in which case you can truncate the needed dynamics of positions (given that you won't need those anymore that you now KNOW have probability 0). So you can "leave that part of the dynamics out" if you wish - but you can just as well keep it, it won't make any difference. It is a bit (very naive analogy) as if you looked at the Newtonian gravitational potential of the sun, extending to all of space. And then you find out that the Earth and the planets only orbit the sun in a certain region of space: you can just as well "set the rest of the potential to zero" what the effect of the sun on the planets' dynamics is concerned. Or keep it the way it is. It won't make any difference for the motion of the planets.

Now, you can ask: but in about all of quantum mechanics, people always insist (me included) that you CAN'T see the wavefunction as a probability distribution, because that screws up quantum interference. How come that this is exactly what is done in Bohmian mechanics ? Answer: because BM restores quantum interference by subtle action-at-a-distance effects in the quantum force. Particle A will get a pull to the left or to the right according to whether particle B, potentially miles away, will be 5 microns more to the left or to the right.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
vanesch said:
In Bohmian mechanics, there is no collapse: the "guiding field" (deduced from the unitarily evolving wavefunction) goes on without collapsing (just as in MWI). The actual "collapse" just comes about because the particles HAVE specific positions, and hence go this or that way under the quantum force (and in doing so, change the quantum force on all other particles, that's the famous "action at a distance" in BM). However, because before the measurement, we didn't know what the position was, and the possible positions of the particles are such that we need the "entire wavefunction" to predict the possible evolutions of all those possible positions ; after measurement, we've reduced the probability distribution of the positions (because of the measurement result), and hence we now don't NEED anymore the "other branches" of the wavefunction. We can keep them, though. They won't affect future evolution of the particle positions anymore. So we can just as well "cut them away" from the wavefunction (collapse it). But you're not obliged to do so.
Simply because we now KNOW that the particles are in certain positions (or regions), so our probability distribution has "retracted", and we don't need the evolution anymore of pieces of wavefunction (of configuration space), simply because there's no probability there anymore.

EDIT: the behaviour of particles in BM is exactly as in statistical (classical) mechanics: you suppose that they HAVE a specific position, but you only KNOW about a distribution. So you need the dynamics that handles ALL of these potential positions until you learn more about the positions, in which case you can truncate the needed dynamics of positions (given that you won't need those anymore that you now KNOW have probability 0). So you can "leave that part of the dynamics out" if you wish - but you can just as well keep it, it won't make any difference. It is a bit (very naive analogy) as if you looked at the Newtonian gravitational potential of the sun, extending to all of space. And then you find out that the Earth and the planets only orbit the sun in a certain region of space: you can just as well "set the rest of the potential to zero" what the effect of the sun on the planets' dynamics is concerned. Or keep it the way it is. It won't make any difference for the motion of the planets.

Now, you can ask: but in about all of quantum mechanics, people always insist (me included) that you CAN'T see the wavefunction as a probability distribution, because that screws up quantum interference. How come that this is exactly what is done in Bohmian mechanics ? Answer: because BM restores quantum interference by subtle action-at-a-distance effects in the quantum force. Particle A will get a pull to the left or to the right according to whether particle B, potentially miles away, will be 5 microns more to the left or to the right.

But I think that there MUST be definite constraints on the dBB/Bohmian-type solutions if entanglement can be partial. So let's say that Alice is affected by Joe. I guess you could say they are entangled in a sense. And yet, it is Bob's measurement (i.e. how Bob is measured) - and not Joe's - that affects the correlation of Alice and Bob. And further, Alice and Bob can (and probably will) remain entangled afterwards!

Now why do I say that there is a constraint? Because the Bohmian solutions (generally) argue for the primacy of particle position. It is not reasonable that a distribution of deterministic particle positions should simultaneously determine Alice and Bob AND have Alice and Bob as entangled per the results of Bell tests. Clearly, the only variable in their correlations is their observed relative angle to each other. The positions of the remainder of the particles in the universe - indeed the relative time at which they are measured - are not factors even though you would reasonably expect then to be significant factors (by definition). So the constraint I see is: a) the impact of the positions of other particles combined with b) the relative time at which they are observed (since presumably the positions of all particles will be different) must be such that a) + b) completely cancel out. Further, they result in the end of the entanglement for those specific observables, but not for other commuting observables.

My point being: QM is silent and does not postulate mechanics for collapse. So it is mysterious in that respect - a valid criticism although there is no technical flaw. BM is not silent, but I don't think it can withstand the subtle questions that lie in the aftermath of Bell's Theorem. You still have to ask: how can Alice and Bob be entangled in such a way that Bell tests show exactly the correlations they do if their spin characteristics are predetermined but still subject to the influence of the remainder of the universe - when clearly that influence must be nil (else there would not be perfect correlations as well when there are matching angle settings but the observations are at different points in time and space).

From the Stanford Encyclopedia entry on Bohmian Mechanics by Goldstein:

"13. Nonlocality

"Bohmian mechanics is manifestly nonlocal: The velocity, as expressed in the guiding equation, of anyone of the particles of a many-particle system will typically depend upon the positions of the other, possibly distant, particles whenever the wave function of the system is entangled, i.e., not a product of single-particle wave functions. This is true, for example, for the EPR-Bohm wave function, describing a pair of spin-1/2 particles in the singlet state, analyzed by Bell and many others. Thus does Bohmian mechanics make explicit the most dramatic feature of quantum theory: quantum nonlocality.

"It should be emphasized that the nonlocality of Bohmian mechanics derives solely from the nonlocality built into the structure of standard quantum theory, as provided by a wave function on configuration space, an abstraction which, roughly speaking, combines — or binds — distant particles into a single irreducible reality. As Bell (Bell 1987, p. 115) has stressed,

'That the guiding wave, in the general case, propagates not in ordinary three-space but in a multidimensional-configuration space is the origin of the notorious ‘nonlocality’ of quantum mechanics. It is a merit of the de Broglie-Bohm version to bring this out so explicitly that it cannot be ignored.'

"Thus the nonlocal velocity relation in the guiding equation is but one aspect of the nonlocality of Bohmian mechanics. There is also the nonlocality, or nonseparability, implicit in the wave function itself and in its propagation, a nonlocality that does not in fact assume the structure — actual configurations — that Bohmian mechanics adds to orthodox quantum theory. And as Bell has shown, using the connection between the wave function and the predictions of quantum theory concerning experimental results, this nonlocality cannot easily be argued away (see Section 2).

"The nonlocality of Bohmian mechanics can be appreciated perhaps most efficiently, in all its aspects, by focusing on the conditional wave function. Suppose, for example, that in an EPR-Bohm experiment particle 1 passes through its Stern-Gerlach magnet before particle 2 arrives at its magnet. Then the orientation of the Stern-Gerlach magnet for particle 1 will have a significant effect upon the conditional wave function of particle 2: If the Stern-Gerlach magnet for particle 1 is so oriented as to "measure the z-component of spin," then after particle 1 has passed through its magnet the conditional wave function of particle 2 will be an eigenvector (or eigenstate) of the z-component of spin (in fact, belonging to the eigenvalue that is the negative of the one "measured" for particle 1), and the same thing is true for any other component of spin. You can dictate the kind of spin eigenstate produced for particle 2 by appropriately choosing the orientation of an arbitrarily distant magnet. As to the future behavior of particle 2, in particular how it is affected by its magnet, this of course depends very much on the character of its conditional wave function and hence is very strongly influenced by the choice of orientation of the distant magnet.

"This nonlocal effect upon the conditional wave function of particle 2 follows from combining the standard analysis of the evolution of the wave function in the EPR-Bohm experiment with the definition of the conditional wave function. (For simplicity, we ignore permutation symmetry.) Before any magnets have been reached the EPR-Bohm wave function is a sum of two terms, corresponding to nonvanishing values for two of the four possible joint spin components for the two particles, each term a product of an eigenstate for a component of spin in a given direction for particle 1 with the opposite eigenstate (i.e., belonging to the eigenvalue that is the negative of the eigenvalue for particle 1) for the component of spin in the same direction for particle 2. Moreover, by virtue of its symmetry under rotations, it happens that the EPR-Bohm wave function has the property that any component of spin, i.e., any direction, can be used in this decomposition. (This property is very interesting.)

"Decomposing the EPR-Bohm wave function using the component of spin in the direction associated with the magnet for particle 1, the evolution of the wave function as particle 1 passes its magnet is easy to grasp: The evolution of the sum is determined (using linearity) by that of its individual terms, and the evolution of each term by that of each of its factors. The evolution of the particle-1 factor leads to a displacement along the magnetic axis in the direction determined by the (sign of the) spin component (i.e., the eigenvalue), as described in the fourth paragraph of Section 11. Once this displacement has occurred (and is large enough) the conditional wave function for particle 2 will correspond to the term in the sum selected by the actual position of particle 1. In particular, it will be an eigenstate of the component of spin "measured by" the magnet for particle 1.

"The nonlocality of Bohmian mechanics has a remarkable feature: it is screened by quantum equilibrium. It is a consequence of the quantum equilibrium hypothesis that the nonlocal effects in Bohmian mechanics don't yield observable consequences..."


I am not arguing that there is not a non-local component to BM/dBB, as I think this is pretty clear both from the above and the more detailed descriptions of the basic formulas I have seen. I am simply saying that the proposed mechanism doesn't seem to be suited for describing both full entanglement and partial entanglement scenarios. Just having a non-local component does NOT give Bohmian solutions a "pass" on Bell's Theorem. The non-local component must fully explain the observed correlations too, in order for the pass to be valid. It is completely unreasonably to me that - to paraphrase Goldstein above: The setting for magnet A affects the outcome at B, and yet has no affect on commuting observables for A or B.
 
  • #38
vanesch said:
No. You see, there's no such thing as "entangled data", that was my point. You can find *correlations* in data. But *entanglement* is a concept that only makes sense in quantum theory (unless one gives it another definition in another theory). There's nothing "observable" about entanglement. Of course, entangled quantum objects will, through quantum theory, give rise to predictions of certain correlations, but these correlations could also occur by, say, action-at-a-distance theories.
OK, I understand that quantum entanglement is formally different from, say, quantum action-at-a-distance in that the former "is not to be written as the product of two states each belonging to the subspaces of the respective subsystems", but the latter might be.

But suppose we want to interpret the formal expression of quantum entanglement in order to give it some physical meaning. Then can't we say that data correlations satisfying certain criteria are the objectively physical manifestation of the formal expression?

There is something observable about entanglement (even though quantum states themselves aren't observable), else how would you know if you'd produced it or changed it experimentally?

Of course there's no way to tell if the correlations have been produced by FTL communication of some sort between the spatially separated filtration-detection setups, or not.

But, no matter which is the case, we're still dealing with some sort of relationship between coincidentally accumulated data attributes -- and this relationship is physically defined by the experimental preparations and designs and, ultimately, the results.

Here's Schrodinger's characterization of entanglement:
"When two systems, of which we know the states by their respective representatives, enter into temporary physical interaction due to known forces between them, and when after a time of mutual influence the systems separate again, then they can no longer be described in the same way as before, viz. by endowing each of them with a representative of its own. I would not call that one but rather the characteristic trait of quantum mechanics, the one that enforces its entire departure from classical lines of thought. By the interaction the two representatives [the quantum states] have become entangled."

What's my point? I think that we can speak in terms of entangled data without getting into too much semantic trouble. But if you want to be nitpicky about it, then I see your point -- entanglement refers directly to quantum states, and quantum states aren't to be taken literally as real physical states.

vanesch said:
BTW, speculation about the nature of fundamental theoretical concepts is always a "futile exercise" apart from giving you a mental picture.
Following the previous thread on entanglement in which I participated, I no longer have a mental picture of the deep nature of entanglement. :smile:

In saying that speculation about the nature of fundamental theoretical concepts is always a futile exercise, I mean that it seems that no undisputedly correct mental picture (of the deep nature of quantum processes) is even possible ... ever. This is the state of affairs that I'm unhappy about. But I guess I'll get over it. :smile:
 
Last edited:
  • #39
ThomasT said:
In saying that speculation about the nature of fundamental theoretical concepts is always a futile exercise, I mean that it seems that no undisputedly correct mental picture (of the deep nature of quantum processes) is even possible ... ever. This is the state of affairs that I'm unhappy about. But I guess I'll get over it. :smile:

The 'mental picture' is lacking probably because we are trying to think in lengths and areas etc whereas we are operating below that level and need a different way of thinking. Is it a law that we will never know, or is it that we have not got a correct view yet? I believe the latter unless there is some proof otherwise. Consciouseness itself is a very powerful force in the Universe because it produces knowledge that is a scarce commodity in the Universe (see David Deutsch youtube lecture).
 
  • #40
wawenspop said:
The 'mental picture' is lacking probably because we are trying to think in lengths and areas etc whereas we are operating below that level and need a different way of thinking.
Length scales below those which can be directly accessed either by our sensory capabilities or the machines that augment those capabilities are still length scales. There are lengths and areas and volumes even wrt the submicroscopic world. To say that we're operating below the level of "lengths and areas etc" doesn't make sense to me. Any operations that are carried out by us are on the macro, meso, or microscopic levels and our familiar, standardized concepts of "lengths and areas etc" apply.

wawenspop said:
Is it a law that we will never know, or is it that we have not got a correct view yet? I believe the latter unless there is some proof otherwise.
It seems that the existence of a fundamental quantum of action prevents (and Bell's theorem and the Copenhagen Interpretation have helped us to realize) our ever being able to visualize quantum processes the way we can visualize classical processes -- in terms of analogies from everyday experience.

One law pertaining to this would be Heisenberg's uncertainty relations -- that for a large number of similarly prepared measurements on any pair of canonically conjugate variables, the product of the statistical spread around an average value for one variable (eg., delta q, the variance in measurements of position) and the statistical spread around an average value for the other variable (eg., delta p, the variance in measurements of velocity or momentum) must be less than or equal to h (Planck's constant).

wawenspop said:
Consciouseness itself is a very powerful force in the Universe because it produces knowledge that is a scarce commodity in the Universe (see David Deutsch youtube lecture).
This is off topic, but you might start a new thread in the philosophy section.
 
  • #41
ThomasT said:
What's my point? I think that we can speak in terms of entangled data without getting into too much semantic trouble. But if you want to be nitpicky about it, then I see your point -- entanglement refers directly to quantum states, and quantum states aren't to be taken literally as real physical states.

If I give you 2 or 3 or ... series of data (lists of real numbers with a time tag on it), how are you going to say whether they are "entangled" data or not ?

You can find statistical *correlations* between them, but what would it mean for them to be "entangled" ?
 
  • #42
ThomasT said:
One law pertaining to this would be Heisenberg's uncertainty relations -- that for a large number of similarly prepared measurements on any pair of canonically conjugate variables, the product of the statistical spread around an average value for one variable (eg., delta q, the variance in measurements of position) and the statistical spread around an average value for the other variable (eg., delta p, the variance in measurements of velocity or momentum) must be less than or equal to h (Planck's constant).
That should be greater than or equal to h.
 
  • #43
vanesch said:
If I give you 2 or 3 or ... series of data (lists of real numbers with a time tag on it), how are you going to say whether they are "entangled" data or not ?

You can find statistical *correlations* between them, but what would it mean for them to be "entangled" ?
OK, good point. Since I don't know enough about the salient features of all the different sorts and configurations of data produced via entanglement experiments to be able to abstract a set of criteria for deciding whether some data were entangled or not, then the only way I could decide if the correlated data were actually entangled would be to know the whole experimental design and procedure.

How does one know if a certain experiment has produced entanglement?

Can we speak of entangled photons, or electrons? If so, what corresponds to these things in the physical world? Is it data bits? Or, is it, following Bohr, the entire experimental procedure which defines their existence?
 
  • #44
ThomasT said:
How does one know if a certain experiment has produced entanglement?

Can we speak of entangled photons, or electrons? If so, what corresponds to these things in the physical world? Is it data bits? Or, is it, following Bohr, the entire experimental procedure which defines their existence?

That's my point: you cannot, without any theoretical frame, conclude that "entanglement happened", or that a certain experiment has "produced entanglement" or something of the kind. Entanglement is a formal concept within the theoretical framework of quantum theory - and outside of that theoretical framework it doesn't have any meaning. Entanglement is a property of vectors in a product hilbert space. Within quantum theory, it is possible to say that *according to the theory* this system should now be in an entangled quantum state. And it is also true that *according to the theory*, this usually leads to correlations in the data. THESE correlations can be observed and if these correlations correspond with the theoretical predictions, we can as a kind of shortcut say that "entanglement has been observed" but what's in fact meant is that the correlations are being observed in agreement with the predictions of quantum theory on an entangled state. OTHER theories can predict similar or identical correlations without ever introducing something like "entanglement".
 
  • #45
vanesch said:
... the correlations are being observed in agreement with the predictions of quantum theory on an entangled state. OTHER theories can predict similar or identical correlations without ever introducing something like "entanglement".

I understood that correlations of states of entangled particles was a postulate of QM and not a result of QM - i.e. there is no explanation as to why or how, rather 'correlations happen', then the QM put a mathematical framework around it (tensor product of Hilbert spaces etc) to formalize it and allow calculations to predict experimental results.
 
  • #46
wawenspop said:
I understood that correlations of states of entangled particles was a postulate of QM and not a result of QM - i.e. there is no explanation as to why or how, rather 'correlations happen', then the QM put a mathematical framework around it (tensor product of Hilbert spaces etc) to formalize it and allow calculations to predict experimental results.

It may be mincing words, but QM made many of these predictions well before there were any results to discuss. It was not the other way around, though obviously the early (1925-1927) development of QM did consider extant lab results.

As of 1935, when EPR was written, there was no experimental knowledge of entangled particles. The EPR article was merely hypothetical in that regard. At some point, it was realized that particle pairs could appear in the singlet state - and those would have the properties Vanesch describes. But the key point is that the mathematical formalism itself led to many predictions (anti-matter, neutrinos being perhaps examples in addition to entanglement) even though there was no known mechanism (or evidence) for some of these things to occur. And even today, there is no known mechanism for entanglement per se other than the formalism.

The amazing thing is that the QM formalism supports partial collapse, which can be demonstrated experimentally. Any competing theory will need to include that too. I assume that most (if not all) virtual particle pairs are entangled too, since their spin presumably nets to zero.
 
  • #47
vanesch said:
That's my point: you cannot, without any theoretical frame, conclude that "entanglement happened", or that a certain experiment has "produced entanglement" or something of the kind. Entanglement is a formal concept within the theoretical framework of quantum theory - and outside of that theoretical framework it doesn't have any meaning.

Ok, I'll grant you that quantum entanglement is a term that is peculiar to, and only has meaning within, the framework of the quantum theory. Nevertheless, and even though quantum state evolutions take place in an imaginary space, at least some of the symbolic representations that comprise the theory itself have a meaning that can be translated into experimental manipulations.

Following Schrodinger, if the essence of quantum entanglement is the theoretical nonseparability of two or more quanta brought about via the physical interaction and mutual influence of two or more quantum scale physical entities , or the common influencing of two or more quantum scale physical entities, then theoretical quantum entanglement is inexorably linked with experimental quantum entanglement, isn't it? In fact, the way that Schrodinger talks about quantum entanglement seems to me to lend itself quite easily to classical analogy -- even though Schrodinger himself says that it doesn't -- because the separate systems can still be dealt with separately -- it's just that if they're looked at separately after they've interacted or been subjected to a common influence then any entanglement that is present won't emerge as a product of the individual probabilities, but will emerge only with respect to some global experimental parameter which reveals the statistical dependence produced via the mutual interaction or common influencing.

vanesch said:
Entanglement is a property of vectors in a product hilbert space. Within quantum theory, it is possible to say that *according to the theory* this system should now be in an entangled quantum state. And it is also true that *according to the theory*, this usually leads to correlations in the data. THESE correlations can be observed and if these correlations correspond with the theoretical predictions, we can as a kind of shortcut say that "entanglement has been observed" but what's in fact meant is that the correlations are being observed in agreement with the predictions of quantum theory on an entangled state. OTHER theories can predict similar or identical correlations without ever introducing something like "entanglement".
If the physical essence of quantum entanglement is interaction and mutual (common) influence, then in order to produce the correlations that correspond to quantum entanglement per quantum theory it would be necessary to duplicate the experimental conditions. A rose by any other name is still a rose.

If you maintain that there is no physical understanding of the deep nature of quantum entanglement, then your argument makes sense to me. However (ironically?) your position on this would seem to affect your point of departure (ie. necessary assumptions re the meaning of the quantum theoretical formalism) in accepting MWI as a credible alternative to the orthodox probability interpretation.

Of course, there is an understanding of the experimental preparations which produce entangled quantum states -- and these involve interactions and common influences. don't they? So, even if we want to call it something else, or represent it in a different way theoretically, we're still talking about the same thing -- and we know that because of the material and instrumental preparations and the data accumulation and processing, don't we?

Having said that, I will concede that you are technically correct (DrChinese's post 46 underlines why) -- and, in the interest of unambiguous communication, I will no longer speak of entangled data. :smile:
 
  • #48
When agree to take a Hilbert space product for the two entangled particles H spaces,
then we are assuming entanglement has taken place, otherwise we would have no
justification to do that. Then we get correct (as of present time) predications
to use in our experiments.

If we ask where does that justification come from? I suggest it comes concepts such
as 'when two particles collide then there total momentum (say) remains the constant
even when separated. In that sense they are correlated.

Then using QM, the unceraintities in the EXACT momemtums of each particle must still
add up to that original total. And this is where the 'strangeness' creeps in, because
how does one particle 'know' what the other's probabilty came out to be? (when they were
spacially separated).
 
  • #49
ThomasT said:
Ok, I'll grant you that quantum entanglement is a term that is peculiar to, and only has meaning within, the framework of the quantum theory. Nevertheless, and even though quantum state evolutions take place in an imaginary space, at least some of the symbolic representations that comprise the theory itself have a meaning that can be translated into experimental manipulations.

The experimental manipulations that give, in the frame of a quantum-mechanical treatment, rise to entangled states, would normally be called "interactions". In fact, quantum theory is such that when initially non-entangled systems interact, they usually end up in an entangled state. In classical physics, this is not the case: individual systems keep their "individuality" after an interaction, while quantum systems (with the quantum mechanical description) can have a certain "individuality" before interaction, but loose it upon interaction. So the experimental setup that "gives rise to entanglement" is interaction. If a classical physicist were looking at the experimental preparation, he'd see nothing else but "things that are set up to interact".

Following Schrodinger, if the essence of quantum entanglement is the theoretical nonseparability of two or more quanta brought about via the physical interaction and mutual influence of two or more quantum scale physical entities , or the common influencing of two or more quantum scale physical entities, then theoretical quantum entanglement is inexorably linked with experimental quantum entanglement, isn't it?

Yes, that's exactly it: two systems that are entangled have no "individual identity" anymore in their quantum-mechanical description. But again, that's a sheer property of the quantum-mechanical description.

In fact, the way that Schrodinger talks about quantum entanglement seems to me to lend itself quite easily to classical analogy -- even though Schrodinger himself says that it doesn't -- because the separate systems can still be dealt with separately -- it's just that if they're looked at separately after they've interacted or been subjected to a common influence then any entanglement that is present won't emerge as a product of the individual probabilities, but will emerge only with respect to some global experimental parameter which reveals the statistical dependence produced via the mutual interaction or common influencing.

Indeed, that's how classical action-at-a-distance can mimic perfectly the quantum-mechanical entanglement (or, quantum-mechanical entanglement can mimic perfectly action-at-a-distance ; depends on your PoV).

If the physical essence of quantum entanglement is interaction and mutual (common) influence, then in order to produce the correlations that correspond to quantum entanglement per quantum theory it would be necessary to duplicate the experimental conditions. A rose by any other name is still a rose.

I don't understand what you say here.

If you maintain that there is no physical understanding of the deep nature of quantum entanglement, then your argument makes sense to me. However (ironically?) your position on this would seem to affect your point of departure (ie. necessary assumptions re the meaning of the quantum theoretical formalism) in accepting MWI as a credible alternative to the orthodox probability interpretation.

I try to keep a distinction between what is "hard fact" and what are interpretational pictures. MWI is a way of giving a picture to the quantum-mechanical happening, which "explains" then of course entanglement and all that - but it's only that: a picture. It's not a hard fact.

Of course, there is an understanding of the experimental preparations which produce entangled quantum states -- and these involve interactions and common influences. don't they? So, even if we want to call it something else, or represent it in a different way theoretically, we're still talking about the same thing -- and we know that because of the material and instrumental preparations and the data accumulation and processing, don't we?

Entanglement is - within quantum theory - caused by interactions. That doesn't mean that "interaction = entanglement". But the experimental setup, which, to a quantum physicist, prepares an entangled state, would, to a classical physicist, just let some systems interact.

It is true that, through the quantum formalism, entangled states give rise to weird correlations which cannot always be explained by classical interaction, locality and some other reasonable assumptions (re Bell's theorem and all that). So our classical physicist will then invent "action-at-a-distance" or "superdeterminism" or something of the kind to explain the correlations that he finds from his experiment, because he cannot explain them in a local interaction picture (with some additional assumptions), while our quantum physicist just "reads off" the expected correlations from his entangled states in his formalism.
 
  • #50
wawenspop said:
When agree to take a Hilbert space product for the two entangled particles H spaces,
then we are assuming entanglement has taken place, otherwise we would have no
justification to do that. Then we get correct (as of present time) predications
to use in our experiments.

If you ask why one needs to use the product hilbert space H1 x H2, then there's an easy answer: the superposition principle. Because all |h1> |h2> states are possible states (that's like in classical mechanics), then, by the superposition principle, non-product superpositions of these product states must also be physical states of the system. Hence the tensor product.
 
  • #51
So are we saying
1) That there needs (for entanglement to end - this thread) to be no mechanism involved, it happens.
2) We can never know the mechanism even if there is one (our brains are not correctly positioned to understand)
3) There is a mechanism which in the future we will probably find.
5) Its all solved, no need to discuss further.
4) Something else not in this list.
 
  • #52
wawenspop said:
So are we saying
1) That there needs (for entanglement to end - this thread) to be no mechanism involved, it happens.
2) We can never know the mechanism even if there is one (our brains are not correctly positioned to understand)
3) There is a mechanism which in the future we will probably find.
5) Its all solved, no need to discuss further.
4) Something else not in this list.

Yes :wink:
 
  • #53
Thanks for the thoughtful replies. Just a few more points of clarification.

vanesch said:
If a classical physicist were looking at the experimental preparation, he'd see nothing else but "things that are set up to interact".
Maybe, maybe not. If the essence of quantum entanglement is the formal nonseparability corresponding to the statistical dependence produced by mutual interaction or common influence (and ultimately the filtering/measuring of the separated disturbances via a common global parameter), then (wrt to a simple Bell optical setup anyway) the cross-corrolation can also be understood in terms of analogy to a classical polariscopic setup.

The point is that the physical referent of the formal nonseparability is ultimately the statistical dependence that's produced via the experimental design.

vanesch said:
... two systems that are entangled have no "individual identity" anymore in their quantum-mechanical description.
Yes, but only if you're describing the simultaneous behavior of both systems wrt a global parameter. Otherwise, they still have an individual identity. It's just that the cross-correlation can't be understood without reference to the global parameter. This is the same state of affairs whether we're talking about it in terms of the qm formalism, or FLT or instantaneous influences between spacelike separated events, or the polariscope analogy.

vanesch said:
But again, that's a sheer property of the quantum-mechanical description.
For reasons I've stated, I'm thinking that maybe the essence of entanglement is not solely a property of the qm description. It depends on how one looks at it. As you say:

vanesch said:
... classical action-at-a-distance can mimic perfectly the quantum-mechanical entanglement (or, quantum-mechanical entanglement can mimic perfectly action-at-a-distance ; depends on your PoV).
So, the essence of this thing for which we have interchangeable formal descriptions is not one description or the other, but rather something or things that they have in common.

In any case, I will continue to refrain from using the term "entangled data".

Regarding my observation that your stance on this was possibly in conflict with your adherence to the MWI you wrote:

vanesch said:
I try to keep a distinction between what is "hard fact" and what are interpretational pictures. MWI is a way of giving a picture to the quantum-mechanical happening, which "explains" then of course entanglement and all that - but it's only that: a picture. It's not a hard fact.
I don't get any picture at all from the MWI approach. :smile:

vanesch said:
It is true that, through the quantum formalism, entangled states give rise to weird correlations which cannot always be explained by classical interaction, locality and some other reasonable assumptions (re Bell's theorem and all that).
The correlations are weird only if associated with the qm formalism or FTL or instantaneous propagations of some sort. When viewed via the polariscope analogy they are what one would expect for two identical waveforms being simultaneously analyzed by two identical filters. The correlation will vary as you vary the difference in the settings of the filters in a way that mimics the Malus Law results of polariscopic setups.

It's just that no value can be assigned to what's being filtered prior to a detection associated with some specific filter setting. This amounts to giving up the pseudo-objective view of reality that classical physics has allowed us to entertain.

In closing, I had written:
If the physical essence of quantum entanglement is interaction and mutual (common) influence, then in order to produce the correlations that correspond to quantum entanglement per quantum theory it would be necessary to duplicate the experimental conditions. A rose by any other name is still a rose.

To which you replied:
vanesch said:
I don't understand what you say here.
I have taken it that you are saying that the essence of quantum entanglement is the quantum theoretical formalism. I'm saying that maybe the formalism isn't the essence of it. So, even if you give it another name, or attribute different sorts of causes to it, we're still talking about, essentially, the same thing, and that thing is characterized not by the quantum formalism but by experimental designs which entangle two or more quanta and the resulting data which satisfies certain criteria.
 
  • #54
ThomasT said:
… a few more points of clarification.

The correlations are weird only if associated with the qm formalism or FTL or instantaneous propagations of some sort. When viewed via the polariscope analogy they are what one would expect for two identical waveforms being simultaneously analyzed by two identical filters. The correlation will vary as you vary the difference in the settings of the filters in a way that mimics the Malus Law results of polariscopic setups.

The problem here is stating that “When viewed via the polariscope analogy they are what one would expect …”
On what basis do you think there is an expectation that the “polariscope analogy” should produce the results that lead to Malus Law.
Malus Law is not built on an expectation – it is built from observations that can only be described as “weird”.
With the Horizontal polarized light re-measured at 90° to pass 100% of the light but at 0° pass no light and at 45° passing 50% of the light are all reasonable easy to explain expectations.
However results at 22.5° pass 15% f the light instead of 25% or 67.5° passing 85% instead of 75% cannot be said to be “expected”.
The classical assumption that Malus Law accurately defines or predicts what the results will be, is not the same as describing an expectation based on any rational description of why such “weird” results are produced.

Remember Malus Law does not address the behaviors of individual photons but the results of measuring many of them just as does QM Formalism.

SO IMO both Malus Law and EPR Correlations (both following the same Cos2 rule) are weird results defined by observation but not explained by Classical Expectations. And both are better explained by QM Formalism or equivalent interpretations of QM.
 
  • #55
RandallB said:
The problem here is stating that “When viewed via the polariscope analogy they are what one would expect …”
On what basis do you think there is an expectation that the “polariscope analogy” should produce the results that lead to Malus Law.
Malus Law is not built on an expectation – it is built from observations that can only be described as “weird”.

With the Horizontal polarized light re-measured at 90° to pass 100% of the light but at 0° pass no light and at 45° passing 50% of the light are all reasonable easy to explain expectations.
However results at 22.5° pass 15% f the light instead of 25% or 67.5° passing 85% instead of 75% cannot be said to be “expected”.
The classical assumption that Malus Law accurately defines or predicts what the results will be, is not the same as describing an expectation based on any rational description of why such “weird” results are produced.

Remember Malus Law does not address the behaviors of individual photons but the results of measuring many of them just as does QM Formalism.

SO IMO both Malus Law and EPR Correlations (both following the same Cos2 rule) are weird results defined by observation but not explained by Classical Expectations. And both are better explained by QM Formalism or equivalent interpretations of QM.
Thanks for your reply. After posting, I had some second thoughts on what I had written. I agree with the points you make here. What happens is that after doing lots of classical polariscope setups and becoming comfortable with the classical description, then one tends to think of these observations as not weird and that the nature of light isn't still a mystery. But, as you indicated, they are weird, and the quantum experimental phenomena have underlined the fact that the nature of light is still a mystery.

So, my comparison of simple optical Bell setups and results with a polariscope setup and results still doesn't solve the problem -- even if the analogy is correct.

Could it be that there's something wrong with the classical model of polarization viz the failure of local hidden variable models wrt EPR-Bell tests? I think I'll start a new thread on this. Is this topic appropriate for the quantum physics forum?
 
Last edited:
  • #56
The correlation of states between entangled particles? There is no mass involved and no real information transmitted so SR cannot be violated and it is free to travel FTL. But, one may ask the question what is transmitted between the two particles that has no mass and carries no 'real' information (i.e. information that could introduce 'cause'). Looks mighty like nothing to me. Sure nothing can travel FTL. Why not?... (Yikes, what am I saying here!)

But whatever it is that maintains correlations does not depend on separation distancebetween particles, it seems. (realism and locality arguments). So, what is the mecahnism when the two particles are right on top of each other for maintaining correlation? It will probably be the same as when they are distant. There are no 'forces' involved, its more about probabilities.

When the Universe picks its probabilities for the two particles, how exactly does it do it? It will not be using a look up table or atomic distintegrations I assume. But, to be sure, that mechanism does not change with separation distance.
 
  • #57
Randall, after thinking about this some more, I'd like to address some of your comments.

RandallB said:
The problem here is stating that “When viewed via the polariscope analogy they are what one would expect …”
On what basis do you think there is an expectation that the “polariscope analogy” should produce the results that lead to Malus Law.

On the basis of sinusoidal wave models. One would expect the intensity of the wave transmitted by the analyzer in a polariscopic setup to be proportional to the square of the cosine of the angular difference between the transmission axes of the polarizer and the analyzer.

RandallB said:
Malus Law is not built on an expectation ...
I don't know, but I suspect that you're probably right that the original experimental discovery was not preceded by any theoretical prediction of it. But the experimental phenomenon lent itself quite readily to modelling in terms of sinusoidal functions. And, that's how propagating waves (whether light or matter) have continued to be modeled in both classical and quantum physics (using Fourier analysis where necessary for convenience).

RandallB said:
... – it is built from observations that can only be described as “weird”.
I've changed my mind on this. I don't think of the results of polariscopic setups as weird. This is just how one would expect EM waves to behave -- unless you or someone else can tell me what's weird about the standard EM wave model.

RandallB said:
With the Horizontal polarized light re-measured at 90° to pass 100% of the light but at 0° pass no light and at 45° passing 50% of the light are all reasonable easy to explain expectations.
However results at 22.5° pass 15% f the light instead of 25% or 67.5° passing 85% instead of 75% cannot be said to be “expected”.
They can if you're using the standard, classical model for it.

I'll agree that the relationship might have been surprising when first discovered. But during the past 150 years or thereabouts it has become increasingly less so. Now this might be attributed to just becoming familiar with a model that itself might be characterized as weird, but I don't think of it in that way. Viewed in terms of orthogonal plane wave components, the propagating wave is as visualizable as a surface wave from our everyday experience, sort of.

RandallB said:
The classical assumption that Malus Law accurately defines or predicts what the results will be, is not the same as describing an expectation based on any rational description of why such “weird” results are produced.
The classical model looks like a rational description to me.

RandallB said:
Remember Malus Law does not address the behaviors of individual photons but the results of measuring many of them just as does QM Formalism.
Yes, understood. When I use the term individual measurement I'm referring to the average of many trials.

RandallB said:
SO IMO both Malus Law and EPR Correlations (both following the same Cos2 rule) are weird results defined by observation but not explained by Classical Expectations. And both are better explained by QM Formalism or equivalent interpretations of QM.
I'm not saying that we have the option of using either a classical or qm model in the case of simple optical Bell tests, but the results do seem less weird to me (meaning, in part, that I don't have to worry about there really being FTL propagations of some sort) if I take those setups to be analogous to classical polariscopic setups (even though I then have to contend with those who say that Bell's theorem shows that it just can't be that both A and B are analysing the same disturbance simultaneously).

So, I guess we'll have to agree to disagree a little bit here -- unless you can convince me otherwise. My thinking on this remains open to criticism and direction to considerations I might be missing.
 
  • #58
ThomasT said:
I've changed my mind on this. I don't think of the results of polariscopic setups as weird. This is just how one would expect EM waves to behave -- unless you or someone else can tell me what's weird about the standard EM wave model.

They can if you're using the standard, classical model for it.

I'll agree that the relationship might have been surprising when first discovered. But during the past 150 years or thereabouts it has become increasingly less so. Now this might be attributed to just becoming familiar with a model that itself might be characterized as weird, but I don't think of it in that way. Viewed in terms of orthogonal plane wave components, the propagating wave is as visualizable as a surface wave from our everyday experience, sort of.

The classical model looks like a rational description to me.

The Malus Law comes from:
Actual_Amplitude = Initial_Amplitude CosB - classically reasonable assumption!

But intensity (related to number of particles observed)

Intensity = Amplitude squared

So classical AND quantum predicts:

Actual_Intensity = Initial_Intensity cos squared B - Malus AND QM predictions.

So Bell's Inequality is incorrectly assuming cos B instead of cos squared B
and so proves nothing at all! I knew it all the time!
 
  • #59
Epicurus3 said:
So Bell's Inequality is incorrectly assuming cos B instead of cos squared B and so proves nothing at all! I knew it all the time!

:smile: Before you jump to conclusions: Malus applies to light (spin 1 photons). Bell's argument used spin 1/2 particles (electrons), for which the related formula is cos(theta). A version of Bell's argument is easily fashioned for photons (which of course uses the cos^2 version), and the conclusion is the same: no local realistic theory can reproduce the results of QM (which has been experimentally validated in this respect).
 
  • #60
Bell was Irish and Irish physics is bound to be wrong.
 
  • #61
Epicurus3 said:
Bell was Irish and Irish physics is bound to be wrong.

Ah, but Padraig Harrington is Irish and he won 2 major golf championships this year!
 
  • #62
ThomasT said:
So, I guess we'll have to agree to disagree a little bit here
Sorry but I cannot agree to that.
I do not agree your approach as being based on rational modeling that can be considered acceptable science.
You are claiming classical “polariscopic” assumptions as an acceptable “not weird” or “Not Non-Local” solution that is as scientifically complete as QM.

The cos2 shape of your “Model” is based on measurements of light – not the modeling of individual photons. You cannot just apply the cos2 to individual photons, it is not a “classically reasonable assumption”. Planck demonstrated photons do not have variable intensities like light does.

The EPR paradox is based realistically modeling individual photon behaviors not the average result of measured light intensities. How does this “polariscopic” solution realistically model individual photon movements without even using a Einstein "local and realistic hidden variable". Can you describe those movements for anyone photon?

The “polariscopic” solution is simply an ineffective rebuttal against claims made by QM and the Bell proofs.
 
  • #63
Epicurus3 said:
So Bell's Inequality is incorrectly assuming cos B instead of cos squared B and so proves nothing at all! I knew it all the time!

A couple things you do not seem to know:
The shape of a cos and cos2 functions are exactly the same; one is centered on Zero, the other never goes negative, is centered on 0.5 and twice the Hz.
Also the Bell Inequality shape does not assume a cos and cos2 shape. The Bell Inequality is defined as a straight line that Classical or Local Realistic interpretation should not be able to cross.

It is the QM interpretation that uses a cos and cos2 function to violate that line depending on type of experiment being performed. Stern- Gerlach or Polarization.
 
  • #64
RandallB said:
You are claiming classical “polariscopic” assumptions as an acceptable “not weird” or “Not Non-Local” solution that is as scientifically complete as QM.
I'm claiming, first, that for a classical polariscopic setup the classical model of polarization works ok, and that it doesn't present a weird picture. I don't see how the classical model of polarization is weird or strange. If anyone thinks it is, then I'm interested to see why they think so.

I'm also claiming that the classical polariscopic setup provides an acceptable analogy to simple optical Bell setups -- that is, the two setups have several salient features in common.

RandallB said:
The cos2 shape of your “Model” is based on measurements of light – not the modeling of individual photons. You cannot just apply the cos2 to individual photons, it is not a “classically reasonable assumption”.
Photon detections require light emissions/transmissions of some sort, don't they? Given a polariscopic setup where individual photons are being detected, the intensity of the light transmitted by the analyzing polarizer is the number of photon detections per unit of time. The analog of this in a simple optical Bell setup is the number of coincidental photon detections per unit of time.

RandallB said:
How does this “polariscopic” solution realistically model individual photon movements without even using a Einstein "local and realistic hidden variable".
Hasn't quantum theory taught us that we can't effectively model, and predict the outcomes of, individual trials? The polariscope analogy isn't a solution to the hidden variable problem. It just provides a way of looking at Bell tests that seems to indicate that maybe experimental violations of Bell inequalities aren't telling us anything about nonlocality, because if one understands it as a rather more complicated polariscope, then FTL explanatory fictions are obviated.

RandallB said:
Can you describe those movements for anyone photon?
No.

RandallB said:
The “polariscopic” solution is simply an ineffective rebuttal against claims made by QM and the Bell proofs.
The polariscope analogy isn't aimed at rebutting any claims made by qm. In fact, it provides a way of looking at why, after a qualitative result (a photon detection at one end), the transmission axis of the polarizer associated with the detection can be taken as the principle axis of the disturbance incident on the other polarizer.
 
Last edited:
  • #65
Epicurus3 said:
The Malus Law comes from:
Actual_Amplitude = Initial_Amplitude CosB - classically reasonable assumption!

But intensity (related to number of particles observed)

Intensity = Amplitude squared

So classical AND quantum predicts:

Actual_Intensity = Initial_Intensity cos squared B - Malus AND QM predictions.

So Bell's Inequality is incorrectly assuming cos B instead of cos squared B
and so proves nothing at all! I knew it all the time!
I'm not sure what you're saying, but it is true that Bell-type inequalities don't, taken by themselves, prove anything. They're mathematical identities. Tautologies.

However, the physical meaning of the experimental and theoretical violation of suitably derived and applied Bell inequalities is still an open question.
 
  • #66
ThomasT said:
The polariscope analogy isn't aimed at rebutting any claims made by qm. In fact, it provides a way of looking at why, after a qualitative result (a photon detection at one end), the transmission axis of the polarizer associated with the detection can be taken as the principle axis of the disturbance incident on the other polarizer.

We've been through this already. But in as much that this is a very plausible picture when it is *the same photon* that went through the first polarizer (and hence "got its principle axis turned into the polarizer direction" by interaction with that polarizer) it is not a surprise that when it arrives at the second polarizer, we find a relationship as given by Malus' law which depends on the difference of the axes of the first polarizer (now integrated into the photon itself after interaction) and the second polarizer (next interaction with the modified photon), I don't see how this can be an evident picture for two separate photons - even though they might start out with the same "principle axis" in the source. In what way will the twisting of the photon axis of the first photon by the first polarizer twist and turn the photon axis of the second one which is far away, so that it gets aligned with the orientation of the first polarizer, before it meets its own (second) polarizer ?
 
  • #67
ThomasT said:
Hasn't quantum theory taught us that we can't effectively model, and predict the outcomes of, individual trials? The polariscope analogy isn't a solution to the hidden variable problem. It just provides a way of looking at Bell tests that seems to indicate that maybe experimental violations of Bell inequalities aren't telling us anything about nonlocality, because if one understands it as a rather more complicated polariscope, then FTL explanatory fictions are obviated.
Well; yah – duh.
That is the whole point!
What your saying here is that your polariscope analogy is a “non-local & unrealistic“ classical interpretation that cannot describe movements for individual photons. I would call that a Classically Modified Copenhagen principle.
That is no less Weird than QM!
And since it does not, IMO, provide any usefully formalism to predicatively apply to physical sciences like chemistry and materials to help produce practical applications of new chemicals, semiconductors, etc. – I would say it not even as complete as QM claims to be.

You cannot hang your hat on an assertion like the polariscope analogy “seems to indicate that maybe” …
Just what are you claiming it does indicate for sure! And how is it not weird.

That you do not see what you have described as weird and non-local only means you have yet to grasp the full meaning behind what “Einstein Local” means.
I recommend that you and Epicurus3 take some time to ruminate on what “Local” means before continuing this pointless argument. Honestly if you cannot grasp the full meaning of Local you are not going to understand EPR; it will just be too advanced for you at this time.

Beyond that, I don’t think I can be of any more help for you on this; – good luck.
 
  • #68
RandallB said:
That you do not see what you have described as weird and non-local only means you have yet to grasp the full meaning behind what “Einstein Local” means.
I recommend that you and Epicurus3 take some time to ruminate on what “Local” means before continuing this pointless argument. Honestly if you cannot grasp the full meaning of Local you are not going to understand EPR; it will just be too advanced for you at this time.

Randall - Bells Theorem is a joke devised after a few Guinesses in a bar by an Irishman. It is ridiculously convoluted and has so many holes in it. "The number of particles which have A but not B plus the number which have B but not C is greater than or equal to the number which have A but not C." It is a clever joke!

You want to prove local variables cannot be true...? He fooled you all!

Of course, this post will be deleted! (because the truth is unbearable)

EDIT (vanesch): I won't delete this post, but it is not the kind of post that is constructive.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #69
Epicurus3 said:
Of course, this post will be deleted! (because the truth is unbearable)
No it won't. And we'll try very hard not to lose sleep after your devastating coup de grace. :-p
 
  • #70
DaveC426913 said:
No it won't. And we'll try very hard not to lose sleep after your devastating coup de grace. :-p

If you understand superposition - as Bell did - then his Theroem follows from that with a bit of Sudoku level statistics.

The correlation between the states of two entangled particles is random for both particles as is clear from the wave equation. (not that they have secret states that only 'appear' when observed)

Bell realized that this statement (or similar, - better worded than mine) would not make a career for him, so he devised his joke intelligence test after a couple of beers and managed to make a career out of it. One of the guys in the same bar gave him the idea.

I have seen Bell interviewed - it was clear he had nothing more to contribute to physics than his little superposition side bar - and actually had a thin understanding of physics generally.

<flames on>
So let's hear no more about the subtley of Bell's Theorem PLEASE. Try AOP and pattern programming if you like convolution. Bell's is NOTHING MUCH, and follows from superposition directly.
<flames off>
 
Back
Top