- #106
rubi
Science Advisor
- 847
- 348
The fact that you are unable to make sense of the post shows that you haven't understood it. ##A## in that equation is a random variable on both sides of the equation. I will try one last time to explain the situation:wle said:(In fact, I'm having to guess to make sense of your post because what you're claiming doesn't even look well formed. For example in ##v(A) = A(x)## you have ##A## appearing as both a random variable and as a Hermitian operator.)
First we have the Kochen-Specker theorem:
In ##d>2##, there is no valuation function (satisfying certain assumptions) on a certain subset of quantum observables.
The next theorem is a triviality:
On all random variables on a classical probability space, there exists a valuation function (satisfying said assumptions).
(If you are unable to prove this highly trivial theorem on your own, then see for example http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9803055v4)
Now, if we could represent the quantum observables as random variables on a classical probability space, then the second theorem would imply the existence of a valuation function. This is in contradiction with the KS theorem.
By the way, not even Bohmians have a problem admitting that not all quantum observables are represented as random variables in their theory. You are completely alone with the belief that this can be accomplished.
No, this is also common knowledge. See for example the nice book that bhobba always quotes: https://www.amazon.com/dp/0387493859/?tag=pfamazon01-20I think you're making this up as you go along.
In order to get a probability space, you must restrict the event algebra of quantum mechanics (an orthomodular lattice) to a sublattice of commuting events. Otherwise the integral you have written down doesn't even make sense, because you don't even have an integration measure (the probabiliy functional on the full event algebra is not a measure). If you believe that you can define this integral using the probability functional on the quantum event algebra, then either explain how to do it or point me to a reference. If you cannot do this, then you should be very careful making such non-sensical statements.
I agree, there is a counterexample in 2 dimensions. However, that doesn't invalidate the theorem, which holds for any dimension > 2. I have done my homework and studied all these things for many years. Even my own research is concerned with causality in quantum gravity. The fact that you don't even know what a random variable is clearly shows that you have no expertise in this subject. Random variables are the most basic concept of probability theory.Oh please. Earlier in this thread you insisted, loudly and repeatedly, that there can't be a hidden-variable model for spin-1/2 until I pointed out that even the KS theorem doesn't apply to that. That immediately tells me you never invested your own "little bit of time" studying the theorem. If you actually look at a proof of the KS theorem (like the one on its Wikipedia page), it is actually quite easy to see why the kind of counterexample they construct cannot work for qubits.
The measurement problem is the result of having a theory that is in conflict with classical probability theory. All interpretational problems on QM can be traced back to this fact. If QM were a classical probability theory, then the interpretational problems would be solved automatically.No. The most common reasons I've seen for discussing interpretations of quantum physics are the measurement problem (e.g. many-worlds interpretation, Bohmian mechanics, stochastic collapse models), "make it more intuitive" (e.g. Transactional interpretation) and attempts to redefine what should be expected from a scientific theory to include quantum physics (e.g. Qbism).
Last edited by a moderator: