How can the Cauchy integral and Fourier integral produce the same result?

  • Thread starter nrqed
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Qft
In summary, the conversation discusses questions about causality and measurements in quantum field theory (QFT). The concept of causality in QFT is different from classical physics and involves considering the possibility of particles propagating over spacelike intervals. The connection between QFT and non-relativistic quantum mechanics (NRQM) is also discussed, with a question about the classical limit of QED. The issue of causality in QFT is further explored, with a suggestion that allowing for negative energies in the propagator may restore locality. However, the overall understanding of these concepts in QFT remains unclear and there is a lack of clear explanations in literature.
  • #246
strangerep said:
X corresponds to the position observable. Exp(X) transformations correspond
to translations in momentum space, and this does indeed have certain
difficulties of its own (so I read).

That's what I am having problems with. For Poincare group generators H, P, J, K, the corresponding finite transformations Exp(H), Exp(P), Exp(J), Exp(K) have a well-defined and easily observable physical meaning as transformations of inertial reference frames. On the other hand, momentum-space translations Exp(X) are rather abstract things. That's why I don't feel like treating X on the same footing as other generators.



strangerep said:
But I guess it's a subjective judgement whether something is/isn't "artificial".

Here I should agree with you. Relativistic quantum theory is so weird. It seems that no matter which approach we take, we face artificial or counterintuitive things of one kind or another. Most often, these things cannot be directly measured. So, which of them are less "artificial" remains largely a matter of taste. Apparently, we have different tastes for these things. I don't think it's bad.

Eugene.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #247
meopemuk said:
This leakage can be used to transmit information superluminally. However, I am not convinced that these facts can be used to build a machine that sends signals back to the past. If the possibility of such a machine can be proved, then we are in a deep trouble.

Hi meopemuk,

I haven't followed the thread for the last few days. But what struck me was your statement above about signals being sent back to the past. I feel I have to object to this.

First, I think, the term "past" is defined by the backward lightcone and not just by some event that has t<0 in some frame. I guess the region outside the lightcone is commonly called present (even if t<0 in some frame).

Second, even if it was possible to "send signals back to the past" (the backward lightcone), this would not be interpreted by the observer as such. Think of the advanced propagator in classical ED: what we would see in such a case was a spherical wave that runs towards a specific spacetime point, and when it reaches it, it vanishes and creates a delta-source (the reverse of what the retarded propagator does: create a delta source in connection with an outgoing spherical wave). So I guess the term "sending signals back to the past" is a bit misleading because it implies that the past can be changed, which it can't. Rather signals seemingly sent to the past correspond to very unlikely course of events (in some sense similar to the broken roof tile that heals magically and flies back to the roof...).

Do you agree with that ?
 
  • #248
OOO said:
So I guess the term "sending signals back to the past" is a bit misleading because it implies that the past can be changed, which it can't.

I agree with you here. I think it is impossible to send signals back to the past even if it is quite possible to have particle wavefunctions that propagate superluminally or action-at-a-distance interactions. You can find in the literature designs of "time machines" that are based on superluminal signals. These "time machines" should supposedly allow you to make terrible things, like killing your grandfather before you were born, etc.
I think that these designs involve subtle flaws that wouldn't allow them to work as intended.

Eugene.
 
  • #249
meopemuk said:
X corresponds to the position observable. Exp(X) transformations correspond
to translations in momentum space, and this does indeed have certain
difficulties of its own (so I read).
That's what I am having problems with. For Poincare group generators H, P, J, K, the
corresponding finite transformations Exp(H), Exp(P), Exp(J), Exp(K) have a well-defined
and easily observable physical meaning as transformations of inertial reference frames.
On the other hand, momentum-space translations Exp(X) are rather abstract things.
That's why I don't feel like treating X on the same footing as other generators.

If we write [itex]R[/itex] (the N-W position operator) as (for example):

[tex]R = -c^2H^{-1}K - \frac{i \hbar c^2 P}{2H^2} - \frac{cP \times W}{MH(Mc^2 + H)}
[/tex]

then one could also ask what exp[itex](R)[/itex] means. Since it satisfies (at least formally)
the Heisenberg CRs, I think you'd reach an identical conclusion that [itex]R[/itex] generates
translations in momentum space.

The important thing is the basic (linear) Lie algebra of quantities corresponding to observable
properties of physical systems. Then the task is to go further and construct a 4D
infinite-dimensional interacting quantum theory rigorously from the algebra, which of
course no one has done.
 
  • #250
strangerep said:
If we write [itex]R[/itex] (the N-W position operator) as (for example):

[tex]R = -c^2H^{-1}K - \frac{i \hbar c^2 P}{2H^2} - \frac{cP \times W}{MH(Mc^2 + H)}
[/tex]

then one could also ask what exp[itex](R)[/itex] means. Since it satisfies (at least formally)
the Heisenberg CRs, I think you'd reach an identical conclusion that [itex]R[/itex] generates
translations in momentum space.


Yes, it is true that [itex]\exp (R)[/itex] performs translations in momentum space. But it is important to realize that there is no inertial transformations of reference frames, which correspond to such a translation. (Boost transformations come close, but their action on definite momentum states is more complicated than simple translation) So, [itex]\exp (R)[/itex] is not a representative of any Poincare group element. This is the reason why R does not belong to the Poincare Lie algebra and should be constructed as a (rather complicated) function of proper Lie algebra elements that you correctly reproduced.

Eugene.
 
  • #251
strangerep said:
The important thing is the basic (linear) Lie algebra of quantities corresponding to observable
properties of physical systems.

I don't think we should require that all operators of observables must belong to the Lie algebra. Some of them can be expressed as Hermitian functions of Lie algebra elements. The simplest example is the operator of rest mass

[tex] M = \frac{1}{c^2}\sqrt{H^2 - c^2 \mathbf{P}^2} [/tex]

Other examples are operators of velocity, spin, and position.

Eugene
 
  • #252
meopemuk said:
I don't think we should require that all operators of observables must belong to the Lie algebra. Some of them can be expressed as Hermitian functions of Lie algebra elements. [...]
Oops. When I said "the important thing is the basic (linear) Lie algebra of quantities ...",
I meant the things (e.g., unitary irreps) that one uses as basic building blocks to construct
one's QFT. If one thus starts from the unitary irreps of the Poincare group, it's no surprise
that things outside the whole Poincare group (like R itself) turn out to be ill-behaved.

That is, the important thing when constructing a field theory is the basic Lie algebra of observables,
not merely the group of inertial transformations. That's why I tried to use only the phrase
"H-P algebra", not "H-P group". But I suspect we're returning to subjective assessments of
what "important" means, so I'll stop here.
 
Last edited:
  • #253
OOO said:
First, I think, the term "past" is defined by the backward lightcone and not just by some event that has t<0 in some frame. I guess the region outside the lightcone is commonly called present (even if t<0 in some frame)

The pole prescripted propagator which causes all the problems does
propagate backwards in time and does so not only for anti-particles
but for any all day live particle except for the infinite plane wave.

It's the result of requiring that the propagator instead of the wave
function
contains only positive energy frequencies, For me this
is a sign of confusion. One can find the source of such a confusion
in the older texts discussing Green's function relation.

[tex]-(\Box+m^2)D(x-y)\ =\ \delta(x-y)[/tex]

One sees that [itex]\delta(x-y)[/itex] is interpreted as the point-particle and
[itex]D(x-y)[/itex] is regarded as the subsequent wave function. Now, this is all
without consequences if one just sets [itex]i\epsilon=0[/itex] in practical calculations
and this is just what's done most of the time. It would be interesting
to look at the arguments used in the exception cases though.Regards, Hans
 
Last edited:
  • #254
Hans de Vries said:
The pole prescripted propagator which causes all the problems does
propagate backwards in time and does so not only for anti-particles
but for any all day live particle except for the infinite plane wave.

Hans, as you say, the epsilon-propagator D is non-zero outside the lightcone and non-zero in the backward lightcone. I think we agree on it being non-zero outside the lightcone seems to cause some trouble with causality at first glance, but this is resolved by the way D is used in QFT, right ?

Now I propose that the non-vanishing amplitude of the propagator in the backward lightcone is a totally different story. In my opinion this does neither present any problems for causality (there is nothing peculiar about signals coming from the past), nor is it connected to the amplitude outside the lightcone.

The reasoning for the latter is simple: if I am able to find a propagator that vanishes for the past and out of the lightcone (which is what you have done with the Heaviside function), I am also able to find another propagator that vanishes for the future and out of the lightcone (it's the advanced propagator). I just have to flip the "sign of time" for that. But then I can simply average the retarded and advanced propagators to get another one that vanishes outside the lightcone but neither for the future nor the past. Adding further homogeneous solutions gives me the most general propagator which does not vanish anywhere.

So what I have just shown is that the amplitude outside the lightcone has nothing to do with the amplitude in the backward lightcone.
 
  • #255
OOO said:
Hans, as you say, the epsilon-propagator D is non-zero outside the lightcone and non-zero in the backward lightcone.

It also is non-zero at t<0 outside the lightcone, so the propagation would
not only be instantaneous (not zero at t=0 outside the light cone). It also
would propagate to the past outside the lightcone.

Filtering out the negative energy frequencies involves a convolution in
time with f(t)=1/t. Meaning that the propagator is smeared out over the
t-axis.

The inside of the future light-cone is smeared out in the -t and +t
directions. In the vertical direction in the figure below:

[tex]\mbox{light cone:}\quad \begin{array}{c}\bigtriangledown \\ \bigtriangleup \end{array}[/tex]

Going down it gets outside the lightcone and further down into negative t.Regards, Hans

PS. Filtering out negative frequencies = Multiplication with the Heaviside
step function over the E-axis in momentum space = Convolution with the
Fourier transform of the step function over the t-axis in position space.

PPS. For the transform of step-function, see entry 310 in the table here:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Fourier_transform#Distributions
 
Last edited:
  • #256
Hans de Vries said:
It also is non-zero at t<0 outside the lightcone, so the propagation would
not only be instantaneous (not zero at t=0 outside the light cone). It also
would propagate to the past outside the lightcone.

I wouldn't call the region outside the lightcone with t<0 the "past" since this would not be a covariant definition. Just change the frame and what was the past would become the future and vice-versa. That doesn't make sense, at least semantically (whereas, of course, I have no doubt about the appropriateness of Minkowski space).

The only covariant definition of the term "past" is that it is represented by the backward lightcone.
 
Last edited:
  • #257
OOO said:
I wouldn't call the region outside the lightcone with t<0 the "past"
The only covariant definition of the term "past" is that it is represented by the backward lightcone.

Granted. :smile:

Regards, Hans

PS. However, a succession of two such propagation steps can get
you in the past light cone, propagating information from the current
to the past, if normal propagation to the past isn't bad enough...
 
Last edited:
  • #258
OOO said:
The reasoning for the latter is simple: if I am able to find a propagator that vanishes for the past and out of the lightcone (which is what you have done with the Heaviside function), I am also able to find another propagator that vanishes for the future and out of the lightcone (it's the advanced propagator). I just have to flip the "sign of time" for that. But then I can simply average the retarded and advanced propagators to get another one that vanishes outside the lightcone but neither for the future nor the past. Adding further homogeneous solutions gives me the most general propagator which does not vanish anywhere.

So what I have just shown is that the amplitude outside the lightcone has nothing to do with the amplitude in the backward lightcone.

By choosing to integrate in the positive time direction one does
indeed "sneak in" causality. Physically integrating backwards in
time by itself already violates time ordering causality. So, I don't
believe in propagators which are non-zero for t<0.

Zee doesn't either on page 109, in II.2 where he calls "an electron
going backward in time": Poetic but confusing metaphorical language..


Regards, Hans.
 
  • #259
Hans de Vries said:
Now, this is all
without consequences if one just sets [itex]i\epsilon=0[/itex] in practical calculations
and this is just what's done most of the time. It would be interesting
to look at the arguments used in the exception cases though.Regards, Hans

I think, this is exactly the right question to ask. Does it matter somewhere, when calculating Feynman diagrams (which is always done for practical (experimental) purposes, as far as I know, in momentum space) if I take the +i*epsilon or -i*epsilon or maybe even a ++ or -- epsilon prescription? If not, doing the Fourier transform to real space, should be regarded just as a mathematical exercise, and textbooks should put in a warning to not take this result seriously because of its ambiguity.
 
  • #260
Micha said:
I think, this is exactly the right question to ask. Does it matter somewhere, when calculating Feynman diagrams (which is always done for practical (experimental) purposes, as far as I know, in momentum space) if I take the +i*epsilon or -i*epsilon or maybe even a ++ or -- epsilon prescription?

Yes, it matters. Changing the sign of epsilon changes how one does the Wick rotation to euclidean space, and this in turn changes the sign of every one-loop diagram. Among other things, this would mean that in quantum electrodynamics we would have charge antiscreening rather than screening, and hence a negative beta function. Cool, but wrong.
 
  • #261
Avodyne said:
Yes, it matters. Changing the sign of epsilon changes how one does the Wick rotation to euclidean space, and this in turn changes the sign of every one-loop diagram. Among other things, this would mean that in quantum electrodynamics we would have charge antiscreening rather than screening, and hence a negative beta function. Cool, but wrong.

Ok, sorry. I should have taken a more careful look at Zees book. Here the +i*epsilon comes from the fact, that you want a factor -epsilon*phi^2 in the exponent of the path integral to let it go to zero for large phi.
 
  • #262
Hans de Vries said:
Granted. :smile:

Regards, Hans

PS. However, a succession of two such propagation steps can get
you in the past light cone, propagating information from the current
to the past, if normal propagation to the past isn't bad enough...

Yes, I agree with this completely. But vice-versa, you won't be able to combine two propagation steps inside the lightcone to get out of the lightcone. That's what I wanted to emphasize. So [nonzero; out of the lightcone] means trouble with causality, but [nonzero; inside the past lightcone] does not.
 
  • #263
Hans de Vries said:
By choosing to integrate in the positive time direction one does
indeed "sneak in" causality. Physically integrating backwards in
time by itself already violates time ordering causality. So, I don't
believe in propagators which are non-zero for t<0.

I don't understand your reasoning. Isn't it quite natural to think of a present event (at 0,0) as being caused by something in the infinite past and causing something else in the infinite future. In my opinion that's what a time-symmetric propagator could be trying to tell us.

Hans de Vries said:
Zee doesn't either on page 109, in II.2 where he calls "an electron
going backward in time": Poetic but confusing metaphorical language.

This reference to authority stands a bit isolated among your criticism of Zee and other textbook authors... :smile:
 
Last edited:
  • #264
OOO said:
I don't understand your reasoning. Isn't it quite natural to think of a present event (at 0,0) as being caused by something in the infinite past and causing something else in the infinite future. In my opinion that's what a time-symmetric propagator could be trying to tell us.

But the Green's function is defined as the response of a field on a
perturbation at (0,0). Of course, a point in the past would contribute
the same to (0,0) as (0,0) would contribute to that point mirrored
into the future light cone, but the Green's function is defined with
the cause at (0,0), while the inverse Green's function is used to track
back the source of the field.

OOO said:
This reference to authority stands a bit isolated among your criticism of Zee and other textbook authors... :smile:
OK :smile: But I only pointed to Zee's skeptical remarks about Feynman's
original ideas of electrons going back in time, to show that I'm not
alone in my reservations. The "reference to authority" wasn't intended
towards you, since you were not claiming that anyway if I understood
you correctly.

I don't think I'm criticizing Zee, I'm only discussing a piece of sideline math
which comes to us from the early days of QED copied from one textbook
to another.Regards, Hans.
 
Last edited:
  • #265
Hans de Vries said:
But the Green's function is defined as the response of a field on a
perturbation at (0,0). Of course, a point in the past would contribute
the same to (0,0) as (0,0) would contribute to that point mirrored
into the future light cone, but the Green's function is defined with
the cause at (0,0), while the inverse Green's function is used to track
back the source of the field. .

Yes, if that's the definition. I admit that I often mentally switch back to classical electrodynamics where the propagators are obviously defined that way. What we are doing in ED is one of two cases:

1) Move the charge on a predefined trajectory (which amounts to imposing a constraint on it) and calculate the fields that are generated from this movement. The retarded Lienard-Wiechert potentials give us in some sense the "minimal" fields (neither initial nor past fields are non-zero). Of course this must be artificial because there must have been some fields which caused the charge to move like it did in the first place.

2) Apply some fields and calculate the movement of the charge due to Lorentz force.

The combination of both is not possible in classical ED because the energy momentum conservation proves to be incomplete, ie. there is no energy-momentum tensor for the matter field.

Now this is different in QED, where the matter field is included in the Lagrangian and thus in the energy-momentum tensor. So what I was thinking of is that singling out a retarded propagator out of the infinitely many ones is not necessary any more since we have left the realm of moving charges by constraints.

Therefore I conjecture that our insisting on the retarded propagator as the "real" propagator is a reverb of this "moving charges by hand" business. In this sense I also conjecture that a time symmetric propagator is an expression of the fact that an incoming spherical wave causes charge movement and this again causes an outgoing wave, so in sum we are describing a scattering process. On the other hand if we used a retarded propagator only, then causality is violated because the cause of the electron (or charged pion in case of KG) movement is missing from the description.

Hans de Vries said:
OK :smile: But I only pointed to Zee's skeptical remarks about Feynman's
original ideas of electrons going back in time, to show that I'm not
alone in my reservations. The "reference to authority" wasn't intended
towards you, since you were not claiming that anyway if I understood
you correctly.

You did. I also felt a lot better if the books could clearly explain why they do things the way they do. But there seem to be slightly too many excuses around there, or probably things are just too complicated to be explained to such drooling idiots like us. And so we have to keep on thinking and sometimes change our minds about things. I still can't say I'm sure about causality in QFT...
 
  • #266
Let me sum up the state of our discussion:

1. The Feynman propagator does leak out of the light cone.
2. The Feynman propagator is not just another of an infinite number of Greensfunctions. It IS the amplitude for a particle moving from one space-time point to another.
In Zee, chapter I.8. (14), the Feynman propagator is derived from canonical field theory as an integral over space. You can make this a 4 dimensional integral and get in a unique way the +i*epsilon prescription.

This leaves the question open, how the propagator goes together with causality. I think, we have in this thread rediscovered, that we need antiparticles to restore causality, because clearly, with particles only we are stuck at this point.
Indeed I found a statement in this link:
http://aesop.phys.utk.edu/qft/2004-5/2-5.pdf

"Again, causality is due to non-trivial interference between positive-energy
modes (particles) propagating in one direction (x -> y) and negative-energy
modes (anti-particles) propagating in the opposite direction (y -> x)."

I didn't follow the math so far, but I tend to believe, it is true.
Two observations fit nicely:

1. The leaking out of the lightcone get bigger for lighter particles. Cleary for lighter particles, it is easier to create particle-antiparticle pairs
2. The photon propagator does not show any leaking out of the lightcone. This must be, because the photon is its own antiparticle.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #267
I further read in http://aesop.phys.utk.edu/qft/2004-5/ , and I am still convinced, that it can give us the answer to our question about causality.
Notice, that the Feynman propagator is defined as the time ordered product of the two field operators at the two space-time points. Thus we cut the propagator into two pieces, the positive time propagator gives the propagation of the particle only, whereas the negative time propagator gives the propagation of the antiparticle. Clearly this is, what you need in Feynman diagrams, because you work with particle/antiparticle eigenstates.
You can also see this from the fact, that eg. for t>0 only the positive energy pole is contributing.
But for the propagation of a real particle, we have to consider both particle and antiparticle propagation.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #268
Micha said:
Let me sum up the state of our discussion:

Good idea. I haven't been following the discussion anymore, but I'm interested in any conclusions you may end with.

Have you yet come to agreement about how precisely is the propagation amplitude related to the spatial probability densities? As I noted in my question, it at least is not related by the same equation

[tex]
\Psi(t,y) = \int d^3x\; K(t-t_0, y,x) \Psi(t_0,x)
[/tex]

(where K is the propagation amplitude) as it is in the non-relativistic QM.

It is so easy to say "amplitude to propagate", but it doesn't mean anything without clear meaning in terms of spatial probability density.
 
  • #269
Micha said:
1. The Feynman propagator does leak out of the light cone.
Depends what you precisely mean by "leak". The standard Feynman propagator
is indeed non-zero outside the light-cone. That's a mathematical fact, as derived
(for example) in Scharf's "Finite Quantum Electrodynamics" pp64-69. See in
particular eq(2.3.36) and the discussion on the following page 69.

The photon propagator does not show any leaking out of the lightcone.
This must be, because the photon is its own antiparticle.
Actually, it's because the photon is massless. Looking at the equation I mentioned
in Scharf, i.e., eq(2.3.36), all the terms which are non-zero for spacelike separations
are multiplied by the mass. Hence they vanish for a massless particle.

This leaves the question open, how the propagator goes together with causality.
As I tried to explain before, the problem is that a naive Hilbert space whose basis
vectors correspond to ordinary 4D Minkowski space is not a physically-meaningful
Hilbert space. I'll run through the construction again...

Start with a 4-dimensional vector space, denoting an arbitrary vector is denoted as |k>.
That is, it's a 4-momentum vector space, but it is not yet a Hilbert space, nor does it
correspond to a relativistic particle type. It doesn't even have an inner product yet, so
expressions like <k|k'> do not yet have any meaning.

To turn this k-space into a Hilbert space for a relativistic particle of mass m, we restrict
a subspace of those vectors which satisfy [itex]k^2 = m^2[/itex], and also satisfy [itex]E > 0[/itex],
where [tex]E := \sqrt{m^2 + {\underline{p}}^2}[/tex], and [itex]\underline{ p}[/itex] denotes 3-momentum.
That is, we restrict to only those |k> vectors on the mass hyperboloid corresponding to mass=m.

Any vector in the restricted space (the mass hyperboloid) can thus be written
[tex]
|\underline{p}> ~=~ \Theta(E) ~\delta^{(4)}(m^2 - E^2 + {\underline{p}}^2) |k>
[/tex]
where [itex]\Theta(E)[/itex] is a step function restricting to +ve energy.

With these restrictions, the subspace consisting only of these [itex]|\underline{p}>[/itex]
vectors can be made into a Hilbert space by defining an inner product of the form:
[tex]
<\underline{p} | \underline{p'}> ~=~ \delta^{(3)}(\underline{p} - \underline{p'})
[/tex]
(Depending one's conventions, there might also be a factor involving [itex]E[/itex] on
the RHS, but that's not important here.) Note also that these [itex]|\underline{p}>[/itex]
vectors do not span the original |k> vector space in any sense.

Now let's think about trying to change to a position basis. That's easy for the original
|k> space:
[tex]
|x> ~:= \int d^4k ~ e^{ikx} ~ |k>
[/tex]
This gives 4D Minkowski vector space. Unfortunately, it's useless as a Hilbert space,
because it's not the same space as our physical Hilbert space above consisting of [itex]|\underline{p}>[/itex] vectors.
To get position-like vectors in the physical Hilbert space, we must do something
like the following instead:

[tex]
|X> ~:= \int d^4k ~ e^{ikX} ~ \Theta(E) ~\delta^{(4)}(m^2 - E^2 + {\underline{p}}^2) ~ |k>
[/tex]
where here I've used capital "X" so we can remember that it's different from the
previous unphysical [itex]|x>[/itex] vectors. The above is equivalent to:

[tex]
|X> ~\sim~ F_x[\Theta(E)] ~*~ F_x[\delta^{(4)}(m^2 - E^2 + {\underline{p}}^2)] ~*~ |x>
[/tex]

where [itex]F_x[f(k)][/itex] denotes the (inverse) 4D Fourier transform of [itex]f(k)[/itex],
and "[itex]*[/itex]" denotes (4D) convolution in x-space.

Summary: the physically-meaningful position basis vectors are the |X>, and not the |x>.
Each |X> is a complicated convolution of the |x> vectors with all the forward lightcones
in x-space. From an x-space viewpoint, the |X>'s do indeed seem non-local, but that doesn't
matter because "non-locality in x space" means "non-locality in physically irrelevant x-space".
Only the |X> vectors have physical meaning. Indeed, Hilbert space inner products are only
defined between |X>-type vectors.

That's why it also doesn't matter that the Feynman propagator is non-zero outside the
lightcones in x-space. Our Hilbert space is restricted to relativistically correct states
on the mass hyperboloid, and it doesn't matter how things look in x-space. Only X-space
matters, but we almost never use the latter in calculations. Rather we mostly use the
[itex]|\underline{p}>[/itex] 3-momentum Hilbert space (hyperboloid for mass=m).[Hmm... Maybe the Newton-Wigner construction has some merit after all. :-)]
 
Last edited:
  • #270
Good post, strangerep.

To repeat this in my own words, in ordinary QM, if we find a particle at x0, we would assign to it a wavefunction |x0> = delta(x-x0). Now, in QFT, delta(x-x0) is not a vector in Hilbert space and we are forced to choose |X0>. (Actually choosing a delta function is already an idealization in ordinary QM and we would choose a very narrow wavepackage.)
This means we are simply not able to produce a fully localized single particle state in QFT.
Honestly, I do not have an idea yet, how these |X> states look like.
 
  • #271
Your approach is quite different to how they look at causality in http://aesop.phys.utk.edu/qft/2004-5/ .

It is interesting though, that the negative energy solutions (or suppressing them) play an important role in your approach as well.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #272
strangerep said:
Actually, it's because the photon is massless. Looking at the equation I mentioned
in Scharf, i.e., eq(2.3.36), all the terms which are non-zero for spacelike separations
are multiplied by the mass. Hence they vanish for a massless particle.

I am sure, you have your math correct.

I was trying to make sense of the following statement:

"Again, causality is due to non-trivial interference between positive-energy
modes (particles) propagating in one direction (x -> y) and negative-energy
modes (anti-particles) propagating in the opposite direction (y -> x)."

Looking at this again I must say I am confused. While photons are their own antiparticles, neutral scalar particles are as well.
 
  • #273
Micha,

OK, the UTK web document you quoted is essentially a course version
that combines material covered in Peskin & Schroeder, ch2, with some
extra stuff.

In particular, UTK's eq(1.4.6) is the equal-time (ie special) case of D(x-y):

[tex]
D(x-y) = \frac{m}{4\pi^2\sqrt{-(x-y)^2}} ~ K_1(m \sqrt{-(x-y)^2})
[/tex]

This equal-time expression, involving the [itex]K_1[/itex] Bessel
function, is a special case of the more general expression I mentioned
in Scharf. But even in UTK's expression, you can see immediately that
it is 0 if m=0.

Regarding the specific quote you mentioned:

Again, causality is due to non-trivial interference between
positive-energy modes (particles) propagating in one direction (x -> y)
and negative-energy modes (anti-particles) propagating in the opposite
direction (y -> x).

The discussion surrounding this in the UTK document is a bit brief.
P&S give more (on pp 28-29).

My personal opinion is that the word "due" in the quote "causality is
due to non-trivial interference..." should be regarded as an
interpretation. In their approach, I would have said "causality is
recovered by appealing to non-trivial interference...".

To understand this, I'll summarize the standard (canonical)
approach to QFT (which is basically what UTK and P&S follow):

1) Start with a classical Lagrangian function over phase space.
Ensure it is a relativistic scalar. That is, ensure the Lagrangian
is compatible with (classical) special relativity.

2) "Quantize" it, which means "construct a mapping from functions
over phase space to operators on a Hilbert space". This is
non-trivial, but most textbooks do it very quickly by saying
"promote the classical field and its conjugate momentum to
operators, and impose canonical commutation relations between them".
Then check that all the relativity transformations that were
applicable on the classical phase space are correctly represented
by operators on the Hilbert space, satisfying the Poincare commutation
relations.

Following this path, one then discovers the puzzle of the Feynman
propagator being non-zero outside the lightcone, in general. However,
this embarassment can be interpreted away by appealing to real-world
measurements. Eg, P&S say on p28: "To really discuss causality,
however, we should ask not whether particles can propagate over
spacelike intervals, but whether a meaurement performed at one point
can affect a measurement at another point whose separation from the
first is spacelike." Then they go on to show that such a relationship
between two measurements doesn't occur. However, they have to broaden
the context of their discussion to complex Klein-Gordon fields and
talk about particles and anti-particles.

My take on all this is that it's no surprise that they can derive
the result of no-effect between measurements at spacelike intervals,
because that's just basic special relativity, which was a crucial
input to the whole theory right from the start.

The difference between the above, and what I described in my
earlier post, is that the above tries to quantize the whole classical
phase space, whereas I restricted it to a mass hyperboloid first.

In one case, we find puzzling issues about the Feynman propagator
being non-zero outside the light cone. In the other, we find really
weird expressions for position states. IMHO, neither of these
approaches is entirely satisfactory (I think it's because of the
way Fourier transforms are used with gay abandon). Hence my earlier
post about the Heisenberg-Poincare group, though the latter is
still a rather speculative research topic.

You also said:

It is interesting though, that the negative energy solutions
(or suppressing them) play an important role in your approach as well.
In both approaches, this is built-in from the start as axioms, in
that both approaches assume positive-energy - which is a
phenomenological expression of the fact that we don't experience
any form of backward time-travel. In my post, I used the
[itex]\Theta(E)[/itex] to express this. In the canonical approach, this
is assumed implicitly in the way the Feynman propagator is chosen
(choosing which way to deform the energy integration contour).

You also asked about my "[itex]|X>[/itex]" states:

This means we are simply not able to produce a fully localized
single particle state in QFT. Honestly, I do not have an idea yet, how
these |X> states look like.
The |X> states look quite horrible, and I don't think they're even
well-defined. For example, the Fourier transform of the
nastily-discontinuous [itex]\Theta(E)[/itex] function is something like:

[tex]
-\frac{1}{it\sqrt{2\pi}} + \sqrt{\frac{\pi}{2}}~\delta(t)
[/tex]

and that's just the start of the nightmares in trying to find an
explicit expression for a general [itex]|X>[/itex].

That's why you hardly ever hear anything about such states in basic
textbooks. They're of no practical help when trying to derive
experimental consequences of QFT such as scattering cross-sections.
Unfortunately, that also encourages people to think that the ordinary
(x,t) of Minkowski are somehow physically meaningful in QFT, and then
they derive various embarrassing theorems (e.g: EPR, Reeh-Schlieder, etc)
which show that something is seriously wrong somewhere. In these situations,
it helps to think about the physically-more-relevant [itex]|X>[/itex] states.
 
  • #274
strangerep,
I agree with your summary of what the link (obviously based on Peskin & Schroeder) has to say about this. I don't possesses P&S, so I would love to hear any further details from anybody. With the following text of your post, especially at the end, I have the feeling that you are slightly leaving the ground of standard QFT. The EPR effect is an established piece of standard QM, not even QFT, right? The Reeh-Schlieder effect (at least what I saw in google) seems to be a weird, but to be mathematically well established theorem of standard QFT.

I read, that in QFT the field is not to be mixed up with the wavefunction, which is a fact, that maybe has not yet been well enough appreciated in this discussion. I also think, from physical grounds, that our discussion about causality should consider, that a totally sharp localized particle in real space is not possible in QFT, because the energy needed to measure with higher and higher precision would lead to the creation of particle/antiparticle pairs, so you wouldn't know, which is the particle, you want to localize. This is why I had some sympathy for your |X> states. But I really would like to keep this discussion within standard QFT.
My take on all this is that it's no surprise that they can derive
the result of no-effect between measurements at spacelike intervals,
because that's just basic special relativity, which was a crucial
input to the whole theory right from the start.
A theory, which is consistent with special relativity right from the beginning, is all, we are asking for, I think.Back to the explanation of P&S:
Their point is, that to check, whether two measurements at different spacetime points can influence each other, you need to go the commutator of the according operators.
The vacuum amplitude for the commutator of two field operators then is nothing else as the difference of the propagators ( D(x-y) - D(y-x) ).
I am almost convinced. But I would like to understand it a little better.
Would sending a signal from A to B always involve a measurement in A? (I can understand, it involves a measurement at B). Also I would like to understand the relation to antiparticles better. Are antipartcles needed to ensure, that the propagator has the following property for spacelike intervals:
D(x-y) = D(y-x) ?
 
Last edited:
  • #275
Micha said:
I read, that in QFT the field is not to be mixed up with the wavefunction, which is a fact, that maybe has not yet been well enough appreciated in this discussion.

This is the reason why I don't like canonical quantization at all. In the path-integral approach it is apparent from the start (at least if you do not extend it to infinite times), that the path-integral is in fact a wavefunctional which depends on final field configurations, much like the wavefunction in nonrelativistic QM depends on final particle positions.
 
  • #276
strangerep said:
The |X> states look quite horrible, and I don't think they're even
well-defined. For example, the Fourier transform of the
nastily-discontinuous [itex]\Theta(E)[/itex] function is something like:

[tex]
-\frac{1}{it\sqrt{2\pi}} + \sqrt{\frac{\pi}{2}}~\delta(t)
[/tex]

Found a simple way to show that the seemingly innocent operation
of "filtering out the negative frequencies" is something which
devastatingly violates Lorentz invariance and leads to those crazy
situations which Eugene is talking about.

"Filtering out the negative frequencies" comes down to:

[tex]\Theta(E)\ f(E,p)\ \ \Rightarrow \ \ \frac{1}{2}~\left( \delta(t) - \frac{i}{\pi t} \right) ~* ~ f(t,x)[/tex]

The latter is a convolution over the vertical t-line (think Minkovski).
Do this on a point particle at rest, which is a vertical line, and the
result is again a point particle at rest. Do this on a moving particle
on the tilted t' line and you get a smeared out line which belongs to
a particle which is not local anymore! The general formula gives:

[tex]\frac{1}{2}~\left( \delta(t) - \frac{i}{\pi t} \right)~ * ~ \delta(t-vx)
\ \ =\ \ \frac{1}{2}~\left( \delta(t-vx) - \frac{i\beta}{\pi(t-vx)} \right)[/tex]

So the smearing out is proportional to the speed. Clearly, what's
below the E=0 line is not necessary below the E=0 line in other
frames. The frequencies which go from - to + all belong to off-
shell propagation corresponding to imaginary mass. Regards, Hans
 
Last edited:
  • #277
Hans de Vries said:
Found a simple way to show that the seemingly innocent operation
of "filtering out the negative frequencies" [...] leads to those crazy situations [...]
Thanks. Doing it for a simple case makes it easier to see that something is seriously weird.

It's not surprising, because [itex]\Theta(E)[/itex] is not a tempered distribution. It causes
trouble near E=0 (infrared divergences) and also at high energy where it stays stubbornly
constant to [itex]\infty[/itex] (ultraviolet divergences). Scharf makes a big deal out of this.
His version of QED (based on Epstein-Glaser) relies in large part on smoothing out the
undesirable discontinuities and divergences (order by order).

Cheers.
 
  • #278
Micha said:
With the following text of your post, especially at the end, I have the feeling that you are slightly leaving the ground of standard QFT. The EPR effect is an established piece of standard QM, not even QFT, right? The Reeh-Schlieder effect (at least what I saw in google) seems to be a weird, but to be mathematically well established theorem of standard QFT.
I was just highlighting the problems., certainly not proposing an alternate theory.

The theorems I mentioned (Reeh-Schlieder in particular) fall under the auspices of
standard axiomatic QFT. This starts by postulating a set of fields over Minkowski space,
and then demands that they carry a causal representation of the Poincare group.
The Reeh-Schlieder theorem says (roughly) that if you have 2 regions of Minkowski spacetime
O1 and O2 which are spacelike separated from each other, it is nevertheless possible to reconstruct
the fields on O1 arbitrarily accurately by cyclic operations of fields in O2 upon the vacuum.
That's a serious embarrassment. In recent years, there have been papers with titles like
Newton-Wigner vs Reeh-Schlieder (or something like that - I forget).

Anyway, I wasn't really departing from standard QFT, but just showing how/where/why
some of the well-known problems occur.

I read, that in QFT the field is not to be mixed up with the wavefunction, [...]
Right, which is why I kept my posting in terms of more abstract Hilbert space states.

I also think, from physical grounds, that our discussion about causality should
consider, that a totally sharp localized particle in real space is not possible in QFT,
because the energy needed to measure with higher and higher precision would lead to the
creation of particle/antiparticle pairs, so you wouldn't know, which is the particle, you
want to localize.
That's a rationalization/interpretation. That sort of thing ought to fall out of the math
rather than being put in by hand mid-calculation. In other words, all such "physical
grounds" ought to be encoded into theory's axioms at the start, after which we just
crank the mathematical handle. If we have to inject "physical grounds" again later,
it just means our initial axioms were inappropriate and should be revised.

This is why I had some sympathy for your |X> states. But I really would like to
keep this discussion within standard QFT.
Those |X> states just express an alternate basis of the physical Hilbert space. Remember
that (in momentum space) we're restricted to a 3D mass hyperboloid, spanned by the
usual |\underline p> states. The |X> states are just an alternate basis for exactly the
same Hilbert space, but don't try and use them for practical calculations. :-)


Back to the explanation of P&S:
Their point is, that to check, whether two measurements at different spacetime points can influence each other, you need to go the commutator of the according operators.
The vacuum amplitude for the commutator of two field operators then is nothing else as the difference of the propagators ( D(x-y) - D(y-x) ).
I am almost convinced. But I would like to understand it a little better.
Would sending a signal from A to B always involve a measurement in A? (I can understand, it involves a measurement at B). Also I would like to understand the relation to antiparticles better. Are antipartcles needed to ensure, that the propagator has the following property for spacelike intervals: D(x-y) = D(y-x) ?
The antiparticle thing is a bit misleading. To follow it closely, one must go back to the
fields that make up the Lagrangian, and carry through the full quantization to multiparticle
Fock space.

But to understand the point above, it's sufficient to know two things: 1) D(x-y) is a Lorentz
invariant; 2) if x,y are spacelike-separated, there exists a continuous Lorentz transformation
that transforms (x-y) into (y-x). (P&S illustrate this with their fig 2.4, but I don't know
how to reproduce that diagram here.)

So, (1) and (2) together imply that D(x-y) = D(y-x) for spacelike-separated x,y. You don't
need to fuss around with measurements, signals or antiparticles. It's simply a consequence
of the relativity maths that D(x-y) = D(y-x), and hence [itex][\phi(x), \phi(y)] = 0.[/itex]
for spacelike x-y

(If you need more than that, with vacuum states and everything, a little more detail and
sophistication are necessary.)
 
  • #279
A technical point:
[tex]\lim_{m\to 0}mK_1(mr)={1\over r}[/tex]
not zero.
 
  • #280
strangerep said:
The theorems I mentioned (Reeh-Schlieder in particular) fall under the auspices of
standard axiomatic QFT. This starts by postulating a set of fields over Minkowski space,
and then demands that they carry a causal representation of the Poincare group.
The Reeh-Schlieder theorem says (roughly) that if you have 2 regions of Minkowski spacetime
O1 and O2 which are spacelike separated from each other, it is nevertheless possible to reconstruct
the fields on O1 arbitrarily accurately by cyclic operations of fields in O2 upon the vacuum.
That's a serious embarrassment. In recent years, there have been papers with titles like
Newton-Wigner vs Reeh-Schlieder (or something like that - I forget).

Anyway, I wasn't really departing from standard QFT, but just showing how/where/why
some of the well-known problems occur.

Ok, thanks. I am seeing a direct connection to our topic now. How can Reeh-Schlieder proove such a theorem, while Peskin & Schroeder is providing a proof for causality? But maybe to start a discussion about this interesting theorem would be too much for this already long thread, at least for now.
strangerep said:
That's a rationalization/interpretation. That sort of thing ought to fall out of the math
rather than being put in by hand mid-calculation. In other words, all such "physical
grounds" ought to be encoded into theory's axioms at the start, after which we just
crank the mathematical handle. If we have to inject "physical grounds" again later,
it just means our initial axioms were inappropriate and should be revised.
I perfectly agree with what you say. It does not mean however, that intution is useless. It is useful as a guide to the right formal theory, if you haven't found it yet, or while you are learning it and even if you know it, intution is helpful as a shortcut to find the right answer without long calculation. Of course always with the danger of being wrong depending on how complicated the topic and how good your intution is.
And not only that, finally you have to connect your math to the real world by comparing it to measurement. So you need to know, what your math means.

strangerep said:
The antiparticle thing is a bit misleading. To follow it closely, one must go back to the
fields that make up the Lagrangian, and carry through the full quantization to multiparticle
Fock space.

But to understand the point above, it's sufficient to know two things: 1) D(x-y) is a Lorentz
invariant; 2) if x,y are spacelike-separated, there exists a continuous Lorentz transformation
that transforms (x-y) into (y-x). (P&S illustrate this with their fig 2.4, but I don't know
how to reproduce that diagram here.)

So, (1) and (2) together imply that D(x-y) = D(y-x) for spacelike-separated x,y. You don't
need to fuss around with measurements, signals or antiparticles. It's simply a consequence
of the relativity maths that D(x-y) = D(y-x), and hence [itex][\phi(x), \phi(y)] = 0.[/itex]
for spacelike x-y

(If you need more than that, with vacuum states and everything, a little more detail and
sophistication are necessary.)
I agree, to show, that [itex][\phi(x), \phi(y)] = 0.[/itex] is true, is only mathematics.
You don't need to talk about antiparticles. (Although it would be nice to understand, why other
people see a connection here.)
But in order to say, that [itex][\phi(x), \phi(y)] = 0.[/itex] means, that causality is preserved, you need to have a concept of causality first, to which you can connect. And the best definition of causality in physics I know, is, that you can not send a signal from A to B with a speed greater than the speed of light.
 
Back
Top