An argument against Bohmian mechanics?

In summary: Simple systems can exhibit very different behavior from more complex systems with a large number of degrees of freedom. This is a well-known fact in physics. Thus, I don't understand why you keep bringing up the hydrogen atom as a counterexample to ergodic behavior, when it is not a representative system for such a discussion. In summary, Neumaier argues that Bohmian mechanics is wrong because it fails to predict all observed results from experiments. However, this argument ignores the theory of quantum measurements and fails to take into account the effect of measurement. Furthermore, the Bohmian theory of quantum measurements is incomplete and cannot fully explain the behavior of the single universe we know of. Additionally, the claim that ergodic theorem is necessary for
  • #316
atyy said:
But the world is manifestly not in thermodynamic equilibrium.
And that's one of the greatest mysteries in statistical physics. A natural state is thermodynamic equilibrium, and nobody knows why exactly we are not in equilibrium.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #317
Demystifier said:
And that's one of the greatest mysteries in statistical physics. A natural state is thermodynamic equilibrium, and nobody knows why exactly we are not in equilibrium.

Well, at least you are consistent. I've always thought the mystery was why silly things like the canonical ensemble actually work :)
 
  • #318
vanhees71 said:
What you describe further is the collapse hypothesis,

Tell me how my story changes if you don't assume collapse. I think that without collapse, then measurements become only subjective, which is basically the Many Worlds idea.

I would distinguish three aspects of the collapse hypothesis:
  1. After measurement, there is no longer observable interference between alternatives.
  2. Measurement reveals a fact about the world (that a certain observable has a certain value).
  3. After measurement, the composite system (system measured plus measuring device plus environment) is in a state consistent with the value measured, and so from then on, evolves from that state, not the original superposition.
Number 1 is not a necessary assumption, because it is presumably derivable from ordinary quantum mechanics, if you take into account decoherence.

So in denying collapse, are you denying 2? Measurements don't actually reveal anything about the world? I can't believe that. How could a result count as a measurement if it doesn't tell us anything about the world? But if it does tell us something about the world, what is telling us about the world?

As for #3, my discussion didn't mention anything about evolution after the measurement, so that's not relevant.

This is again an example of philosophical misunderstandings.

On the contrary, I think it shows that the minimal interpretation is incoherent as it stands. What am I misunderstanding?
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #319
vanhees71 said:
This is again an example of philosophical misunderstandings. The Born rule doesn't single out ineractions between a measurement device and the system with regard to any other interaction. The same fundamental interactions of the Standard Model are at work always. Of course quantum theory as well as classical theory is about what we are able to observe and measure.
Classical theory is about what is really there. With measurements we check that the theory faithfully describes what is there. So measurements are special in classical theory i.e. measurements can falsify the theory.
In QT the Born rule eliminates solipsism from the theory and puts it on the grounds where it can be checked against reality. If you discard Born rule you can't perform scientific test of QT.
And this is how I understand this phrase from stevendaryl's post:
stevendaryl said:
The infinite regress must stop at some point where something simply HAS some value, not "is measured to have some value".
 
  • #320
vanhees71 said:
You mention entropy production yourself, but that indeed makes it necessary to neglect information, i.e., to coarse grain to the relevant macroscopic observables.

Coarse graining does not explain how measurement results in only one outcome from a superposition of several possible outcomes. That's a misunderstanding on your part.
 
  • #321
vanhees71 said:
What you describe further is the collapse hypothesis, which I think is only a very special case which almost always doesn't apply and if so it's a measurement device carefully constructed to enable a (good approximation) of a von Neumann filter measurement. I thus don't say, that the system undergoes a transition to a the state ##|\psi_i \rangle \langle \psi_i|## with probability ##|c_i|^2## but simply that I measure ##o_i## with this probability. It may well be that the system is destroyed by the measurement process (e.g., a photon is absorbed when registered by a photodetector or em. calorimeter).

I went through that already. Yes, that's what you say, and I claim that it is nonsense. That's the infinite regress that I'm talking about. For the microscopic system, it's not that it is ACTUALLY in state with eigenvalue [itex]o_i[/itex], it is only that the measuring device MEASURES it to have eigenvalue [itex]o_i[/itex]. But the meaning of "the measuring device measures [itex]o_i[/itex]" is that makes a transition to some corresponding macroscopic state [itex]S_i[/itex]. Now, you want to say that the device isn't ACTUALLY in state [itex]S_i[/itex], it's just that's I OBSERVE it to be in that state. But since I'm a quantum mechanical system, as well, presumably, I'm not ACTUALLY in the state of "observing the device to be in state [itex]S_i[/itex]", it's that a third person observes me to be observing the device to be in state [itex]S_i[/itex]. Etc.

If measurements are ordinary interactions, then saying that "X observes Y" is a statement about the state of X. X is in the particular state of observing measurement outcome Y. So there is no need to bring in measurements again--it's simply a fact about the system X.
 
  • #322
Demystifier said:
So what's the most rational interpretation of QM in your opinion? Consistent histories? With non-classical logic (see Griffiths)? Changing the rules of logic is the least rational thing to do for my taste.
Consistent histories doesn't change the rules of logic. It specifies rules for how to obtain a single framework. All interpretations need to do this or how do you calculate the probability for ##S_x=1\wedge S_y=-1## in BM? Quantum theory is contextual and no interpretation can deny this fact without changing the predictions of the theory. CH is not really an interpretation of QT. It rather accomplishes the necessary job of telling us, how to obtain probabilities that add up to 1. The interpretational part of CH is to view time evolution as a stochastic process. What you call "changing the rules of logic" is common to all interpretations of QT, even BM. It's just that the CH people first understood, how to deal with it mathematically.

I don't know what's the most rational explanation, but if an interpretation requires a conspiracy of cosmic extent, then practically everything is more rational. The analogy between BM and epicycles is really quite obvious.

stevendaryl said:
Coarse graining does not explain how measurement results in only one outcome from a superposition of several possible outcomes. That's a misunderstanding on your part.
I don't understand why you think that a stochastic theory needs to explain how one outcome is selected. If I have a theory about a classical coin tossing experiment, which specifies the probabilities ##p_{h/t}=\frac{1}{2}##, then "nature is genuinely random and will randomly select one of the possibilities" is a perfectly fine explanation. If that's true, then no further explanation can be possible.
 
  • #324
Demystifier said:
Are you saying that Griffiths
https://arxiv.org/abs/1110.0974
is wrong?
No. The deviation from classical reasoning for quantum phenomena is dictated by experiments. CH explains, how to obtain single frameworks, within which one can resort to classical reasoning and use classical probability theory. No interpretation gets around this. "##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1##" is a completely valid conjunction of propositions according to classical logic, so if you claim that it is a valid statement in BM, you should be able to tell me what probability BM assigns to it.
 
  • #325
rubi said:
The analogy between BM and epicycles is really quite obvious.

It's a poor analogy. Epicycles have been shown to be right. BM remains conjectural.
 
  • Like
Likes rubi
  • #326
atyy said:
It's a poor analogy. Epicycles have been shown to be right. BM remains conjectural.
Well, there are two possibilities:
1. BM makes the same predictions as QM, which is what the Bohmians usually claim. In that case, the analogy is spot on.
2. BM makes different predictions than QM. In that case it either contradicts experiments or the different predictions concern only situations that have not been experimentally tested yet. Then, most physicist would expect the QM predictions to be right and the BM predictions to be wrong. If the QM predictions turned out to be wrong, people would be more likely to just adjust the QM model (e.g. modify the Hamiltonian) than to adopt BM (e.g. see neutrino oscillation).
 
  • #327
rubi said:
No. The deviation from classical reasoning for quantum phenomena is dictated by experiments. CH explains, how to obtain single frameworks, within which one can resort to classical reasoning and use classical probability theory. No interpretation gets around this. "##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1##" is a completely valid conjunction of propositions according to classical logic, so if you claim that it is a valid statement in BM, you should be able to tell me what probability BM assigns to it.
"##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1## (at the same time)" is an invalid statement in BM. It is also an invalid statement in the standard Copenhagen interpretation. And more importantly, there is no experiment which gives ##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1## (at the same time). So how can this be dictated by experiments?
 
  • #328
rubi said:
I don't understand why you think that a stochastic theory needs to explain how one outcome is selected. If I have a theory about a classical coin tossing experiment, which specifies the probabilities ##p_{h/t}=\frac{1}{2}##, then "nature is genuinely random and will randomly select one of the possibilities" is a perfectly fine explanation. If that's true, then no further explanation can be possible.

I think you're arguing something different than vanhees is. I am not arguing against the possibility of a stochastic description of physics.

The point about coarse-graining is that if you could actually do the computations to figure out how the composite wave function for system + measuring device + observer + environment (however far it goes) evolves, then you would find that:

If
  • when the system being measured is in a state corresponding to eigenvalue [itex]o_1[/itex], the measuring device makes a transition to a macroscopic state [itex]S_1[/itex], and
  • when the system being measured is in a state corresponding to eigenvalue [itex]o_2[/itex], the measuring device makes a transition to a macroscopic state [itex]S_2[/itex], then
  • when the system is in a superposition of those two states, then the composite wave function makes a transition to a superposition of those macroscopic states (or mixture, if you like, but I'm using superposition because I'm including the environment in the wave function)
That follows from the linearity of the evolution equations for quantum mechanics. Coarse graining is a mathematical tool for extracting a macroscopic state from a microscopic state. It isn't going to produce a single outcome if the underlying microscopic state reflects a superposition of macroscopically different outcomes.

You can certainly have an additional, stochastic step in which one coarse-grained macroscopic state is selected from the superposition or mixture, but that is an additional step.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #329
stevendaryl said:
Tell me how my story changes if you don't assume collapse. I think that without collapse, then measurements become only subjective, which is basically the Many Worlds idea.

I would distinguish three aspects of the collapse hypothesis:
  1. After measurement, there is no longer observable interference between alternatives.
  2. Measurement reveals a fact about the world (that a certain observable has a certain value).
  3. After measurement, the composite system (system measured plus measuring device plus environment) is in a state consistent with the value measured, and so from then on, evolves from that state, not the original superposition.
Number 1 is not a necessary assumption, because it is presumably derivable from ordinary quantum mechanics, if you take into account decoherence.

So in denying collapse, are you denying 2? Measurements don't actually reveal anything about the world? I can't believe that. How could a result count as a measurement if it doesn't tell us anything about the world? But if it does tell us something about the world, what is telling us about the world?

As for #3, my discussion didn't mention anything about evolution after the measurement, so that's not relevant.
On the contrary, I think it shows that the minimal interpretation is incoherent as it stands. What am I misunderstanding?

After a measurement usually you have a "pointer reading", i.e., a macroscopic observable but you are far from knowing the precise quantum state of the composite system. There's no collapse in the sense of some Copenhagen flavors, because this violates locality and causality implemented in relativstic QFT.
 
  • #330
vanhees71 said:
After a measurement usually you have a "pointer reading", i.e., a macroscopic observable but you are far from knowing the precise quantum state of the composite system.

That's what the macroscopic states [itex]S_i[/itex] are: pointer readings. So are you saying that after the measurement, the device is in one of the states [itex]S_i[/itex] with probability [itex]|c_i|^2[/itex]? How is that not a collapse?
 
  • #331
It's not a collapse in the sense of Copenhagen. It's due to a local interaction between the measured object and the device but not an instantaneous interaction at a distance violating causality!
 
  • #332
Demystifier said:
"##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1## (at the same time)" is an invalid statement in BM. It is also an invalid statement in the standard Copenhagen interpretation. And more importantly, there is no experiment which gives ##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1## (at the same time). So how can this be dictated by experiments?
This is exactly what CH says. It is logically invalid to form the conjunction ##A\wedge B##, if ##A## is ##S_x=+1## and ##B## is ##S_y=-1##, i.e. you cannot apply the rules of classical logic to propositions about quantum systems. BM of course (like every other interpretation) doesn't get around this. The CH rules tell you, which propsitions are logically meaningful and can be combined into a single framework. My example about ##S_x## and ##S_y## is one such meaningless proposition. It's not meaningful in CH, Copenhagen and BM. CH doesn't violate the rules of classical logic more than BM does. In classical logic, you can always form conjunctions like ##A\wedge B##. If you give me two meaningful propositions ##A## and ##B## and I'm not allowed to take their conjunction ##A\wedge B##, then I'm not dealing with classical logic.

stevendaryl said:
I think you're arguing something different than vanhees is. I am not arguing against the possibility of a stochastic description of physics.
Okay, I see.

when the system is in a superposition of those two states, then the composite wave function makes a transition to a superposition of those macroscopic states (or mixture, if you like, but I'm using superposition because I'm including the environment in the wave function)
Maybe in vanhees POV, these superpositions will cancel each other, leaving only one macroscopic possibility (with ##P>\epsilon##). I don't think this is impossible, but one needs a big enough Hilbert space and there will of course always remain some variables (concerning the whole system), which will be completely non-classical.
 
  • #333
vanhees71 said:
It's not a collapse in the sense of Copenhagen. It's due to a local interaction between the measured object and the device but not an instantaneous interaction at a distance violating causality!

This is the point that I have been making: I don't have a philosophical problem with what you're saying; I have a technical problem with it. It's factually incorrect. You seem to be saying that local interactions are sufficient to explain the occurrence of definite results for quantum measurements. That's provably false. Bell proved it to be false.
 
  • #334
rubi said:
This is exactly what CH says. It is logically invalid to form the conjunction ##A\wedge B##, if ##A## is ##S_x=+1## and ##B## is ##S_y=-1##, i.e. you cannot apply the rules of classical logic to propositions about quantum systems. BM of course (like every other interpretation) doesn't get around this. The CH rules tell you, which propsitions are logically meaningful and can be combined into a single framework. My example about ##S_x## and ##S_y## is one such meaningless proposition. It's not meaningful in CH, Copenhagen and BM. CH doesn't violate the rules of classical logic more than BM does. In classical logic, you can always form conjunctions like ##A\wedge B##. If you give me two meaningful propositions ##A## and ##B## and I'm not allowed to take their conjunction ##A\wedge B##, then I'm not dealing with classical logic.
So physical impossibility in other interpretations is promoted to a logical nonsense in CH interpretation. But one could do that even in classical physics. For example, let
A = there are two free massive particles at distance r
B = these two particles are not attracted by a force
Due to gravitational force, it is never the case that both A and B are true. In a CH interpretation of Newtonian mechanics, one would say that ##A\wedge B## is a logical nonsense. But that's not a good approach, because science must be testable. One must consider the statement ##A\wedge B## as a logical possibility, and then make experiments to see whether ##A\wedge B## is true. (The experiments show that it isn't).
 
  • Like
Likes ShayanJ
  • #335
stevendaryl said:
This is the point that I have been making: I don't have a philosophical problem with what you're saying; I have a technical problem with it. It's factually incorrect. You seem to be saying that local interactions are sufficient to explain the occurrence of definite results for quantum measurements. That's provably false. Bell proved it to be false.

Let's go through this for the EPR experiment.

Alice has a device that has two pointer states: [itex]S_u[/itex] and [itex]S_d[/itex]. If an electron that is spin-up along the z-axis interacts with her device, then the device will almost certainly make a transition to having the pointer state [itex]S_u[/itex]. If an electron is spin-down, the device will almost certainly make a transition to having the pointer state [itex]S_d[/itex]. If an electron is in a superposition or mixed state of spin-up and spin-down, then the device will make a nondeterministic transition to either the state [itex]S_u[/itex] or [itex]S_d[/itex] (depending on the coefficients of the superposition or mixture). So far, it seems that everything is perfectly well described by local interactions. But now, we add one more constraint on Alice's device:
  • If, far far away, Bob's device, interacting with the electron's twin, already made the transition to the state pointer state [itex]S_u[/itex], then Alice's device will definitely make the transition to [itex]S_d[/itex]
You can't account for this additional fact with only local interactions.
 
  • Like
Likes ShayanJ and PeterDonis
  • #336
Demystifier said:
So physical impossibility in other interpretations is promoted to a logical nonsense in CH interpretation.
If the problem were only physical impossibility, then the statement ##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1## would be completely unproblematic. We would just assign ##P=0## to it and be happy. However, no possible assignment of probabilities to such a proposition is consistent with QM, so it must be the case that taking this conjunction is an invalid operation. (I know the ##d=2## loophole. Let's stick to ##d=2## for simplicity.) This is all CH says. You must restrict yourself to a single framework if you want to apply classical logic. If your framework includes ##S_x=+1##, then it can't include ##S_y=-1##. Nothing more and nothing less. Bohmians should agree with this.

But one could do that even in classical physics. For example, let
A = there are two free massive particles at distance r
B = these two particles are not attracted by a force
Due to gravitational force, it is never the case that both A and B are true. In a CH interpretation of Newtonian mechanics, one would say that ##A\wedge B## is a logical nonsense.
No, CH has nothing to say about this example. The CH rules apply to propositions that are modeled as projectors in a Hilbert space. The problem with your propositions is that they are self-referential. This is not possible in classical logic either. You are dealing with an unformalized problem in natural language here. Translate it into formalized logic and the problem should vanish.

But that's not a good approach, because science must be testable. One must consider the statement ##A\wedge B## as a logical possibility, and then make experiments to see whether ##A\wedge B## is true. (The experiments show that it isn't).
Whether ##S_x=+1\wedge S_y=-1## is a valid proposition can be tested experimentally and the experiment says that it isn't (again, let's not harp on about the ##d=2## loophole).
 
Last edited:
  • #337
vanhees71 said:
It's not a collapse in the sense of Copenhagen. It's due to a local interaction between the measured object and the device but not an instantaneous interaction at a distance violating causality!

Just so we're clear: You are agreeing that after a measurement, the measurement device has a definite pointer state. Is that correct? If so, I don't understand how that is not a "collapse". Whether or not it is mediated by local interactions, the result is that a single outcome is selected out of a set of possible outcomes. That's what people mean by "collapse".
 
  • #338
stevendaryl said:
Let's go through this for the EPR experiment.

Alice has a device that has two pointer states: [itex]S_u[/itex] and [itex]S_d[/itex]. If an electron that is spin-up along the z-axis interacts with her device, then the device will almost certainly make a transition to having the pointer state [itex]S_u[/itex]. If an electron is spin-down, the device will almost certainly make a transition to having the pointer state [itex]S_d[/itex]. If an electron is in a superposition or mixed state of spin-up and spin-down, then the device will make a nondeterministic transition to either the state [itex]S_u[/itex] or [itex]S_d[/itex] (depending on the coefficients of the superposition or mixture). So far, it seems that everything is perfectly well described by local interactions. But now, we add one more constraint on Alice's device:
  • If, far far away, Bob's device, interacting with the electron's twin, already made the transition to the state pointer state [itex]S_u[/itex], then Alice's device will definitely make the transition to [itex]S_d[/itex]
You can't account for this additional fact with only local interactions.
Yes, we can! The answer is relativistic QFT. The correlations are not due to non-local interactions but due to the preparation in an entangled state at the very beginning, and it's indeed incompatible with local deterministic models a la Bell.
 
  • #339
stevendaryl said:
Whether or not it is mediated by local interactions, the result is that a single outcome is selected out of a set of possible outcomes. That's what people mean by "collapse".

Perhaps it would help to state a concrete example. Suppose we put an electron through a Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction. The spin eigenstates of this measurement are ##\vert z+ \rangle## and ##\vert z- \rangle##. The "pointer variable" here is the direction in which the electron is moving; it starts out moving horizontally, which we will call pointer state ##\vert R \rangle## (for "ready"), and ends up moving either up or down, which we will call pointer states ##\vert U \rangle## and ##\vert D \rangle##.

We know that the Hamiltonian is such that the spin eigenstates will induce evolution as follows:

$$
\vert z+ \rangle \vert R \rangle \rightarrow \vert z+ \rangle \vert U \rangle
$$

$$
\vert z- \rangle \vert R \rangle \rightarrow \vert z- \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

Therefore, a superposition of spin eigenstates ##\vert \psi \rangle = a \vert z+ \rangle + b \vert z- \rangle##, where ##\vert a \vert^2 + \vert b \vert^2 = 1##, will induce evolution as follows:

$$
\vert \psi \rangle \vert R \rangle \rightarrow a \vert z+ \rangle \vert U \rangle + b \vert z- \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

This state does not describe "a single outcome"; it describes a superposition of "outcomes". But this state is what unitary evolution predicts. So if in fact the final state is not the above, but either

$$
\vert z+ \rangle \vert U \rangle
$$

or

$$
\vert z- \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

with probabilities ##\vert a \vert^2## and ##\vert b \vert^2## respectively, then some other process besides unitary evolution must be involved, and this other process is what is referred to by the term "collapse". Decoherence doesn't change this; all decoherence does is ensure that there are no "cross terms" of the form ##\vert z+ \rangle \vert D \rangle## or ##\vert z- \rangle \vert U \rangle## in the superposition.
 
  • Like
Likes MrRobotoToo
  • #340
stevendaryl said:
''
''
  • when the system is in a superposition of those two states, then the composite wave function makes a transition to a superposition of those macroscopic states (or mixture, if you like, but I'm using superposition because I'm including the environment in the wave function)
That follows from the linearity of the evolution equations for quantum mechanics. Coarse graining is a mathematical tool for extracting a macroscopic state from a microscopic state. It isn't going to produce a single outcome if the underlying microscopic state reflects a superposition of macroscopically different outcomes.

You can certainly have an additional, stochastic step in which one coarse-grained macroscopic state is selected from the superposition or mixture, but that is an additional step.
Looking at the third point, "... the composite wave function makes a transition to a superposition of those macroscopic states ... or mixture ... ".

If you mean a statistical mixture then that implies that on every run of the experiment ( ensemble member ) a definite outcome was achieved, and no further step is required. Nor any explanation of how the state was selected. But you probably don't mean that, do you ?
 
  • #341
stevendaryl said:
But in QM, the difference is not simply a matter of what to choose to ignore. Different rules apply to measurements than to other types of interactions.
This may be only a minor point but I don't like the distinction of "ordinary interactions" and "measurement interactions". The Heisenberg cut can be shifted. So whether a specific interaction is of the first or of the second type depends on the person which does the analysis. Measurements are not merely physical.

stevendaryl said:
In what I would consider a coherent formalism, you would describe how the world works, independently of observers, and then add physical-phenomenal axioms saying that such-and-such a condition of such-and-such subsystem counts as a measurement of such-and-such a property. There would be no additional physics to the measurement process, since it would just be an ordinary process.
I agree that this sounds desireable but the chain of logic doesn't reflect how science is done. Our theories are distilled from observations so it isn't a priori clear that we can take the observer out of the picture. Sure, it did work for classical physics but it doesn't for theories with entanglement-like properties.

So given that we have a theory with entanglement, we should ask what a possible alteration of the Born rule could look like in order that we wouldn't consider it ad hoc. If separating the observer from the system changes the system in a non-trivial way, there doesn't seem to be n easy way for this. So for me, the weird thing about QM is that I cannot imagine how a non-weird version of it would look like and I take that as a sign that I don't understand what exactly is weird well enough.
 
  • #342
atyy said:
But why can we ignore part of the universe? Is it because of locality? Why is the universe operationally local, even though reality is nonlocal (or retrocausal etc ...)?
I'm not sure how this relates to what I wrote.

Your starting point seems to be that out of all possible theories, we got one which is demonstrably nonlocal on a fundmental level but at the same time, everything we as humans can think of to exploit this nonlocality is equally demonstrably impossible. How strange! (Please correct me if I'm wrong)

The starting point of my post #281 was us doing experiments. From this point of view, your first question doesn't make sense. We cannot not ignore part of the universe because in order to observe something, we have to exclude at least the part of ourselves which experiences the observation.

(Also, more fundamental theories must include the older ones as limiting cases. So shouldn't you condition your second question on the fact that classical physics is local? But here I see even less connection to my post)
 
  • #343
stevendaryl said:
Let's go through this for the EPR experiment.

Alice has a device that has two pointer states: [itex]S_u[/itex] and [itex]S_d[/itex]. If an electron that is spin-up along the z-axis interacts with her device, then the device will almost certainly make a transition to having the pointer state [itex]S_u[/itex]. If an electron is spin-down, the device will almost certainly make a transition to having the pointer state [itex]S_d[/itex]. If an electron is in a superposition or mixed state of spin-up and spin-down, then the device will make a nondeterministic transition to either the state [itex]S_u[/itex] or [itex]S_d[/itex] (depending on the coefficients of the superposition or mixture). So far, it seems that everything is perfectly well described by local interactions. But now, we add one more constraint on Alice's device:
  • If, far far away, Bob's device, interacting with the electron's twin, already made the transition to the state pointer state [itex]S_u[/itex], then Alice's device will definitely make the transition to [itex]S_d[/itex]
You can't account for this additional fact with only local interactions.

I can't quite follow this,( but I'm trying my best). If the electron were in a superposition of u and d states wouldn't it have needed to have been prepared in a definite state of l or r to be guaranteed to produce a random result in the u/d direction? If the up coefficient were bigger than the down coefficient (so to speak) would it not be expected to migrate one way rather than the other?
 
  • #344
Mentz114 said:
Looking at the third point, "... the composite wave function makes a transition to a superposition of those macroscopic states ... or mixture ... ".

If you mean a statistical mixture then that implies that on every run of the experiment ( ensemble member ) a definite outcome was achieved, and no further step is required. Nor any explanation of how the state was selected. But you probably don't mean that, do you ?

It's a little difficult to discuss without getting into endless levels of details. But the use of mixtures is not limited to the case in which a system has a definite (though unknown) state. You also get a mixture by taking a composite system and "tracing out" unobservable degrees of freedom.

This is what makes the discussion a little complicated. On the one hand, people say that realistically, you shouldn't use pure states to describe macroscopic objects, you should use mixtures. But the use of mixtures already blurs the distinction between probabilities that are inherent in the quantum formalism and probabilities that are due to lack of knowledge. Some people say that there is no distinction, but that seems wrong to me. To say that an electron is in a superposition of spin-up and spin-down is not to say that it is one state or the other, I just don't know which.
 
  • #345
PeterDonis said:
Therefore, a superposition of spin eigenstates ##\vert \psi \rangle = a \vert z+ \rangle + b \vert z- \rangle##, where ##\vert a \vert^2 + \vert b \vert^2 = 1##, will induce evolution as follows:

$$
\vert \psi \rangle \vert R \rangle \rightarrow a \vert z+ \rangle \vert U \rangle + b \vert z- \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

This state does not describe "a single outcome"; it describes a superposition of "outcomes". But this state is what unitary evolution predicts. So if in fact the final state is not the above, but either

$$
\vert z+ \rangle \vert U \rangle
$$

or

$$
\vert z- \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

with probabilities ##\vert a \vert^2## and ##\vert b \vert^2## respectively, then some other process besides unitary evolution must be involved, and this other process is what is referred to by the term "collapse". Decoherence doesn't change this; all decoherence does is ensure that there are no "cross terms" of the form ##\vert z+ \rangle \vert D \rangle## or ##\vert z- \rangle \vert U \rangle## in the superposition.

Unless I'm misunderstanding you, you seem to be agreeing with me. Decoherence, or irreversibility is not going to result in a definite outcome.

So if someone says that a measurement results in either the state [itex]|U\rangle[/itex], with such-and-such probability, or the state [itex]|D\rangle[/itex], with such and such a probability, then does that imply that something nonunitary is involved?
 
  • #346
vanhees71 said:
Yes, we can! The answer is relativistic QFT.

This is a misconception on your part. There are two parts to QFT, just as there are two parts to nonrelativistic quantum mechanics: (1) evolution of the quantum state, and (2) the Born rule.

QFT affects the first part, but not the second. We're only talking about the second.
 
  • #347
stevendaryl said:
you seem to be agreeing with me.

Yes, I am. But I'm trying to state your point using a concrete example in the hope that it will help to make it clearer to others.

stevendaryl said:
So if someone says that a measurement results in either the state ##|U\rangle##, with such-and-such probability, or the state ##|D\rangle##, with such and such a probability, then does that imply that something nonunitary is involved?

To me it obviously must, since unitary evolution gives the superposition. So a no collapse interpretation, like MWI, would say that the measurement results in the superposition--i.e., "measurement" is not a non-unitary collapse but simply a unitary entanglement interaction between the measured system and the "pointer" system (the one whose state becomes entangled with the measured system's state). In the Stern-Gerlach case, the measured system is the electron's spin and the pointer system is the electron's momentum.
 
  • #348
vanhees71 said:
Yes, we can! The answer is relativistic QFT. The correlations are not due to non-local interactions but due to the preparation in an entangled state at the very beginning, and it's indeed incompatible with local deterministic models a la Bell.

No, relativistic QFT is not the answer. Look, if you described everything in EPR---the twin pair, the detectors, Bob, Alice, the environment, etc.---using QFT, what you would NOT find is that smooth unitary evolution would result in Alice's detector having a definite pointer state. What you would find is that the composite wave function of everything relevant would evolve into a superposition of different worlds with different pointer states. It doesn't matter whether you describe the detectors using QFT or nonrelativistic quantum mechanics. The evolution equations are not stochastic, they are deterministic.

So if Alice's detector ends up in a definite pointer state, that is NOT described by QFT's unitary evolution.
 
  • #349
kith said:
This may be only a minor point but I don't like the distinction of "ordinary interactions" and "measurement interactions". The Heisenberg cut can be shifted. So whether a specific interaction is of the first or of the second type depends on the person which does the analysis. Measurements are not merely physical.

Okay, that's a possible answer, which is that there is nothing objective about measurement results--for one person, an object might be in a definite state, while for another person, the same object might be in a superposition.

So given that we have a theory with entanglement, we should ask what a possible alteration of the Born rule could look like in order that we wouldn't consider it ad hoc. If separating the observer from the system changes the system in a non-trivial way, there doesn't seem to be n easy way for this. So for me, the weird thing about QM is that I cannot imagine how a non-weird version of it would look like and I take that as a sign that I don't understand what exactly is weird well enough.

Fair enough. I'm not sure what a nonweird version of QM would be like, either.
 
  • #350
stevendaryl said:
It's a little difficult to discuss without getting into endless levels of details. But the use of mixtures is not limited to the case in which a system has a definite (though unknown) state. You also get a mixture by taking a composite system and "tracing out" unobservable degrees of freedom.

This is what makes the discussion a little complicated. On the one hand, people say that realistically, you shouldn't use pure states to describe macroscopic objects, you should use mixtures. But the use of mixtures already blurs the distinction between probabilities that are inherent in the quantum formalism and probabilities that are due to lack of knowledge. Some people say that there is no distinction, but that seems wrong to me. To say that an electron is in a superposition of spin-up and spin-down is not to say that it is one state or the other, I just don't know which.
As far as I understand this I can't see anything to disagree with. The point I've emphasized is worth exploring further, so I'll do that for a bit.
 

Similar threads

Replies
109
Views
9K
Replies
159
Views
11K
Replies
235
Views
21K
Replies
491
Views
30K
Replies
13
Views
2K
Back
Top