Quantum mechanics is not weird, unless presented as such

In summary, quantum mechanics may seem weird due to the way it is often presented to the general public. However, there is a long history of this approach, as it sells better. In reality, it can be an obstacle for those trying to truly understand the subject. The paper referenced in the conversation shows that quantum mechanics can actually be derived from reasonable assumptions, making it not as weird as some may think. However, this derivation is only one author's view and may not be the complete truth. There are also other interpretations of quantum mechanics, such as the ensemble interpretation, which may not be fully satisfactory. Overall, a proper derivation of quantum mechanics must account for all aspects, including the treatment of measurement devices and the past before measurements
  • #526
A. Neumaier said:
Does quantum mechanics have to be weird?

It sells much better to the general public if it is presented that way, and there is a long history of proceeding that way.

But in fact it is an obstacle for everyone who wants to truly understand quantum mechanics, and to physics students who have to unlearn what they were told as laypersons.

I think that while the discussion about the Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics is still such a controversial subject then yes QM is weird even to the intiated. Sure the maths is there and is solid, but we can't yet properly bridge the gap between what the equations tell us and the correct way to fully apply it to reality. QM still stands out there on its own as the subject in physics which blows the mind of the undergrad and has never been truly reconcilled with our experience. Delving into the maths allows us to hold the technical knowledge to make predictions in laboratory conditions but we don't yet have a way to perceive the subject which stops it being weird. I think I'm in good company in believing that the study of the Interpretations of QM is highly significant in understanding the scope of the problem of Quantum Gravity.

The fact that on this forum, Interpretations of QM is still so often deferred to the realms of philosophy while we don't have solutions to the Preferred Basis Problem (and its ilk) and QG are testament to the fact that we all still find it weird.

From an educational perspective, I fully understand that for the purpose of motivation, QM is presented as mysterious from the outset with the Double Slit Experiment, but there is no route through the subject which can avoid the question of how the quantum world gives rise to our everyday experience, and we just don't have all the information to explain it. Personally, I can't buy the arguments that, for any given interpretation, all that remains to be done is "dotting the i's and crossing the t's", because each of those come from a presumption that the originating interpretation is correct, which only has subjective merit.

In my experience physicists are naturally depth first learners as opposed to breadth first learners and QM is taught depth first to avoid the complexity of the Interpretations of QM but the bright physicist naturally generates questions on how to interpret the subject and these questions should be addressed even without any definitive answer.

There are still questions to be answered and research to be performed, to explain how the microscopic world and macroscropic world co-exist. I firmly believe that until we have the answers to these questions then we should be mindful that we while we can make any particular interpretation work, with some unknowns, we cannot presume any interpretation to be correct and that is the source of the weirdness.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #527
rubi said:
You can't just define a quantity and claim that it represents a correlation.

I can define anything I want, since names don't have any intrinsic value in themselves. Maybe you and Khrennikov like to reserve the word "correlation" for something different than what's used in some simple Bell inequalities like CHSH. If that's the case then good for you, but that doesn't say anything about Bell's theorem.

That is the quantum mechanical expression and it doesn't take the same form as the one you wrote, precisely, because we are dealing with a contextual theory.

Your reply doesn't even make any sense. I took the definition that I wrote for ##E_{xy}## and that you quoted and I substituted in the Born rule to get the quantum mechanical expression for ##E_{xy}##.

Actually you have proven yourself wrong here, because with your expression, you can achieve at most ##2##, rather than ##2\sqrt{2}##, so the quantum mechanical expression for ##E_{xy}## must necessarily be different form the one you gave.

Huh? Given only the definition ##E_{xy} = P(00 \mid xy) - P(01 \mid xy) - P(10 \mid xy) + P(11 \mid xy)##, the algebraic bound on the CHSH expression is 4. Only Bell-local models are limited to 2.
 
  • #528
wle said:
I can define anything I want, since names don't have any intrinsic value in themselves. Maybe you and Khrennikov like to reserve the word "correlation" for something different than what's used in some simple Bell inequalities like CHSH. If that's the case then good for you, but that doesn't say anything about Bell's theorem.
Well, you can define whatever you want, but I'm telling you what it means: It is the correlation that you get by assuming that all random variables live on a single probability space. It's not me and Khrennikov, but rather the whole mathematics and physics community that defines correlations the way I told you and you will find it in every single book on the topic. I'm telling you that your definition is just a special case of the general definition. Again, if you want to understand subtleties, you have to be rigorous about everything. Your presentation of the proof would not be acceptable to a probability theorist. The first thing he'd ask you is: "What probability spaces are you working with?"

Your reply doesn't even make any sense. I took the definition that I wrote for ##E_{xy}## and that you quoted and I substituted in the Born rule to get the quantum mechanical expression for ##E_{xy}##.
Woops, I misread. I somehow thought you had already included the locality condition and performed the integral. The combination of your ##E_{xy}## and the locality condition implies a specific probability space. You can only split it up that way, because the measures happen to be product measures. (You can also have a locality condition in the contextual case! See Khrennikovs paper.) However, you can always split up mathematical expressions into two parts. That doesn't mean that they refer to one thing.

Huh? Given only the definition ##E_{xy} = P(00 \mid xy) - P(01 \mid xy) - P(10 \mid xy) + P(11 \mid xy)##, the algebraic bound on the CHSH expression is 4. Only Bell-local models are limited to 2.
Yes, again, I had the complete definition of ##E_{xy}## in mind. The point is that the quantum mechanical expression cannot coincide with Bell's.
 
  • #529
wle said:
I can define anything I want, since names don't have any intrinsic value in themselves. Maybe you and Khrennikov like to reserve the word "correlation" for something different than what's used in some simple Bell inequalities like CHSH. If that's the case then good for you, but that doesn't say anything about Bell's theorem.

wle said:
Your reply doesn't even make any sense. I took the definition that I wrote for ##E_{xy}## and that you quoted and I substituted in the Born rule to get the quantum mechanical expression for ##E_{xy}##.

wle said:
Huh? Given only the definition ##E_{xy} = P(00 \mid xy) - P(01 \mid xy) - P(10 \mid xy) + P(11 \mid xy)##, the algebraic bound on the CHSH expression is 4. Only Bell-local models are limited to 2.

Labelling the outcomes as ##+1## and ##-1##, Wikipedia gives ##E(a,b) = \int{\underline{A}(a,\lambda)\underline{B}(b,\lambda})\rho(\lambda)d\lambda##, which is why rubi says it is a correlation or an expectation.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CHSH_inequality

However, like you, I don't see how the contextuality assumption enters, since the quantity can be directly computed in quantum mechanics.
 
  • #530
Let me make it clear by stating the assumptions completely:
In an experiment, we measure correlations ##E_{ab}## and we can ask, whether there is a probabilistic model that explains these explanation. So we are looking for the following:
1. A probability space ##(\Gamma_{ab},\Sigma,\mu_{ab})##
2. Random variables ##A_a : \Gamma_{ab}\rightarrow \{-1,1\}## and ##B_b : \Gamma_{ab}\rightarrow \{-1,1\}##
We want ##E_{ab}= \int_{\Gamma_{ab}} A_a(\gamma) B_b(\gamma)\mathrm d\mu_{ab}(\gamma)##.

Bell assumes ##\Gamma_{ab} = \Lambda##, ##\mathrm d\mu_{ab}=\rho(\lambda)\mathrm d\lambda##, ##A_a : \Lambda\rightarrow \{-1,1\}## and ##B_b : \Lambda\rightarrow \{-1,1\}##, so ##E_{ab}=\int_\Lambda A_a(\lambda) B_b(\lambda)\mathrm \rho(\lambda)\mathrm d\lambda## and this already includes his locality condition.

A contextual theory would be: ##\Gamma_{ab} = \Lambda\times\Lambda_a\times\Lambda_b##, ##A_a : \Lambda\times\Lambda_a\times\Lambda_b\rightarrow \{-1,1\}## and ##B_b : \Lambda\times\Lambda_a\times\Lambda_b\rightarrow \{-1,1\}## and the locality condition would be ##A_a(\lambda,\lambda_a,\lambda_b) = A_a(\lambda,\lambda_a)## and ##B_b(\lambda,\lambda_a,\lambda_b) = B_b(\lambda,\lambda_b)##. So ##E_{ab}=\int_{\Lambda\times\Lambda_a\times\Lambda_b} A_a(\lambda,\lambda_a) B_b(\lambda,\lambda_b)\mathrm d\mu_{ab}(\lambda,\lambda_a,\lambda_b)##.

These are two different ways to define a probabilistic model that explains the correlations. In Bell's case, the random variables all live on one probability space, while in the contextual case, they live on many different spaces, depending on ##a## and ##b##.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #531
rubi said:
Again, if you want to understand subtleties, you have to be rigorous about everything. Your presentation of the proof would not be acceptable to a probability theorist. The first thing he'd ask you is: "What probability spaces are you working with?"

I think I've been quite a bit more rigorous than you in this thread. Among other things I gave you an outline of Bell's theorem and invited you to point out exactly where your "single probability space" assumption is being introduced. All you've done since then is take issue with a simple definition at the beginning, before I even mentioned Bell locality, and lecture me about rigour.

atyy said:
However, like you, I don't see how the contextuality assumption enters, since the quantity can be directly computed in quantum mechanics.

Indeed, I don't think rubi is even reading my posts.
 
  • #532
wle said:
I think I've been quite a bit more rigorous than you in this thread. Among other things I gave you an outline of Bell's theorem and invited you to point out exactly where your "single probability space" assumption is being introduced. All you've done since then is take issue with a simple definition at the beginning, before I even mentioned Bell locality, and lecture me about rigour.
You don't need to give me an outline of the proof, since I already have seen it. You lack rigor for the reason that you don't specify your assumptions at a level of rigor that a mathematician would find acceptable and this is also the reason for why you are unable to see where the assumptions are made. What you call "a simple definition" is the crucial point of the argument, so I naturally put emphasis on it.

The point is that Bell uses a very specific probabilistic model to explain the correlations and he shows that this model is not consistent with QM. However, Bell's model is not the only model one could pick. You only see this if you are rigorous about all parts of the argument.
 
  • #533
rubi said:
You don't need to give me an outline of the proof, since I already have seen it. You lack rigor for the reason that you don't specify your assumptions at a level of rigor that a mathematician would find acceptable and this is also the reason for why you are unable to see where the assumptions are made. What you call "a simple definition" is the crucial point of the argument, so I naturally put emphasis on it.

The point is that Bell uses a very specific probabilistic model to explain the correlations and he shows that this model is not consistent with QM. However, Bell's model is not the only model one could pick. You only see this if you are rigorous about all parts of the argument.

But wle's point is that the expectation value does exist within quantum mechanics itself, so defining the expectation value does not constitute an assumption of non-contextuality.
 
  • #534
atyy said:
But wle's point is that the expectation value does exist within quantum mechanics itself, so defining the expectation value does not constitute an assumption of non-contextuality.
That's a misunderstanding, the QM expectation value is a way to obtain the numerical values of the correlations. A probabilistic model is a theory that explains the correlations. The QM expectation value doesn't yet include a hidden variable. Bell wants to explain the correlations by postulating that the random variables live on a single probability space. However, one can think of a different, more complicated probabilistic model that explains the correlations by allowing contextuality (i.e. several probability spaces). Bell doesn't consider the possibility to explain the correlations this way in his proof. The violation of his inequality only falsifies his specific probabilistic model, not the contextual one (see my post #530).

Edit: In other words: Bell assumes a specific probabilistic model to explain the correlations and he finds that it satisfies an inequality. This inequality is violated, so his model cannot explain the correlations. Since his proof assumed his specific probabilistic model, it cannot be used to argue against the other one. One would have to prove an individual inequality that is satisfied by the contextual model or find some other argument to falsify it.

Edit2: So here is a challenge for you and wle: Prove that the contextual model in post #530 is incompatible with the predictions of QM.

And by the way, it is not important for this argument, whether wle splits up his model for the correlations into two parts or not. His model is exactly the same model as the first one I gave in post #530, just phrased differently.
 
Last edited:
  • #535
rubi said:
You lack rigor for the reason that you don't specify your assumptions at a level of rigor that a mathematician would find acceptable

Bell's theorem is physics, not mathematics. Your post #530 likewise doesn't impress me as a physicist, for instance, since it completely ignores the context that Bell's theorem was derived in. In particular, the variable ##\lambda## appearing in Bell's theorem is intended to represent initial conditions that you know or could know, according to some theory, that could help you eventually make predictions about the outcomes in an experiment. This means it should have a well defined value independently of the measurements pretty much by definition. Even quantum physics provides an object for this purpose -- the initial quantum state -- that is well defined independently of the measurements that are eventually performed.

I shouldn't even have to argue this since the point seems to me to already have been made: Khrennikov's article was published several years ago and it has not generally impacted the way we think about Bell's theorem.

this is also the reason for why you are unable to see where the assumptions are made

Your post #530 undermines your point as far as I am concerned. First of all, if you thought the "hidden assumption" was that the variable ##\lambda## in Bell's theorem is well defined independently of the measurements, you could have just said so. I don't think the mathematical jargon in your post makes that clearer at all. Second, like I point out, introducing different "probability spaces" for the variable ##\lambda## associated with different measurements doesn't make a whole lot of sense if you consider Bell's theorem in context, so it is not something I would have flagged by being "more rigorous".
 
  • #536
wle said:
Bell's theorem is physics, not mathematics.
Physics also needs to use valid mathematics. Being mathematically precise about everything just improves clarity. You wanted me to expose, where Bell assumes a single probability space. I then described it rigorously, so not even you seem to question the assumption anymore, and now you are accusing me for using rigorous mathematics.

Your post #530 likewise doesn't impress me as a physicist, for instance, since it completely ignores the context that Bell's theorem was derived in. In particular, the variable ##\lambda## appearing in Bell's theorem is intended to represent initial conditions that you know or could know, according to some theory, that could help you eventually make predictions about the outcomes in an experiment. This means it should have a well defined value independently of the measurements pretty much by definition. Even quantum physics provides an object for this purpose -- the initial quantum state -- that is well defined independently of the measurements that are eventually performed.
Bell's theorem is not relevant for the contextual model. The point of the contextual model is to provide an alternative explanation for the correlations. It also has a variable ##\lambda## that is common to all measurements and that serves to describe pre-determined information. As I pointed out earlier, the purpose of my argument was to argue for the possibility of a common cause explanation of the correlations, which can in principle be achieved by the contextual model through the variable ##\lambda##. Thus locality is not falsified by QM. I don't care, whether the contextual model is not a classical deterministic theory. After all, QM isn't one either. I only care about saving locality. Since the contextual model has not yet been falsified, locality is not falsified either, whether you like it or not. In order to argue against locality, you would have to argue against the contextual model, rather than questioning that Bell assumes a single probability space, which you did since the beginning of the argument.

I shouldn't even have to argue this since the point seems to me to already have been made: Khrennikov's article was published several years ago and it has not generally impacted the way we think about Bell's theorem.
If all physicists are like you, then this is not surprising. You were already rejecting his argument aggresively, before you had even attempted to understand it. Also, the paper is not even 10 years old. This is a very short amount of time for research level physics to reach a larger audience.

Your post #530 undermines your point as far as I am concerned. First of all, if you thought the "hidden assumption" was that the variable ##\lambda## in Bell's theorem is well defined independently of the measurements, you could have just said so.
This is not the "hidden assumption". The hidden variable ##\lambda## is well defined independently of the measurements even in the contextual model, because it is a variable that is shared by all the probability spaces. The "hidden assumption" is the fact that the ##X_x## live on one single probability space, and it is also not "hidden", since it is clearly visible even in informal arguments (unless one tries to hide it explicitely).

I don't think the mathematical jargon in your post makes that clearer at all.
The "mathematical jargon" exposes the underlying probability structure precisely, while informal presentations never emphasize it. The point of science is to be precise about every subtlety, rather than to sweep things under the carpet.

Second, like I point out, introducing different "probability spaces" for the variable ##\lambda## associated with different measurements doesn't make a whole lot of sense if you consider Bell's theorem in context, so it is not something I would have flagged by being "more rigorous".
As I said, the variable ##\lambda## is shared by all probability spaces. The point of the contextual theory is that ##\lambda## does not solely determine the correlations. There can be additional ##\lambda_x## for every context.
 
  • #537
rubi said:
As I said, the variable ##\lambda## is shared by all probability spaces. The point of the contextual theory is that ##\lambda## does not solely determine the correlations. There can be additional ##\lambda_x## for every context.

I think that misses the point of Bell's theorem, like I said.
 
  • #538
rubi said:
As I said, the variable ##\lambda## is shared by all probability spaces. The point of the contextual theory is that ##\lambda## does not solely determine the correlations. There can be additional ##\lambda_x## for every context.

Doesn't this traditionally come under the outs called "superdeterminism" or "free will"? It seem the same as what is discussed eg. under the "locality loophole" on p51 of http://arxiv.org/abs/1303.2849.
 
  • #539
wle said:
I think that misses the point of Bell's theorem, like I said.
Well, it misses the point of Bell's theorem, because it is supposed to miss the point of Bell's theorem. Bell wants to exclude deterministic hidden variables and the violation of the inequality shows that he was successful. It's not about finding a loophole in Bell's argument, I happily reject deterministic hidden variables. The point of the contextual model is to offer an alternative explanation to deterministic hidden variables, while still maintaining locality. The question is: Is there an apriori reason to exclude contextual probabilistic models like the one I described in post #530? If not, then either we can show that these models are incompatible with QM as well (which I doubt), or we are unable to claim that QM violates locality.

atyy said:
Doesn't this traditionally come under the outs called "superdeterminism" or "free will"? It seem the same as what is discussed eg. under the "locality loophole" on p51 of http://arxiv.org/abs/1303.2849.
I don't think it is the same as superdeterminism, since it doesn't require any kind of fine-tuning and it also doesn't doubt the free will of the experimenters. The locality loophole in that article seems to be concerned with deterministic hidden variables as well. I think the point of all loopholes is to reject the conclusions of Bell's theorem, in order to save local realism. The contextual models don't attempt to save local realism. Instead, they offer an alternative to local realism. (By local realism, I mean Bell's probabilistic model.)
 
  • #540
rubi said:
I don't think it is the same as superdeterminism, since it doesn't require any kind of fine-tuning and it also doesn't doubt the free will of the experimenters. The locality loophole in that article seems to be concerned with deterministic hidden variables as well. I think the point of all loopholes is to reject the conclusions of Bell's theorem, in order to save local realism. The contextual models don't attempt to save local realism. Instead, they offer an alternative to local realism. (By local realism, I mean Bell's probabilistic model.)

It seems to me that if there are additional ##\lambda_{x}##, and ##x## is the measurement choice, then the measurement choice is not independent of the preparation, so it is a violation of free will.

Edit: Another example which I think makes clear that what you are talking about is freedom of choice is Scheidl's http://arxiv.org/abs/0811.3129: "In other words, the probability distribution of the hidden variables is therefore independent of the setting choices: ρ(λ|a,b) = ρ(λ) for all settings a and b. Without this independence, there is a loophole for local realistic theories which has not been addressed by any experiment to date."
 
Last edited:
  • #541
stevendaryl said:
Bell discussed a toy model for EPR correlations in which the "hidden variable" was a hemisphere, and Alice measured spin-up if she chose an axis in that hemisphere, and spin-down if she chose an axis not in that hemisphere. That model does not replicate the predictions of QM.
Agreed, I have come across this too. I believe that the toy model assumes a direction that is predetermined in all three directions. My toy model assumes that it is only predetermined in one.
 
  • #542
rubi said:
Well, it misses the point of Bell's theorem, because it is supposed to miss the point of Bell's theorem. Bell wants to exclude deterministic hidden variables and the violation of the inequality shows that he was successful. It's not about finding a loophole in Bell's argument, I happily reject deterministic hidden variables. The point of the contextual model is to offer an alternative explanation to deterministic hidden variables, while still maintaining locality. The question is: Is there an apriori reason to exclude contextual probabilistic models like the one I described in post #530? If not, then either we can show that these models are incompatible with QM as well (which I doubt), or we are unable to claim that QM violates locality.

As far as I'm concerned, the way Bell defined locality excludes the sort of contextual hidden variables you're describing: the point is to be able to explain correlations in terms of some common origin or past interaction, described by variables ##\lambda##, and variables that don't have a value independently of the choice of measurement aren't useful for this purpose. But if you define locality differently than Bell did then of course the result can be different.

If you want to argue that we should be OK with a type of contextual local model that is more general than Bell then you need to consider why one might want an alternative model to quantum physics in the first place. If you look at Bell's reasons, he criticised quantum physics for being too vague and badly defined, specifically describing what we would nowadays call the measurement problem. From this perspective I think contextuality doesn't even qualify as a well-defined physical concept since, for me, if you call a model "contextual" you're basically admitting it will have the same sort of measurement problem as quantum physics does.
 
  • #543
stevendaryl said:
No, I wasn't arguing for that. What I assumed, as I said in an earlier post, was:
  1. There is a single random variable, [itex]\lambda[/itex], associated with the twin pair. This is chosen according to some probability distribution, [itex]P(\lambda)[/itex].
  2. When a particle reaches Alice, she has already picked a measurement setting [itex]\vec{a}[/itex], and her device is already in some state [itex]\alpha[/itex]. Then she will get result [itex]+1[/itex] according to some probability [itex]P_A(\vec{a}, \alpha, \lambda)[/itex] that depends on [itex]\vec{a}[/itex], [itex]\alpha[/itex] and [itex]\lambda[/itex].
  3. Similarly, when the other particle reaches Bob, he will get result [itex]+1[/itex] according to some probability [itex]P_B(\vec{b}, \beta, \lambda)[/itex] that depends on [itex]\vec{b}[/itex], [itex]\beta[/itex] and [itex]\lambda[/itex], where [itex]\vec{b}[/itex] is his detector's setting, and [itex]\beta[/itex] is other facts about his detector.
There is no assumption of determinism here. But there is no way to reproduce the perfect anti-correlations predicted by QM unless Alice's and Bob's results are deterministic functions of [itex]\lambda, \vec{a}[/itex] and [itex]\vec{b}[/itex], or unless there are nonlocal interactions (so that [itex]P_A[/itex] may depend on facts about Bob, or [itex]P_B[/itex] may depend on facts about Alice).

In this paper by C.S. Unnikrishnan http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0407041.pdf
" If both analyzers were set to the same direction a=b the (anti) correlation is perfect according
to the conservation of angular momentum "
And later he shows that P (a,b)c = - ab = P(a,b)QM = -cos (θ)
 
  • Like
Likes stevendaryl
  • #544
Jilang said:
Agreed, I have come across this too. I believe that the toy model assumes a direction that is predetermined in all three directions. My toy model assumes that it is only predetermined in one.

Well, I don't see how that could possibly work. It would be nice to see you work out the mathematics to show what such a model predicts for correlations.
 
  • #545
Closed pending moderation

Edit: the thread has outlived its usefulness and will remain closed
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

Replies
21
Views
1K
  • New Member Introductions
Replies
7
Views
300
Replies
36
Views
3K
  • Sticky
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
6K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
7
Replies
218
Views
12K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
14
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
2K
Back
Top