A stronger proof of nonlocality, or what?

In summary, a paper published in Nature Physics presents a proof of nonlocality that is stronger than Bell nonlocality. The experiment and theorem show that at least one of three commonly held assumptions about reality must be false: that events really happen when observed, that free choices are possible, and that choices made in one place cannot instantly affect a distant event. The minimal statistical interpretation would deny the first assumption, stating that everyday language statements do not accurately represent the results in the paper. Additionally, the parody conversation discusses the concept of reversibility and how it relates to reality in both classical and quantum physics.
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
Demystifier said:
1) P. Holland, The Quantum Theory of Motion, Chapter 8.
Okay regardless of whether that is a full equivalence proof it does give what I need to answer the question.

This new inequality rules out nonlocal theories where the particles can interact nonlocally but always possesses well defined values for observable quantities such as momentum and spin. In Bohmian Mechanics spin is a contextual result of the interaction of the device with the particle, not a property inherent to the particle.

So we might say the current result proves that particles do not intrinsically possesses most of the properties we measure them to have. Up until now this would have been "interpretational", now it is a proven fact.
 
  • #38
Kolmo said:
Okay regardless of whether that is a full equivalence proof it does give what I need to answer the question.

This new inequality rules out nonlocal theories where the particles can interact nonlocally but always possesses well defined values for observable quantities such as momentum and spin. In Bohmian Mechanics spin is a contextual result of the interaction of the device with the particle, not a property inherent to the particle.

So we might say the current result proves that particles do not intrinsically possesses most of the properties we measure them to have. Up until now this would have been "interpretational", now it is a proven fact.
I don't think that's correct. In Bohmian mechanics, a particle always has both position and momentum. But momentum is not always distributed according to the Born rule, the Born rule for momentum is contextual. Similarly, in the Holland's book you will find Bohmian models in which a particle always has a well defined spin in all 3 directions, but again those values are not always distributed according to the Born rule.

You might revise your statement by saying that we now have a proof that the Born rule is contextual for most observables, but I think we already knew that from older theorems.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #39
Demystifier said:
I don't think that's correct. In Bohmian mechanics, a particle always has both position and momentum
Sorry I meant our observed values are not those of the actual particle, i.e. observed spin and momentum are an emergent property of the particle-device set up, we're not just reading off the actual particle momentum for example.

Demystifier said:
You might revise your statement by saying that we now have a proof that the Born rule is contextual
It's not quite the same as Kochen-Specker contextuality so I wouldn't use that phrase. Also the paper is just looking at correlation-topes, it's not specific to QM so the Born rule as a QM specific thing is not as such a characterization of it.
 
  • Like
Likes physika
  • #40
Let me try to say it another way. This basically rules out theories were there is a nonlocal interaction between the particles but the device readouts are either directly reading out the properties of the particles or contextual to the device local to the particle.

In essence even nonlocal interactions between the particles combined with contextual values of the measurement results gives a bound which quantum theory violates. You need the values measured in each location to be contextual to both devices.

This is not the same Kochen Specker contextuality which is local and doesn't directly discuss the Born rule since it's about regions in correlation space in general, not about specific features of quantum mechanics.
 
  • Like
Likes physika and Demystifier
  • #41
Demystifier said:
I don't think that's correct. In Bohmian mechanics, a particle always has both position and momentum.
No. It has both position and velocity. There is a trajectory ##q(t)\in Q## and so there is also a velocity ##v(t)= \dot{q}(t)\in Q##. Momentum is contextual - the result of a momentum measurement depends on the position of the measurement device too, thus, is not a property of the particle. There is, in particular, no trajectory ##p(t)##. One should be careful to distinguish momentum p and ##mv##.
 
  • #42
Sunil said:
No. It has both position and velocity. There is a trajectory ##q(t)\in Q## and so there is also a velocity ##v(t)= \dot{q}(t)\in Q##. Momentum is contextual - the result of a momentum measurement depends on the position of the measurement device too, thus, is not a property of the particle. There is, in particular, no trajectory ##p(t)##. One should be careful to distinguish momentum p and ##mv##.
In the sense in which momentum is contextual, in that sense the velocity ##v\equiv m^{-1}p## is also contextual. And by the way, even the measured position, that is the position of the macroscopic pointer of the apparatus, may differ from the Bohmian position of the measured microscopic particle; the authors who discovered it called it surreal Bohmian trajectories. So in that sense even position can be considered contextual in Bohmian mechanics.
 
  • #43
Demystifier said:
In the sense in which momentum is contextual, in that sense the velocity ##v\equiv m^{-1}p## is also contextual.
No. Because conceptually there is no such equivalence. Momentum is defined in dependence of the Lagrangian, ##p_i = \frac{\delta S}{\delta \dot{q}}##. A Lagrangian depends on the context, it is contextual (in this sense) already in classical physics.
And, again, there is a Bohmian trajectory ##q(t)## and correspondingly ##\dot{q}(t)## but no such trajectory ## p(t)##.

Demystifier said:
And by the way, even the measured position, that is the position of the macroscopic pointer of the apparatus, may differ from the Bohmian position of the measured microscopic particle; the authors who discovered it called it surreal Bohmian trajectories. So in that sense even position can be considered contextual in Bohmian mechanics.
First, the measured position is irrelevant, the trajectory ##q(t)## is the real position.

Then, "surreal Bohmian trajectories" are nothing but a subjective feeling of some people who expect the trajectories to look like classical trajectories. They simply failed to develop the correct Bohmian intuitions. That's also quite irrelevant.

The correct intuitions about Bohmian trajectories are not that strange. First, they look much less strange if considered only as average trajectories. In stable energy eigenstates there is, in the average, no motion. The classical motion is circular. The average velocity is zero, which is natural. That it should be exactly zero looks slightly strange. Then, let's look at superpositional states. There, the trajectory will be as if the position would have been measured. And that will be a quite classical trajectory. Only if in one part you make a measurement of something different from position, then even the far away other particle will do some surrealistic things too. If that measurement will be a measurement in the sense of the results made macroscopic or not does not matter.
 
  • #44
I've just had a discussion with two authors (Wiseman and Cavalcanti) of the paper. They explained me that violation of their "local friendliness" would imply that the purely instrumental interpretation a'la "Quantum theory needs no interpretation" https://pubs.aip.org/physicstoday/article/53/3/70/411209/Quantum-Theory-Needs-No-Interpretation is wrong. In other words, the experiment could in principle rule out the interpretation that most practical physicists, including @vanhees71, seem to take for granted. But pure instrumentalists don't need to bother yet, because actual realization of such experiments, involving fine manipulations of quantum properties of the measuring apparatus, would be terribly difficult.
 
  • #45
Which paper are you talking about? The Physics today article by Fuchs and Peres tells it all: All you need is the minimal interpretation. If you find an experiment which clearly and reproducibly contradicts the (probabilistic) prediction of QT, then QT is wrong and has to be substituted by a better theory, but not before that happens.

Whether or not QT or another "better" theory satisfies the one or other philosophical prejudice about how Nature must be because of some "ism" is not part of science.
 
  • #46
vanhees71 said:
Which paper are you talking about?
The one referred to in the first post of this thread. It discusses a thought experiment of the Wigner-friend type, which manipulates the quantum state of the measuring apparatus and concludes that, if quantum mechanics is applicable to the measuring apparatus as to any other quantum object, then the minimal purely instrumental interpretation of QM is wrong. But the actual experiment has not been performed(*), and probably will not be in a near future, so a pure instrumentalist, like you, does not need to worry.

(*) An experiment has been performed in which a true measuring apparatus is replaced with a single qubit, obviously because a single qubit is much easier to manipulate in a way needed for the experiment.
 
Last edited:
  • #47
vanhees71 said:
Whether or not QT or another "better" theory satisfies the one or other philosophical prejudice about how Nature must be because of some "ism" is not part of science.
How about minimal-ism and instrumental-ism, are they philosophical prejudices too? :wink:
Remarkably, the thought experiment is supposed to rule out precisely those ism's.
 
  • #48
@Demystifier why are you so sure of the outcome of the future experiment? May be it will not rule out but confirm the instrumentalist point of view?
 
  • #49
martinbn said:
@Demystifier why are you so sure of the outcome of the future experiment? May be it will not rule out but confirm the instrumentalist point of view?
Sure, it's also a possibility. In fact, this result would be much more interesting.
 
  • #50
vanhees71 said:
If you find an experiment which clearly and reproducibly contradicts the (probabilistic) prediction of QT, then QT is wrong and has to be substituted by a better theory, but not before that happens.
The experiment by itself would not say what a better theory is, but it would tell us that at least one of the 3 common sense assumptions in post #1 must be wrong.
 
  • #51
Demystifier said:
An experiment has been performed in which a true measuring apparatus is replaced with a single qubit, obviously because a single qubit is much easier to manipulate in a way needed for the experiment.
And just as obviously, makes the experiment irrelevant to the question such experiments are supposed to address, since you can't make a measuring apparatus out of a single qubit.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and gentzen
  • #52
Demystifier said:
because actual realization of such experiments, involving fine manipulations of quantum properties of the measuring apparatus, would be terribly difficult.
If the difficulty is due to the requirements of information processing capacity, and at some point it simply exceeds what we have at hand, would we still call it just a difficulty, or would be call it not possible in principle?

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #53
Fra said:
If the difficulty is due to the requirements of information processing capacity, and at some point it simply exceeds what we have at hand, would we still call it just a difficulty, or would be call it not possible in principle?
To say what is possible or impossible in principle, one must first specify - the principle. The principle is a theoretical concept, not an experimental one. The formulation of a principle may be guided by experiments, but it becomes a principle only when we give it a theoretical formulation, either as an axiom of a given theory, or something derived from more fundamental axioms. But our theories, and hence the principles, change and evolve as our knowledge develops. For example, consider the 2nd law of thermodynamics. According to the thermodynamic theory (as formulated before the Boltzmann's statistical mechanics), it is impossible in principle to violate the 2nd law. But according to statistical mechanics, it's possible in principle, but very difficult in practice.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen, vanhees71 and WernerQH
  • #54
Demystifier said:
To say what is possible or impossible in principle, one must first specify - the principle. The principle is a theoretical concept, not an experimental one. The formulation of a principle may be guided by experiments, but it becomes a principle only when we give it a theoretical formulation, either as an axiom of a given theory, or something derived from more fundamental axioms. But our theories, and hence the principles, change and evolve as our knowledge develops. For example, consider the 2nd law of thermodynamics. According to the thermodynamic theory (as formulated before the Boltzmann's statistical mechanics), it is impossible in principle to violate the 2nd law. But according to statistical mechanics, it's possible in principle, but very difficult in practice.
Yes, the principle I had in mind was what I take implicit to the whole standard paradigm of QM: That inferences are made from experiments in the form of statistics of preparation procedures and detections. Somehow, I think it seems fair to say that it's how it's done, regardless of "interpretations"? Modulo observer equivalence transformations, all observers must be able to agree on the statistics, which is why some says it's on the "classical side".

For example, an experiment with a measurement device that isn't as reliable as "classical record" isn't just difficult, I think it doesn't qualify as a measurement, and thus invalid to use in the QM paradigm?

I agree this is a big problem. But I don't think the problem can be analyzed within QM itself, as it entertains for good reasons "measurements" that should make sense, but are somehow generalisations of the more constrained "quantum measurements", so we can't handle them as per the QM paradigm.

The question then was, is it possible in principle to infer the mentioned problems of QM itself, using its own "inference system" and experimental protocol (without bending the presumed rules)?

/Fredrik
 
  • #55
Fra said:
But I don't think the problem can be analyzed within QM itself, as it entertains for good reasons "measurements" that should make sense, but are somehow generalisations of the more constrained "quantum measurements", so we can't handle them as per the QM paradigm.
Fra said:
The question then was, is it possible in principle to infer the mentioned problems of QM itself, using its own "inference system" and experimental protocol (without bending the presumed rules)?
Is the first quote your answer to your question in the second quote?
 
  • #56
Demystifier said:
Is the first quote your answer to your question in the second quote?
Yes. Its my strong hunch. I havent contempled ny proofs though.

/Fredrik
 
  • #57
This was highlighted earlier in the thread...
Demystifier said:
  1. When someone observes an event happening, it really happened.
To me this is essentially what it means for an observer to be in the "classical world" - where "real" is define as whatever the consensus is among observers, via equivalence transformations.

Without this, I agree as hinted by others that QM paradigm makes no sense, as QM is built on this solid ground.

If we widen our views however, I would of course expect the QM to break down at some point anyway, so this assumption is pretty much the first I would do away with from an agent-centered stance. After all, as I mentioned before, there is a difference between the principle of "no preferred observer", (which seems easy to accept as anybodys views is as right asn anyones elses) and the much stronger "all observers are equivalent". The former does not exclude disagreements, and there is thus perhaps no solid ground? And therefore QM may have limited validity only to the extent that the classical backround IS stable enough, and the more general framework to describe this in, is still missing. This is what I meant with that, in the paradigm of QM, I think (1) must hold. IF we relax it, we leave the QM paradigm?

/Fredrik
 
  • #58
Fra said:
To me this is essentially what it means for an observer to be in the "classical world" - where "real" is define as whatever the consensus is among observers, via equivalence transformations.
I think that reality has nothing to do with classicality. For instance, dreams and hallucinations, which are not real, are equally classical.
 
  • Like
Likes physika and vanhees71
  • #59
Demystifier said:
I think that reality has nothing to do with classicality. For instance, dreams and hallucinations, which are not real, are equally classical.
Reality of position is related to classicality. But in a non-classical theory why should position be real? Or more generaly why should there be an observable with a classical analog/limit which is real?
 
  • #60
martinbn said:
Reality of position is related to classicality. But in a non-classical theory why should position be real? Or more generaly why should there be an observable with a classical analog/limit which is real?
I believe I answered such questions in my "Bohmian mechanics for instrumentalists".
 
  • #61
Demystifier said:
I believe I answered such questions in my "Bohmian mechanics for instrumentalists".
Yes, but my impression is that you argue that there has to be something real that is classical like position. Then you cannot say that reality and classicality have nothing to do with each other.
 
  • #62
Demystifier said:
I think that reality has nothing to do with classicality. For instance, dreams and hallucinations, which are not real, are equally classical.
It seems we get into discussions on definition of real. Then what does " classical mean"? classical mechanics?

Id say my dreams are real experiences realized by the physics of my brain, but they often violate classical mechanics. So in what sense are dreams classical?

/Fredrik
 
  • #63
Trying to calibrate terms...
Demystifier said:
in my "Bohmian mechanics for instrumentalists".
Do you take the "non-perceptible" items that are "thinking tools" and provides explanatory value within a theoey as what is real?

/Fredrik
 
  • #64
martinbn said:
Yes, but my impression is that you argue that there has to be something real that is classical like position. Then you cannot say that reality and classicality have nothing to do with each other.
Impression is the key word.
 
  • #65
Fra said:
Do you take the "non-perceptible" items that are "thinking tools" and provides explanatory value within a theoey
Yes.
Fra said:
as what is real?
Not necessarily.
 
  • #66
Fra said:
It seems we get into discussions on definition of real. Then what does " classical mean"? classical mechanics?

Id say my dreams are real experiences realized by the physics of my brain, but they often violate classical mechanics. So in what sense are dreams classical?
By classical I mean not quantum. To explain dreams in terms of physical processes in the brain, one does not need quantum physics.
 
  • #67
Are your solipsist HV "classical", but "not real" by that terminology?

And not observable(in QM terminology)?

/Fredrik
 
Last edited:
  • #68
Demystifier said:
The one referred to in the first post of this thread. It discusses a thought experiment of the Wigner-friend type, which manipulates the quantum state of the measuring apparatus and concludes that, if quantum mechanics is applicable to the measuring apparatus as to any other quantum object, then the minimal purely instrumental interpretation of QM is wrong. But the actual experiment has not been performed(*), and probably will not be in a near future, so a pure instrumentalist, like you, does not need to worry.

(*) An experiment has been performed in which a true measuring apparatus is replaced with a single qubit, obviously because a single qubit is much easier to manipulate in a way needed for the experiment.

The implication in bold is too strong for a takedown of instrumentalism, as instrumentalists can readily describe a measurement apparatus quantum mechanically. A better statement would be something like: If measurement data are not sufficiently classical, then the purely instrumental interpretation of QM is wrong.

I.e. We can reject the notion that there are superobservers, but still be fine with describing the measurement apparatus quantum mechanically. QM descriptions don't entail superobservers, and it's the superobservers that would cause an issue for instrumentalists.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and Demystifier
  • #69
Fra said:
Are your solipsist HV "classical", but "not real" by that terminology?
Just the opposite, it is quantum and real, in the same sense in which particle trajectories in Bohmian interpretation are quantum and real.

Fra said:
And not observable(in QM terminology)?
It's not an observable, in the sense that it is not described by an operator in the (rigged) Hilbert space, if that's what you meant.
 
  • #70
Demystifier said:
Just the opposite, it is quantum and real, in the same sense in which particle trajectories in Bohmian interpretation are quantum and real.
Are you thus conceptually "ok" with considering something "real" that different observers fail to agree upon, because its "solipsistic" in nature?

/Fredrik
 
Back
Top