In what sense does MWI fail to predict the Born Rule?

In summary, the Born Rule is a mathematical rule that describes how the probability of finding a particle or system in a particular state is related to the amount of energy it has.
  • #36
Derek P said:
Frequencies in a history? One history, one branch. No branch counting. But apparently frequencies are not enough, or else they don't emerge. I thought they were and they did but apparently they aren't or they don't, so we have to use decision theory in order to explain the projection rule. :biggrin:
I'm not aware of a solid proof that they emerge from Frequencies in a given history. It would be essentially equivalent to branch counting and run into the same problems. Regardless I haven't seen such a proof, or seen one mentioned where a frequency within a history approach is used that is different from branch counting.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
stevendaryl said:
So there is another special thing about the typical histories, which is that they obey some kind of symmetry principle---that if there is no reason to favor outcome ##A## over outcome ##B##, then they will have equal relative frequencies. That kind of aesthetic beauty only exists in some possible worlds. In the other ones, physics might not even develop --- but engineering and, as you say, religion probably would.
Well one would have to assume that the symmetry-breaking observations only and always took place in a laboratory but everywhere else things were typical, otherwise common sense would have evolved to expect symmetry-breaking and to regard the 50/50 case as strange!
 
  • #38
stevendaryl said:
It seems to me that arguments about proving Born's rule (using decision theory or some other logic) are sort of beside the point. Maybe there is a kind of "anthropopic principle" for the existence of viable theories, like there is one for the existence of intelligent life.

Suppose you have a nondeterministic theory of physics. This theory gives rise to a set of possible histories. Among those histories, only some of them will be "typical", where relative frequencies for repeated trials of random events are calculable from the theory. So even if the theory is "correct", only in the typical worlds will intelligent beings bother to develop that theory.
The problem with Many-Worlds is more that you can't even prove there are any typical histories, aside from uniform ones.

There has to be someway of deriving the association between the amplitudes and probabilities, regardless of if your world is similar to the expected values or not.

EDIT: Removed last line as it was written poorly
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes jbergman
  • #39
DarMM said:
The problem with Many-Worlds is more that you can't even prove there are any typical histories, aside from uniform ones.

I'm not sure what you mean. Let's pick an experiment: Say, I pick two directions in space, ##\vec{a}## and ##\vec{b}##, and I repeatedly perform the experiment:
  1. Put an electron into the state of having spin-up along the ##\vec{a}## axis.
  2. Later, measure its spin along the ##\vec{b}## axis, and write down either "U" or "D" in my notebook.
  3. Beside each entry, I also calculate the relative frequencies of ##U## versus ##D##, so far.
In the many-worlds interpretation, there will be many versions of my notebook. Some of them will have relative frequencies close to that predicted by quantum mechanics (##cos^2(\frac{\theta}{2})## where ##\theta## is the angle between ##\vec{a}## and ##\vec{b}##), and some will not.
 
  • #40
stevendaryl said:
ome of them will have relative frequencies close to that predicted by quantum mechanics (##cos^2(\frac{\theta}{2})## where ##\theta## is the angle between ##\vec{a}## and ##\vec{b}##), and some will not.
I've no problem that there will be worlds where the ratio matches the Born Rule.

Let me take a simpler case, the state of the particle is:

$$\sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} | \uparrow \rangle + \sqrt{\frac{2}{3}} | \downarrow \rangle \tag 1$$

and I repeatedly perform a set of measurements on the spin.

What shows that distribution of the observations across branches "peaks" around worlds where the frequency of observing spin-down is twice that of observing spin up?

That is to say that there is a higher weight of worlds "near" the 2:1 ratio. Or "more" worlds with the 2:1 ratio.

I don't see how the world structure is any different from the one resulting from repeated experiments on:

$$\sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} | \uparrow \rangle + \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} | \downarrow \rangle \tag 2$$
 
  • #41
DarMM said:
Currently it would seem that every world should see uniform frequencies.
I don't see why. A world is superposition of a vast collection of microstates created through entanglement. They are decoherent and therefore add as the square root of the number of states. At the same time the probabilities that each microstate contributes when the mess is finally observed add linearly. Where's the catch?
 
  • #42
That was poorly worded, #40 to stevendaryl is more my point.
 
  • #43
DarMM said:
Let me take a simpler case, the state of the particle is:

$$\sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} | \uparrow \rangle + \sqrt{\frac{2}{3}} | \downarrow \rangle \tag 1$$

and I repeatedly perform a set of measurements on the spin.

What shows that distribution of the observations across branches "peaks" around worlds where the frequency of observing spin-down is twice that of observing spin up?

There will be "worlds" where those expected frequencies occur, and worlds where they don't. The first type of world will be happy with quantum mechanics, and the other type will not be happy with it.

That is to say that there is a higher weight of worlds "near" the 2:1 ratio. Or "more" worlds with the 2:1 ratio.

That will be true, if we use the Born rule to weight possible worlds. But my point is that we developed QM within a single world, and what's important for us is that the Born rule works for repeated trials in our world. Why is it relevant to us what happens in other worlds?

I don't see how the world structure is any different from the one resulting from repeated experiments on:

$$\sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} | \uparrow \rangle + \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} | \downarrow \rangle \tag 2$$

That's a puzzling philosophical question, but what I would say is that there is nothing particularly quantum-mechanical about the puzzle. You can do the same thing with classical probabilities:

You flip a coin many times and convince yourself that it has a 50/50 chance of heads versus tails. Now, completely unknown to you, God (or some computer scientist, if you happen to be a simulation inside a supercomputer) does the following: Every time you flip a coin, God makes an exact copy of the world, and makes sure that in this copy, the opposite result occurs. He does the same for every new world: Every time someone in any of the worlds flips a coin, there are two copies made, one where the result is "heads" and the other where the result is "tails".

This multiverse has the nice property that the probability of any sequence of coin flips is equal to the fraction of worlds where that coin flip sequence happens. Great.

But now, suppose purely on a whim, God changes his mind, and changes his rule so that there are 2 copies made where the result is "heads" and only one copy where the result is "tails"? On the one hand, from the branch counting point of view, that makes heads have a probability of 66% while tails has a probability of 33%. That seems like a drastic change to the laws of physics. But surely, the extra copies have no effect on the existing copies? The existence or nonexistence of an alternate world can't possibly affect my empirically derived notion of relative frequencies. Regardless of how many copies are produced with each flip, some of the worlds will observe 50/50 relative frequencies, and will be happy because it agrees with their notions of symmetry. Others will observe other ratios and will be puzzled by the lack of symmetry in relative frequencies.
 
  • #44
DarMM said:
1. How do I know which "fictional" uniform case my state is a modification of to say my probability is ##1/N##?
Any choice should work, as long as the magnitude of each branch is equal.
2. How does this apply to something where a non-uniform probability state is measured by a single observer. Like electrons coming from a silver oven toward one detector.
This is all about what a single observer will experience, so I don't think I understand your point here.
However ignoring all this, it still doesn't answer the objection I always have to these derivations. What is the model?
The precise model is given by decoherence, quantum darwinism and other unitary dynamics. That's the same as all interpretations and it's complex, so I think it's right not to focus on it in regards to the Born rule.
Also it is in essence an extra axiom, as unitary QM only gives you the state above (3), which under a naive MWI reading is two-worlds. You have to add the assumption that the value of the amplitude also tells you how many copies there are of each world, e.g. in (3) there are two "down worlds".

However, if it's not branch-counting, what is it?
There are extra axioms, indeed. In Vaidman's approach, they are locality and symmetry principles, which say that if you decompose your state into equal-weighted branches, then branch counting agrees with the Born rule.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #45
DarMM said:
That is to say that there is a higher weight of worlds "near" the 2:1 ratio. Or "more" worlds with the 2:1 ratio.

I don't see how the world structure is any different from the one resulting from repeated experiments on:

$$\sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} | \uparrow \rangle + \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} | \downarrow \rangle \tag 2$$

If a river splits into two branches, one twice as wide as the other, nobody questions that a random fish will more likely end up flowing down the wider branch. Even though it has the same branching structure as an equal divide.

Akin to how the one real world in Bohmian mechanics can be represented as a point-particle guided by the wavefunction, instead of considering splitting it works to consider every point on the wavefunction as a possible world. And when they diverge, there will be a higher density of worlds/points following the higher-magnitude branches. At least for me, this is one approach I've found illustrative.
 
  • #46
akvadrako said:
If a river branches into two branches, one twice as wide as the other, nobody questions that a random fish will more likely end up flowing down the wider branch. Even though it has the same branching structure as an equal divide.

Akin to how the one real world in Bohmian mechanics can be represented as a point-particle guided by the wavefunction, instead of considering splitting it works to consider every point on the wavefunction as a possible world. And when they diverge, there will be a higher density of worlds/points following the higher-magnitude branches. At least for me, this is one approach I've found illustrative.

In Many-Worlds, there are two different notions of measure/probability that come into play: The probability of a world, and the relative frequencies within one world. They are related, in that if you use the Born rule to compute probabilities of possible worlds, then you will find that "most" worlds have relative frequencies that are given by the Born rule, as well.
 
  • #47
Many Worlds, the Born Rule, and Self-Locating Uncertainty
https://arxiv.org/abs/1405.7907

but from my point of view the derivation of Schrodinger equation should come first and since there is no such a thing yet, I see the whole exercise as futile.
 
  • #48
Derek P said:
Which is why I asked why.

Who says MW defines probability? Some make use of a certain version of it - decision theory - you can read about it - to derive the Born Rule. Although not generally discussed there are a number of interpretations of probability - decision theory is just one of them. Actuaries use it a lot in deterministic systems (probably chaotic like financial markets but no assumption of such is made) so it's mathematically valid - as always meaning is the issue.

Is that a valid issue with the interpretation?

Blowed if I know - like all interpretive stuff it often just degenerates into counter-productive heated arguments. They are of zero value. No interpretation is right or wrong - they are just interesting and educational ways to look at the formalism. You can decide what you like or do not like - no need for long threads about it.

What we do here interpretation wise is clarify what they say - not argue about it.

Fact - the Born Rule in MW is often justified using decision theory. You can decide if its a valid approach - arguing about it will simply result in people like me as a mentor keeping it on track. Then we have the non-contextuality theorem and Gleason. You have to get a hold of the book and study it to see if it can be attacked and post a specific question about it. It looks tight to me. But of course the whole issue of probability in a deterministic theory is an issue. But its philosophical which we do not discuss here. That is the real issue with MW - it's philosophical basis is very arguable - but philosophy is not what we discuss here.

Here is an example from the paper I linked to criticizing it. It says. 'Deutsch has proposed using decision theory to show that, under Everettian conditions, it would be rational to decide on bets about the results of quantum measurements as if they were probabilistic and followed the Born rule.' Well BM is deterministic yet all you can't predict things because of the uncertainty principle - only probabilities. This is similar to decision theory as a discipline - in some situations things are deterministic - we just, for some reason or another, do not know the outcome. So IMHO this argument against it is invalid. But these types of things are more philosophical on what probability is and generally just generate a lot of verbose discussion that in the end just says I view probability this way - scientifically IMHO dubious value.

If you want to go down that path, discussion that inherently go no-where will, correctly, be stomped on by mentors like me. They are counterproductive to the aims of the forum. By all means point out statements like the above from the paper are arguable - but don't argue it because it won't really resolve anything.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #49
stevendaryl said:
Let's pick an experiment:

That again raises (in my mind) the question of whether defining probability in terms of an observer refers to an actual observer or an conceptual observer that we only imagine. For example, for a given type of experiment, can there be a history (or "world") where it is never repeated?

Are we using the term "history" in the same sense as the "consistent histories" formulation of QM?

A complicated experiment like "Try to build a transatlantic tunnel" might never be attempted. Is it implicit in any formulation of QM that Nature is composed of "elementary" phenomena that may be always be regarded forming independent repeated experiments? This is different that the question of whether such independent repeated experiments in a world have the "correct" limiting frequencies of outcomes. (Mathematically, a sequence might not have any limiting outcome at all.)
 
  • #50
Stephen Tashi said:
Are we using the term "history" in the same sense as the "consistent histories" formulation of QM?

Actually, I prefer "history" in the sense of "recorded history". There is a macroscopic record of what has happened in previous experiments, and previous observations. Of course, we don't actually write down everything that happens and everything we see, and maybe we misremember, but I'm assuming that the only way we know what has happened in the past is because we have memories of it in the present, which is a fact about the present.

A complicated experiment like "Try to build a transatlantic tunnel" might never be attempted. Is it implicit in any formulation of QM that Nature is composed of "elementary" phenomena that may be always be regarded forming independent repeated experiments? This is different that the question of whether such independent repeated experiments in a world have the "correct" limiting frequencies of outcomes. (Mathematically, a sequence might not have any limiting outcome at all.)

Presumably, even if building a tunnel isn't something likely to be repeated, we can break it down into subevents that are repeatable: For example, metal striking stone. We can reason about the complex process in terms of the component events, right?
 
  • #51
If you don't mind akvadrako, I'm still mulling over your post regarding Vaidman's derivation, I want to read the paper closely again. So I'll just ask a simpler dumber question!

akvadrako said:
If a river splits into two branches, one twice as wide as the other, nobody questions that a random fish will more likely end up flowing down the wider branch. Even though it has the same branching structure as an equal divide.
How is this actually shown I guess is what I am asking. I don't see how the branch is twice as wide, unless it's because there are more copies of that branch.

EDIT: I should say I do of course see how it's "twice" as wide in the vector space sense, just I don't understand how more observers flow down it.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes jbergman
  • #52
Nugatory said:
They don't, but when they introduce the reduction of the wave function as an assumption they can incorporate the Born rule into that assumption. The difficulty for MWI is that MWI rejects any reduction postulate, so has to find the Born rule in unitary evolution.

Decoherent histories has the same issue. It resolves it simply - consistency replaces observation:
https://arxiv.org/pdf/gr-qc/9407040.pdf

You have mentioned many times by means of a coarse graining argument you can get the classical world from QM. Decoherent Histories builds this up from the concept of history which is simply a sequence of projections. In that interpretation QM is simply the stochastic theory of histories. The classical world, complete with the outcome of an observation emerges naturally without even introducing such concepts in the interpretation. In the view of Gell-Mann MW is simply decoherent histories where all the histories exist together in different worlds. He seemed to think the difference was more semantic than actual. The advantage of MW is just one wavefunction, the advantage of DH is its more commonsenseical.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #53
stevendaryl said:
This multiverse has the nice property that the probability of any sequence of coin flips is equal to the fraction of worlds where that coin flip sequence happens. Great.
Alright this is a bit clearer to me, is there a proof that the multiverse does in fact have this property?

stevendaryl said:
That will be true, if we use the Born rule to weight possible worlds. But my point is that we developed QM within a single world, and what's important for us is that the Born rule works for repeated trials in our world. Why is it relevant to us what happens in other worlds?
So in essence the Born Rule is simply an accident, it happens to be the ratio we see. Why do we continuously see it hold across several experiments? I would imagine the answer is because it (approximately) holds in "most" worlds. This leads back to my first question above. Is there a proof that "most" worlds have a Born Rule obeying history?
 
  • #54
bhobba said:
there are a number of interpretations of probability - decision theory is just one of them.

Interpreting Decision Theory might be a problem. In courses I have taken, Decision Theory involves making decisions given both a utility function and a probability model. Such an approach assumes probabilities are already defined.

The current Wikipedia says there are different types of decision theory. My understanding of the Decision Theory being applied to MWI is that it bases decisions on assigning "weights" to "branches" , without calling these "weights" probabilities. When it (supposedly) demonstrates that an observer in any (typical) world would always infer the same probabilities from an given type of experiment , it concludes that the common set of inferred probabilities is a function of the weights associated with the outcomes of the experiment -as given by the Born Rule.

This argument admits there are "maverick" worlds where experimenters infer the wrong probabilities. It considers these worlds unimportant. If it justifies their unimportance by saying they are "improbable" then it has become a circular argument which uses the concept of probability in order to define a concept of probability.
stevendaryl said:
Actually, I prefer "history" in the sense of "recorded history". There is a macroscopic record of what has happened in previous experiments, and previous observations. Of course, we don't actually write down everything that happens and everything we see, and maybe we misremember, but I'm assuming that the only way we know what has happened in the past is because we have memories of it in the present, which is a fact about the present.

But in high-class theoretical arguments, isn't a "history" supposed be enough to define a unique "branch" up to the time the history is recorded? Papers about MWI used the terminology "memory sequence". People can have false memories. I don't think "memory sequences" are allowed to be false records.

Presumably, even if building a tunnel isn't something likely to be repeated, we can break it down into subevents that are repeatable: For example, metal striking stone. We can reason about the complex process in terms of the component events, right?

Yes, we can reason that way based on common experience, but is it explicit or implicit in any mathematical formulation of QM that such repeated component events exist?
 
  • #55
Stephen Tashi said:
Interpreting Decision Theory might be a problem.

Some argue it is. But do you think we will reach a resolution and it will not devolve into philosophy? Specifically it is a type of Bayesian - that utility function can be objective or it can be subjective. In MW its a subjective weight a rational entity would assign to a world (history might be a better term) that rational entity would bet on experiencing. Of course just like the Baysian interpretation of probability that rational entity does not have to be there and is a minefield of all sorts of unresolved philosophical issues.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #56
bhobba said:
Some argue it is. But do you think we will reach a resolution and it will not devolve into philosophy? Specifically it is a type of Bayesian - that utility function can be objective or it can be subjective.
I don't know if we'll reach a resolution, but there are criticisms of the Decision Theory approach that aren't philosophical, such as those of Kent in "One World Versus Many: The Inadequacy of Everettian Accounts of Evolution, Probability, and Scientific Confirmation":

https://arxiv.org/abs/0905.0624

Now some of his objections are philosophical, but his criticisms of Wallace's axioms are mostly physical.
 
  • #57
bhobba said:
Derek P said:
Which is why I asked why.
Who says MW defines probability? Some make use of a certain version of it - decision theory - you can read about it - to derive the Born Rule.
[good stuff]
But its philosophical which we do not discuss here. That is the real issue with MW - it's philosophical basis is very arguable - but philosophy is not what we discuss here.
Quite so. I asked that people keep on topic in post 22. I'm still nursing a faint hope I'll get an answer to my question without needing "philosophy" other than a naive ontology.
 
  • #58
Derek P said:
A world is superposition of a vast collection of microstates created through entanglement. They are decoherent and therefore add as the square root of the number of states.
akvadrako said:
The precise model is given by decoherence, quantum darwinism and other unitary dynamics. That's the same as all interpretations and it's complex, so I think it's right not to focus on it in regards to the Born rule.
Just another question, doesn't decoherence already require the Born rule, to permit tracing over the environment? Hence without the Born Rule, how do you show the state vector is of essentially Schmidt form to permit the clear branching structure without the Born Rule?
 
  • #59
DarMM said:
How is this actually shown I guess is what I am asking. I don't see how the branch is twice as wide, unless it's because there are more copies of that branch.
I can try but I don't think I can be more clear than the author. If you are interested, similar techniques are used in most of the other attempts so they might be enlightening.

To start, let's say nothing is assumed about the relation between two branches. So your example with ##\sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} | \uparrow \rangle + \sqrt{\frac{2}{3}} | \downarrow \rangle## isn't analysable yet. But after decomposing it into terms with with equal weights of ##\sqrt{\frac{1}{3}}##, you can use the symmetry principle to assume branches of equal weight are equally likely and the probability can be calculated.
 
  • #60
DarMM said:
Now some of his objections are philosophical, but his criticisms of Wallace's axioms are mostly physical.

I don't know about mostly but yes some are physical. All however are arguable. Wallace give an account in his book at least on some.

I am not advocating one view or the other.

I want to point out its relation to decoherent histories and both have similar unresolved and arguable issues. The peculiar issue to MW is in what way can the Born rule be given meaning and/or derived. This has been argued ad-infinitum with no resolution. It will not be resolved here. If people wish to pursue it I think its counterproductive to the forums aims. There are texts and papers on it. Specific questions can be asked and that's fine - beyond that it won't go anywhere IMHO.

The answer to the asked question is MW is a deterministic theory - there are issues in applying conventional notions of probability to such. Various views exist - and I have given papers and a text. Read the paper and texts then formulate answerable questions.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #61
Okay fair enough, thanks for the discussion everybody, I think I need to read a bit more and return with more specific questions.
 
  • #62
DarMM said:
Okay fair enough, thanks for the discussion everybody, I think I need to read a bit more and return with more specific questions.

Look into Gleason.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes Derek P
  • #63
bhobba said:
Look into Gleason.

Thanks
Bill
I know the proof of Gleason's theorem, but it has never genuinely helped me comprehend the MWI arguments as it comes from a very different direction, Wallace argues that his proof is a separate line of argumentation to Gleason. I think I need to read Wallace's book in full perhaps.
 
  • #64
stevendaryl said:
In the "typical" history, the relative frequency for heads is 0.5. In an atypical history, maybe the relative frequency for heads is 0.7.
But these are histories that can be many times generated and compared, so that one can tell what is typical. For ''worlds'', this is impossible - so calling a world typical or atypical if only one is known is kind of weird.
stevendaryl said:
In the many-worlds interpretation, there will be many versions of my notebook.
There are all imaginable versions of your notebook, and calling some of them typical is prejudice based on the few notebooks in the single world you have access to.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes jbergman
  • #65
stevendaryl said:
There will be "worlds" where those expected frequencies occur, and worlds where they don't. The first type of world will be happy with quantum mechanics, and the other type will not be happy with it.
So you call the ones conforming to the laws observed in our world typical, because they are similar to our worlds, and worlds that do not, atypical. I believe the correct word for the notion you have in mind is not ''typical'' but ''like the one we actually observe''. Thus it is tautological that in these worlds we observe Born's rule.
DarMM said:
I would imagine the answer is because it (approximately) holds in "most" worlds.
The problem is that ''most'' has no meaning unless you have a means to actually estimate the numbers. With access to only a single world, it is as if we had been shown only the result a single throw of a die (say, 2), without recourse to the mechanism of generating it (involving symmetry and labels 1,...,6), and have to deduce from that the probability law for casting dice.
 
  • #66
Derek P said:
in what sense does MWI fail to predict the Born Rule?
The real question is: In what sense does MWI predict Born's rule? I cannot see any coherent argument.
 
  • Like
Likes jbergman and Stephen Tashi
  • #67
A. Neumaier said:
So you call the ones conforming to the laws observed in our world typical, because they are similar to our worlds, and worlds that do not, atypical.

No, that's not what I was saying. A world is typical or not relative to a proposed law of physics depending on whether the relative frequencies in that world correspond to the probabilities derived from that theory.
 
  • #68
stevendaryl said:
No, that's not what I was saying. A world is typical or not relative to a proposed law of physics depending on whether the relative frequencies in that world correspond to the probabilities derived from that theory.
Yes, this is exactly what I was paraphrasing.

You know exactly one world and what is typical there. Based on this you propose a law of which you know that it holds in this particular world to some approximation. Then you postulate that among all other worlds, those are typical that behave like the single example you know of. It is no surprise that this way of proceeding predicts, no matter with which world you start, that this world satisfies the laws you started with.

If the world under consideration permitted only experiments where the result is always 0.707, this would be the observed law of physics. Now you might propose for arbitrary worlds the law of physics that the result is a constant ##p\in [0,1]##. Then a world would be called typical if ##p\approx 0.707##. To make you theory predictive in the MWI sense, you just need to postulate in addition that the worlds are distributed such that ##p^2## is uniformly distributed in [0,1] and that our world is randomly drawn from it. Now - abrakadabra - you can find an easy derivation of the law of physics in our particular world by doing elementary statistics:
The given world represents the mean value of all possible worlds. By improving the statistics of the proposed collection of worlds, i.e., by requiring that these worlds are even more like the given world, one can make the probability of finding the given world overwhelmingly large.

Of course ''possible'' and ''probable'' is only according to your prejudiced assumptions about what constitutes a possible world. Nothing at all depends on any of these worlds actually existing, or on the true existence or nonexistence of many other worlds that are mostly completely different from the given world.

Thus you assumed what you wanted to derive/explain, just disguised in a lot of mystery about alternative worlds.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #69
I suppose I have one specific question.

We can roughly divide C*-algebras into a few classes based on a two axes of distinction. The first being commutative and non-commutative. The second being the factor type:
$$I_{n},\quad I_{\infty},\quad II_{n},\quad II_{\infty},\quad III_{\lambda}$$

Discrete Classical Probability theory is commutative ##I_{n}##, qubit systems are non-commutative ##I_{n}##, normal non-relativistic QM is Type ##I_{\infty}##. Type ##II## algebras, depending on if commutative or non-commutative, are classical or quantum statistical mechanics (in the thermodynamic limit).
Non-Commutative Type ##III_{1}## has been shown by Fredenhagen and Longo to be the algebra involved in QFT, making QFT in a sense the most general probability theory possible.

Given that Many-Worlds keeps the same formalism as Quantum Mechanics, I was wondering if in the literature there is a discussion of the reasons the theory is isomorphic to a probability theory (and in QFT's case, the unique most general one) given that it is deterministic? It seems odd to me that in a theory that is about the deterministic evolution of the universe, with probability only arising from local subjective viewpoints, the deterministic evolution would have the mathematical form of a probability theory. Is this discussed anywhere? (I've looked, but people here might have better knowledge)
 
  • #70
Derek P said:
I think it is a very awkward attempt to reinstate the idea of probability as a real property of the system. I don't know why anyone would want to do this as MWI seems to predict observation frequencies perfectly well without defining instrinsic probability or whatever you want to call it. But does it? This of course is why I started this thread

Without assuming the concept of probability, how would you define being successful at predicting observational frequencies?

If we use the concept of probability, there are familiar ways to define what it means to be successful at predicting observational frequencies - namely that the prediction method predicts a frequency that has a high probability of being the actual probability. However, what definition can we make without the concept of probability?

There have been attempts to found probability theory on actual frequencies, such as the "collectives" of Richard von Mises. However, I'm not aware of any that meet the modern standards of mathematical rigor.

There is the fundamental problem that "frequency" is a concept (initially) defined for finite numbers of events. For infinite collections of events, frequency must be defined as a limit. To define that limit, some way of considering only a finite number of events from the infinite collection must be specified.

Taking pains to speak only of frequencies, how do we decide if MWI predicts the Born Rule? It has to be something like "On the the most frequent branches ( i.e. the most frequent "wolds") , the frequency of events observed in a repeated experiment is approximately the frequency given by the Born Rule." The delicate part of that argument is how to define what finite sets of branches are used in computing the frequency of branches.

There is a non-circular and non-trivial aspect to the above argument. It is not self-evident that there is a single set of weights than can be used in defining how we pick finite sets of branches to use in defining their frequency that also works to produce the frequencies of events observed in experiments within the frequent branches. If such a set of weights exists, how do we know it is unique? If the weights exist and are unique, we still have to show they correspond to the numbers (for probabilities) given by the Born Rule.

The above type of argument using only frequencies can be disparaged as "branch counting". However, without taking the notion of probability as fundamental, I don't see any alternative approach.
 

Similar threads

Replies
16
Views
3K
Replies
4
Views
1K
Replies
6
Views
2K
Replies
45
Views
11K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
14
Views
3K
Back
Top