A Pi Question: Why do we use the awkward approximation 22/7 ?

In summary, the approximation 22/7 is commonly used for the mathematical constant pi (π) due to its simplicity and relatively close value to the actual figure of approximately 3.14159. While 22/7 is not exact, it provides a convenient way to perform calculations involving pi, especially in educational contexts. The fraction dates back to ancient civilizations and remains popular for its ease of use, although more precise approximations exist.
  • #71
Nik_2213 said:
I'm told hexagonal wheels work okay given exactly the right profile of 'washboard' surface.
And, if I may butt-in, in some less mathematically advanced parts of the world, they have only gotten this far...
1723747843342.jpeg

(from https://www.startupselfie.net/wp-content/uploads/2023/04/Square-Wheeled-Bicycle-The-Q.jpg)
 
  • Like
Likes Nik_2213
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #72
Steve4Physics said:
in some less mathematically advanced parts of the world, they have only gotten this far...
But you can see they have eliminated the brakes, since they are not needed. Quite a weight-saving feature! :wink:
 
  • Like
Likes Steve4Physics
  • #73
Agent Smith said:
Nescio, measure the perimeter and divide it by the "width".
How does one measure the width of a square circle? Is it ##2r## or ##2 \sqrt{2} r##?
Agent Smith said:
The closer the ratio approaches ##\pi## the more circular it is. Archimedes & Zu Chongzhi used polygons to compute ##\pi##. A circle is an infinite-sided polygon?
There is no such thing as a polygon with infinitely many sides.

One might use a limiting process to define the shape converged to by a sequence of polygons with increasing numbers of sides. But the limit converged upon by a sequence of polygons is not necessarily a polygon.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes symbolipoint
  • #74
Agent Smith said:
measure the perimeter and divide it by the "width"
Do you mean width or diameter? As I've already pointed out in response to @jbriggs444 (who gave a link with a definition of "width"), they're not the same.
 
  • Haha
Likes Agent Smith
  • #75
interestingly (to me), there is no explicit requirement in the following wikipedia article on polygons that the number of sides be finite, (although it appears to be taken for granted), and in fact I could find nothing stated in the article that is not true for a (closed) figure with an infinite number of straight sides. Note e.g. that they do not seem to say that every edge has two vertices as endpoints, nor that every end point of an edge is also the common endpoint of another edge. they do use the language of consecutive edges, but do not seem to require that every edge have two (or even one) adjacent edges.
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Polygon
 
  • #76
PeterDonis said:
Do you mean width or diameter? As I've already pointed out in response to @jbriggs444 (who gave a link with a definition of "width"), they're not the same.
The width of a circle is its diameter??? 🤔
 
  • #77
Agent Smith said:
The width of a circle is its diameter??? 🤔
That tells us the width of a figure that is a circle.

What about a figure that is not a circle? Since that is the sort of figure we are discussing.
 
  • #78
jbriggs444 said:
That tells us the width of a figure that is a circle.

What about a figure that is not a circle? Since that is the sort of figure we are discussing.
Nescio, what were Archimedes and Zu Chongzhi doing, approximating a cricle's circumference with polygons? 🤔

jbriggs444 said:
limiting process
Cogito, that's it!

##\displaystyle \lim_{\text{sides} \to \infty} \text{Regular Polygon} = \text{Circle}##
How does that square with ##\displaystyle \lim_{n \to \infty} \left(1 + \frac{1}{n}\right)^n = e##
 
  • Sad
Likes weirdoguy
  • #79
Agent Smith said:
Nescio, what were Archimedes and Zu Chongzhi doing, approximating a cricle's circumference with polygons? 🤔
That is not responsive to a question about defining the "width" of a figure that is not a circle.
Agent Smith said:
##\displaystyle \lim_{\text{sides} \to \infty} \text{Regular Polygon} = \text{Circle}##
How does that square with ##\displaystyle \lim_{n \to \infty} \left(1 + \frac{1}{n}\right)^n = e##
Where is your definition for the limit of a sequence of shapes? You can't use a definition without stating it or referencing it first.

If you had both limit definitions in hand, you might then be able to draw parallels between them.

But regardless, that leaves us no closer to defining the "width" of a figure that is not a circle. I have a definition in mind. But I want to see you put forth a bit of effort here and state yours.
 
  • #80
Agent Smith said:
Nescio, measure the perimeter and divide it by the "width". The closer the ratio approaches ##\pi## the more circular it is. Archimedes & Zu Chongzhi used polygons to compute ##\pi##. A circle is an infinite-sided polygon?
Polygons do not have a unique width. How do you quantify the resemblance of a hexagon to a circle?
 
  • #81
IIRC, before 'series' derivations, the polygon route to Pi was based on 'regular' shape. Akin to the way, perhaps, that a slightly wonky wheel would wear down to 'even'...

FWIW, wasn't there a delightful 'Golden Age' SciFi tale, where an alien culture's religious taboo on full circles --So wheels, pulleys etc etc-- was up-ended thus ?
Visitor introduced three-arced Reuleaux triangle rollers, to the utter consternation of clergy...
Wicked 'malicious compliance'...
 
  • #82
A.T. said:
How do you quantify the resemblance of a hexagon to a circle?
It depends on whether the hexagon is inscribed in the circle or circumscribed around the circle. At least, that's how it worked in Archimedes' method for putting bounds on ##\pi## by considering the perimeter of inscribed and circumscribed polygons with increasing numbers of sides. The "diameter" in all cases was the diameter of the circle; but the relationship of that to the perimeter of the polygon was different for the inscribed vs. circumscribed polygon.
 
  • #83
PeterDonis said:
It depends on whether the hexagon is inscribed in the circle or circumscribed around the circle.
That's just two of infinitely many possibilities for the width of a hexagon.
 
  • #84
A.T. said:
That's just two of infinitely many possibilities for the width of a hexagon.
Yes, but those two are the ones that are most relevant to comparing it to a circle.
 
  • #85
PeterDonis said:
Yes, but those two are the ones that are most relevant to comparing it to a circle.
Why? Why not the mean of the two or something else in between them?
 
  • #86
A.T. said:
Why?
Because they are the two natural relationships between a circle and a regular polygon--inscribing and circumscribing.
 
  • #87
PeterDonis said:
Because they are the two natural relationships between a circle and a regular polygon--inscribing and circumscribing.
I can come up with such "natural relationships" all day: Circle cuts regular polygon sides in 3 equal parts feels natural to me.

But even if, for the sake of the argument, we stick to inscribing or circumscribing, it's still not clear which of the two should be used to quantify the resemblance of a polygon to a circle.
 
  • #88
A.T. said:
even if, for the sake of the argument, we stick to inscribing or circumscribing, it's still not clear which of the two should be used to quantify the resemblance of a polygon to a circle.
That's right; there is no unique way of doing it. We can appeal to the "naturalness" argument I gave (which, as you note, is not rigorous) to reduce the number of choices to two, but no further.
 
  • #89
jbriggs444 said:
How does one measure the width of a square circle? Is it ##2r## or ##2 \sqrt{2} r##?

There is no such thing as a polygon with infinitely many sides.

One might use a limiting process to define the shape converged to by a sequence of polygons with increasing numbers of sides. But the limit converged upon by a sequence of polygons is not necessarily a polygon.
Burago, Burago , Ivanov , in its book " Metric Geometry" describes sequences of Metric Spaces (Including Polygonal ones) and convergence properties. I lost track of my copy, unfortunately.
 
  • #90
A.T. said:
Polygons do not have a unique width. How do you quantify the resemblance of a hexagon to a circle?
Insofar as Archimedes' and Zu Chongzhi's ##\pi## approximation is concerned, we're computing the perimeter of the circumscribing and inscribing regular polygons. The greater the number of sides, the better the perimeter(polygon) approximates circumference(circle). Also, whatever might be the choice for the width of the polygon, it too approximates the diameter of the circumscribed/inscribed circle. In the end as the number of sides goes to infinity, we have the circle's circumference and its diameter and ##c/d = \pi##.
 
  • #91
This is my favorite* geometric calculation of pi.
Troll Maths presents Pi equals 4! - Imgur.png
*favorite does not mean correct
 
  • Like
  • Haha
Likes SammyS, Agent Smith and jbriggs444
  • #92
Frabjous said:
This is my favorite* geometric calculation of pi.
View attachment 350043
*favorite does not mean correct
I did a quick google search and it seems this "proof" is erroneous, but I still haven't figured out where the analogy between the staircase and the curve breaks down. The best way to understand the problem with this "proof" is that some of the points on the staircase are not on the curve This issue is not there when we approximate the curve with a polygon (all the points are on the curve), the way Archimedes and Zu Chongzhi did.
 
  • #93
Agent Smith said:
I did a quick google search and it seems this "proof" is erroneous, but I still haven't figured out where the analogy between the staircase and the curve breaks down. The best way to understand the problem with this "proof" is that some of the points on the staircase are not on the curve This issue is not there when we approximate the curve with a polygon (all the points are on the curve), the way Archimedes and Zu Chongzhi did.
Notice that this curve breaks your perimeter/diameter for circle quality construction.
 
Last edited:
  • #94
Agent Smith said:
I did a quick google search and it seems this "proof" is erroneous, but I still haven't figured out where the analogy between the staircase and the curve breaks down. The best way to understand the problem with this "proof" is that some of the points on the staircase are not on the curve.
Of course the proof is erroneous. We know that going in.

The issue is not that the some of the points on the staircase are not on the curve. Almost none of the points in the circumscribed/inscribed polygons are on the curve either.

One way of compactly stating the issue is that the limit of the perimeters is not equal to the perimeter of the limit. There is no principle of mathematics by which they should be equal. The two ideas do not "commute".
 
  • Like
Likes gmax137 and PeterDonis
  • #95
Frabjous said:
Notice that this curve breaks your perimeter/diameter for circle quality construction.
Oh, that's right, visually that is, but I did stress that the critical ratio has to approximate ##\pi##.

@jbriggs444 , the "perimeter of the limit"?

jbriggs444 said:
Almost none of the points in the circumscribed/inscribed polygons are on the curve either.
The points that matter to the approximation are on the curve (the points get closer and closer as the number of sides increase).

In the case of the staircase, some of the points always stand outside of the curve/line being approximated.
 
Last edited:
  • #96
Agent Smith said:
@jbriggs444 , the "perimeter of the limit"?
Think about a sequence of stair-step approximations to a circle with more and more sides that are each tinier and tinier. That sequence of stairstep shapes approaches a limiting shape. The limiting shape is the circle, of course.

The "perimeter of the limit" would be the perimeter of the limiting shape, aka the perimeter of the circle, ##\pi d##.

Each of the stairstap shapes will have more and more of the tinier and tinier sides. Each shape will have a perimiter. Each will have the same perimeter as it turns out. ##4d## for all of them.

The "limit of the perimeters" would be the limit of the infinite sequence of perimeters. That limit is obviously ##4d##
Agent Smith said:
The points that matter to the approximation are on the curve (the points get closer and closer as the number of sides increase).
Please stop using fuzzy language. Phrases like "matter to the approximation" are meaningless. The points on a stairstep also get closer and closer as the number of sides increase.
Agent Smith said:
In the case of the staircase, some of the points always stand outside of the curve/line being approximated.
In the case of a polygon circumscribing a circle, some of the points always stand outside of the circle about which they are circumscribed.
 
  • Like
Likes Vanadium 50
  • #97
Agent Smith said:
In the case of the staircase, some of the points always stand outside of the curve/line being approximated.
And some of them always stand inside the curve being approximated.
 
  • Like
Likes Agent Smith
  • #98
jbriggs444 said:
Please stop using fuzzy language. Phrases like "matter to the approximation" are meaningless. The points on a stairstep also get closer and closer as the number of sides increase.
Well, what's the explanation for the error then? ##\pi \ne 4, \pi = 3.14159...##. It can only mean that the curve we're assuming is an approximation of the actual curve (the circle, etc.) isn't what we assume/think it is. We're overmeasuring or overcounting. We could investigate where the extra ##0.8584073464102067615373566167205...## is coming from. I'm sure that would be easy for you, being a science person. Can you take a look into that.
 
  • #99
jbriggs444 said:
That sequence of stairstep shapes approaches a limiting shape. The limiting shape is the circle, of course.
I'm not sure this is actually true. For a polygon that is inscribed in the circle or circumscribed around the circle, the angle between the sides approaches 180 degrees as the number of sides increases without bound. In other words, the polygon approaches being a smooth curve, with no angles at all (each "angle" of 180 degrees is just a tangent line to the circle at the "angle" point).

In the case of the stairstep shapes, however, the angle between the sides is constant at 90 degrees; it does not approach being a smooth curve as the number of stairsteps increases without bound. So I do not think the limit of the stairsteps can be a smooth curve. I think the limit might not be well-defined at all.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes jbriggs444
  • #100
Agent Smith said:
Well, what's the explanation for the error then?
See my post #99 just now. If the limit of the stairsteps is not well-defined, then the limit of the perimeter is not well defined either.
 
  • Like
Likes Agent Smith
  • #101
PeterDonis said:
And some of them always stand inside the curve being approximated.
Yes, but as the NumberOfSides(Polygon) increases, all the points are on the curve/circle. This is not true for the staircase. There are 2 sets of points with a staircase, giving us 2 lines, one connects the top edges of the stairs and the other connects the bottom corners of the stairs. Both sets can't be on the same line/curve, producing the error ##\pi = 4##.
 
  • #102
Agent Smith said:
as the NumberOfSides(Polygon) increases, all the points are on the curve/circle.
Only in the limit. At each finite step, the corners of the polygon are not on the circle.

Agent Smith said:
There are 2 sets of points with a staircase, giving us 2 lines, one connects the top edges of the stairs and the other connects the bottom corners of the stairs. Both sets can't be on the same line/curve
For each finite step, this is true. But that doesn't mean it has to also be true in the limit; there is no general rule about limits that entails it.

The correct procedure is to first ask if the limit of the stairsteps is well-defined at all. If it isn't, which is what I argued for in post #99, then it is meaningless to assert any properties of the limit, since there is no well-defined limit for any such properties to apply to.
 
  • Like
  • Skeptical
Likes jbriggs444 and Agent Smith
  • #103
PeterDonis said:
See my post #99 just now. If the limit of the stairsteps is not well-defined, then the limit of the perimeter is not well defined either.
Got it!
 
  • #104
PeterDonis said:
Only in the limit. At each finite step, the corners of the polygon are not on the circle.


For each finite step, this is true. But that doesn't mean it has to also be true in the limit; there is no general rule about limits that entails it.

The correct procedure is to first ask if the limit of the stairsteps is well-defined at all. If it isn't, which is what I argued for in post #99, then it is meaningless to assert any properties of the limit, since there is no well-defined limit for any such properties to apply to.
I should've been clearer. The inscribed polygon's vertices are on the curve being approximated. Archimedes used 2 polygons (circumscribing one and the inscribed one). I have to do the math but my hunch is the inscribed polygon's perimeter more closely approximates the circle's circumference, the outer polygon having the same issue as the staircase approximation. As the number of sides of the polygon increases, the inscribed polygon basically becomes the circle.
 
  • #105
Agent Smith said:
the outer polygon having the same issue as the staircase approximation
No, it doesn't. I made the difference clear in post #99.

Agent Smith said:
As the number of sides of the polygon increases, the inscribed polygon basically becomes the circle.
This is also true of the circumscribed polygon, as I showed in post #99.
 

Similar threads

Replies
4
Views
3K
Replies
25
Views
3K
Replies
14
Views
2K
2
Replies
42
Views
10K
Replies
1
Views
1K
2
Replies
42
Views
7K
Back
Top