- #36
- 24,488
- 15,033
Again, there's no necessity of the collapse postulate at all. It describes a very special preparation process, usually idealized, known as a "von Neumann filter measurement". You don't need the collapse posulate at all to make physics sense of quantum theory. You only need Born's Rule to define the meaning of states (represented by statistical operators). Copenhagen in Bohr's flavor is pretty close to the minimal interpretation. If you say "Copenhagen interpretation", it's never clear what's meant since there are as many sub-interpretations as believers in this "religion" ;-)).atyy said:I mean QM. Ballentine rejects the collapse postulate, as does vanhees71 (see his post #23). In part, this is because Ballentine misunderstands Copenhagen, as bhbobba says. QM without the collapse postulate is wrong, possibly unless one uses many-worlds or Bohmian mechanics or consistent histories, but there is no sign that Ballentine or vanhees71 use any of these other interpretations.
I also don't need many worlds, Bohm etc. Why should I need these? I stick to physics, letting philosophy to the philosophers. Unobservable parallel universes and "trajectories" which are hard (if not impossible) to measure, are irrelevant for physics. For me the whole machinery of QT with the standard postulates are just descriptions of measurements. The "ontology" is purely operational, i.e., defined by hands-on real-world measurement/observation devices in the experimentalists setup. There's not less "ontology" in QT than in classical physics, where you have as abstract mathematical constructs like symplectic manifolds, pseudo-Riemannian space-time manifolds and the like. Nature couldn't care less about these abstract descriptions of our observations!
This fits a bit to Bohr's above quoted dictum, but I'd add that QT describes what we observe in Nature (at least up to now; who knows, whether there's some observation in the future contradicting it).